You can not select more than 25 topics Topics must start with a letter or number, can include dashes ('-') and can be up to 35 characters long.

20611 lines
1.2 MiB

  1. PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781
  2. Human reason, in one sphere of its cognition, is called upon to consider
  3. questions, which it cannot decline, as they are presented by its own
  4. nature, but which it cannot answer, as they transcend every faculty of
  5. the mind.
  6. It falls into this difficulty without any fault of its own. It begins
  7. with principles, which cannot be dispensed with in the field of
  8. experience, and the truth and sufficiency of which are, at the same
  9. time, insured by experience. With these principles it rises, in
  10. obedience to the laws of its own nature, to ever higher and more remote
  11. conditions. But it quickly discovers that, in this way, its labours must
  12. remain ever incomplete, because new questions never cease to present
  13. themselves; and thus it finds itself compelled to have recourse to
  14. principles which transcend the region of experience, while they are
  15. regarded by common sense without distrust. It thus falls into confusion
  16. and contradictions, from which it conjectures the presence of latent
  17. errors, which, however, it is unable to discover, because the principles
  18. it employs, transcending the limits of experience, cannot be tested
  19. by that criterion. The arena of these endless contests is called
  20. Metaphysic.
  21. Time was, when she was the queen of all the sciences; and, if we take
  22. the will for the deed, she certainly deserves, so far as regards the
  23. high importance of her object-matter, this title of honour. Now, it is
  24. the fashion of the time to heap contempt and scorn upon her; and the
  25. matron mourns, forlorn and forsaken, like Hecuba:
  26. Modo maxima rerum,
  27. Tot generis, natisque potens...
  28. Nunc trahor exul, inops.
  29. --Ovid, Metamorphoses. xiii
  30. At first, her government, under the administration of the dogmatists,
  31. was an absolute despotism. But, as the legislative continued to show
  32. traces of the ancient barbaric rule, her empire gradually broke up, and
  33. intestine wars introduced the reign of anarchy; while the sceptics,
  34. like nomadic tribes, who hate a permanent habitation and settled mode
  35. of living, attacked from time to time those who had organized themselves
  36. into civil communities. But their number was, very happily, small; and
  37. thus they could not entirely put a stop to the exertions of those who
  38. persisted in raising new edifices, although on no settled or uniform
  39. plan. In recent times the hope dawned upon us of seeing those disputes
  40. settled, and the legitimacy of her claims established by a kind of
  41. physiology of the human understanding--that of the celebrated Locke. But
  42. it was found that--although it was affirmed that this so-called queen
  43. could not refer her descent to any higher source than that of common
  44. experience, a circumstance which necessarily brought suspicion on
  45. her claims--as this genealogy was incorrect, she persisted in the
  46. advancement of her claims to sovereignty. Thus metaphysics necessarily
  47. fell back into the antiquated and rotten constitution of dogmatism, and
  48. again became obnoxious to the contempt from which efforts had been
  49. made to save it. At present, as all methods, according to the general
  50. persuasion, have been tried in vain, there reigns nought but weariness
  51. and complete indifferentism--the mother of chaos and night in the
  52. scientific world, but at the same time the source of, or at least the
  53. prelude to, the re-creation and reinstallation of a science, when it has
  54. fallen into confusion, obscurity, and disuse from ill directed effort.
  55. For it is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to such
  56. inquiries, the object of which cannot be indifferent to humanity.
  57. Besides, these pretended indifferentists, however much they may try to
  58. disguise themselves by the assumption of a popular style and by changes
  59. on the language of the schools, unavoidably fall into metaphysical
  60. declarations and propositions, which they profess to regard with so much
  61. contempt. At the same time, this indifference, which has arisen in the
  62. world of science, and which relates to that kind of knowledge which
  63. we should wish to see destroyed the last, is a phenomenon that well
  64. deserves our attention and reflection. It is plainly not the effect of
  65. the levity, but of the matured judgement* of the age, which refuses to
  66. be any longer entertained with illusory knowledge, It is, in fact, a
  67. call to reason, again to undertake the most laborious of all tasks--that
  68. of self-examination, and to establish a tribunal, which may secure it
  69. in its well-grounded claims, while it pronounces against all baseless
  70. assumptions and pretensions, not in an arbitrary manner, but according
  71. to its own eternal and unchangeable laws. This tribunal is nothing less
  72. than the critical investigation of pure reason.
  73. [*Footnote: We very often hear complaints of the shallowness of the
  74. present age, and of the decay of profound science. But I do not think
  75. that those which rest upon a secure foundation, such as mathematics,
  76. physical science, etc., in the least deserve this reproach, but that
  77. they rather maintain their ancient fame, and in the latter case, indeed,
  78. far surpass it. The same would be the case with the other kinds of
  79. cognition, if their principles were but firmly established. In the
  80. absence of this security, indifference, doubt, and finally, severe
  81. criticism are rather signs of a profound habit of thought. Our age
  82. is the age of criticism, to which everything must be subjected. The
  83. sacredness of religion, and the authority of legislation, are by many
  84. regarded as grounds of exemption from the examination of this tribunal.
  85. But, if they on they are exempted, they become the subjects of just
  86. suspicion, and cannot lay claim to sincere respect, which reason accords
  87. only to that which has stood the test of a free and public examination.]
  88. I do not mean by this a criticism of books and systems, but a critical
  89. inquiry into the faculty of reason, with reference to the cognitions
  90. to which it strives to attain without the aid of experience; in other
  91. words, the solution of the question regarding the possibility or
  92. impossibility of metaphysics, and the determination of the origin, as
  93. well as of the extent and limits of this science. All this must be done
  94. on the basis of principles.
  95. This path--the only one now remaining--has been entered upon by me; and
  96. I flatter myself that I have, in this way, discovered the cause of--and
  97. consequently the mode of removing--all the errors which have hitherto
  98. set reason at variance with itself, in the sphere of non-empirical
  99. thought. I have not returned an evasive answer to the questions of
  100. reason, by alleging the inability and limitation of the faculties of the
  101. mind; I have, on the contrary, examined them completely in the light
  102. of principles, and, after having discovered the cause of the doubts and
  103. contradictions into which reason fell, have solved them to its perfect
  104. satisfaction. It is true, these questions have not been solved as
  105. dogmatism, in its vain fancies and desires, had expected; for it can
  106. only be satisfied by the exercise of magical arts, and of these I have
  107. no knowledge. But neither do these come within the compass of our mental
  108. powers; and it was the duty of philosophy to destroy the illusions which
  109. had their origin in misconceptions, whatever darling hopes and valued
  110. expectations may be ruined by its explanations. My chief aim in this
  111. work has been thoroughness; and I make bold to say that there is not a
  112. single metaphysical problem that does not find its solution, or at
  113. least the key to its solution, here. Pure reason is a perfect unity; and
  114. therefore, if the principle presented by it prove to be insufficient for
  115. the solution of even a single one of those questions to which the very
  116. nature of reason gives birth, we must reject it, as we could not be
  117. perfectly certain of its sufficiency in the case of the others.
  118. While I say this, I think I see upon the countenance of the reader signs
  119. of dissatisfaction mingled with contempt, when he hears declarations
  120. which sound so boastful and extravagant; and yet they are beyond
  121. comparison more moderate than those advanced by the commonest author of
  122. the commonest philosophical programme, in which the dogmatist professes
  123. to demonstrate the simple nature of the soul, or the necessity of a
  124. primal being. Such a dogmatist promises to extend human knowledge beyond
  125. the limits of possible experience; while I humbly confess that this
  126. is completely beyond my power. Instead of any such attempt, I confine
  127. myself to the examination of reason alone and its pure thought; and I do
  128. not need to seek far for the sum-total of its cognition, because it
  129. has its seat in my own mind. Besides, common logic presents me with
  130. a complete and systematic catalogue of all the simple operations of
  131. reason; and it is my task to answer the question how far reason can go,
  132. without the material presented and the aid furnished by experience.
  133. So much for the completeness and thoroughness necessary in the execution
  134. of the present task. The aims set before us are not arbitrarily
  135. proposed, but are imposed upon us by the nature of cognition itself.
  136. The above remarks relate to the matter of our critical inquiry. As
  137. regards the form, there are two indispensable conditions, which any one
  138. who undertakes so difficult a task as that of a critique of pure reason,
  139. is bound to fulfil. These conditions are certitude and clearness.
  140. As regards certitude, I have fully convinced myself that, in this sphere
  141. of thought, opinion is perfectly inadmissible, and that everything which
  142. bears the least semblance of an hypothesis must be excluded, as of no
  143. value in such discussions. For it is a necessary condition of every
  144. cognition that is to be established upon a priori grounds that it shall
  145. be held to be absolutely necessary; much more is this the case with an
  146. attempt to determine all pure a priori cognition, and to furnish the
  147. standard--and consequently an example--of all apodeictic (philosophical)
  148. certitude. Whether I have succeeded in what I professed to do, it is for
  149. the reader to determine; it is the author's business merely to adduce
  150. grounds and reasons, without determining what influence these ought to
  151. have on the mind of his judges. But, lest anything he may have said may
  152. become the innocent cause of doubt in their minds, or tend to weaken the
  153. effect which his arguments might otherwise produce--he may be allowed
  154. to point out those passages which may occasion mistrust or difficulty,
  155. although these do not concern the main purpose of the present work. He
  156. does this solely with the view of removing from the mind of the reader
  157. any doubts which might affect his judgement of the work as a whole, and
  158. in regard to its ultimate aim.
  159. I know no investigations more necessary for a full insight into the
  160. nature of the faculty which we call understanding, and at the same time
  161. for the determination of the rules and limits of its use, than those
  162. undertaken in the second chapter of the "Transcendental Analytic," under
  163. the title of "Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding";
  164. and they have also cost me by far the greatest labour--labour which, I
  165. hope, will not remain uncompensated. The view there taken, which goes
  166. somewhat deeply into the subject, has two sides, The one relates to the
  167. objects of the pure understanding, and is intended to demonstrate and
  168. to render comprehensible the objective validity of its a priori
  169. conceptions; and it forms for this reason an essential part of the
  170. Critique. The other considers the pure understanding itself, its
  171. possibility and its powers of cognition--that is, from a subjective
  172. point of view; and, although this exposition is of great importance, it
  173. does not belong essentially to the main purpose of the work, because the
  174. grand question is what and how much can reason and understanding, apart
  175. from experience, cognize, and not, how is the faculty of thought itself
  176. possible? As the latter is an inquiry into the cause of a given effect,
  177. and has thus in it some semblance of an hypothesis (although, as I shall
  178. show on another occasion, this is really not the fact), it would seem
  179. that, in the present instance, I had allowed myself to enounce a mere
  180. opinion, and that the reader must therefore be at liberty to hold
  181. a different opinion. But I beg to remind him that, if my subjective
  182. deduction does not produce in his mind the conviction of its certitude
  183. at which I aimed, the objective deduction, with which alone the present
  184. work is properly concerned, is in every respect satisfactory.
  185. As regards clearness, the reader has a right to demand, in the first
  186. place, discursive or logical clearness, that is, on the basis of
  187. conceptions, and, secondly, intuitive or aesthetic clearness, by means
  188. of intuitions, that is, by examples or other modes of illustration
  189. in concreto. I have done what I could for the first kind of
  190. intelligibility. This was essential to my purpose; and it thus became
  191. the accidental cause of my inability to do complete justice to the
  192. second requirement. I have been almost always at a loss, during the
  193. progress of this work, how to settle this question. Examples and
  194. illustrations always appeared to me necessary, and, in the first sketch
  195. of the Critique, naturally fell into their proper places. But I very
  196. soon became aware of the magnitude of my task, and the numerous problems
  197. with which I should be engaged; and, as I perceived that this critical
  198. investigation would, even if delivered in the driest scholastic manner,
  199. be far from being brief, I found it unadvisable to enlarge it still more
  200. with examples and explanations, which are necessary only from a popular
  201. point of view. I was induced to take this course from the consideration
  202. also that the present work is not intended for popular use, that those
  203. devoted to science do not require such helps, although they are always
  204. acceptable, and that they would have materially interfered with my
  205. present purpose. Abbe Terrasson remarks with great justice that, if we
  206. estimate the size of a work, not from the number of its pages, but from
  207. the time which we require to make ourselves master of it, it may be said
  208. of many a book that it would be much shorter, if it were not so short.
  209. On the other hand, as regards the comprehensibility of a system of
  210. speculative cognition, connected under a single principle, we may say
  211. with equal justice: many a book would have been much clearer, if it had
  212. not been intended to be so very clear. For explanations and examples,
  213. and other helps to intelligibility, aid us in the comprehension of
  214. parts, but they distract the attention, dissipate the mental power of
  215. the reader, and stand in the way of his forming a clear conception of
  216. the whole; as he cannot attain soon enough to a survey of the system,
  217. and the colouring and embellishments bestowed upon it prevent his
  218. observing its articulation or organization--which is the most important
  219. consideration with him, when he comes to judge of its unity and
  220. stability.
  221. The reader must naturally have a strong inducement to co-operate
  222. with the present author, if he has formed the intention of erecting a
  223. complete and solid edifice of metaphysical science, according to the
  224. plan now laid before him. Metaphysics, as here represented, is the only
  225. science which admits of completion--and with little labour, if it
  226. is united, in a short time; so that nothing will be left to
  227. future generations except the task of illustrating and applying it
  228. didactically. For this science is nothing more than the inventory of all
  229. that is given us by pure reason, systematically arranged. Nothing can
  230. escape our notice; for what reason produces from itself cannot lie
  231. concealed, but must be brought to the light by reason itself, so soon
  232. as we have discovered the common principle of the ideas we seek. The
  233. perfect unity of this kind of cognitions, which are based upon pure
  234. conceptions, and uninfluenced by any empirical element, or any peculiar
  235. intuition leading to determinate experience, renders this completeness
  236. not only practicable, but also necessary.
  237. Tecum habita, et noris quam sit tibi curta supellex.
  238. --Persius. Satirae iv. 52.
  239. Such a system of pure speculative reason I hope to be able to publish
  240. under the title of Metaphysic of Nature*. The content of this work
  241. (which will not be half so long) will be very much richer than that
  242. of the present Critique, which has to discover the sources of this
  243. cognition and expose the conditions of its possibility, and at the same
  244. time to clear and level a fit foundation for the scientific edifice. In
  245. the present work, I look for the patient hearing and the impartiality
  246. of a judge; in the other, for the good-will and assistance of a
  247. co-labourer. For, however complete the list of principles for this
  248. system may be in the Critique, the correctness of the system requires
  249. that no deduced conceptions should be absent. These cannot be presented
  250. a priori, but must be gradually discovered; and, while the synthesis of
  251. conceptions has been fully exhausted in the Critique, it is necessary
  252. that, in the proposed work, the same should be the case with their
  253. analysis. But this will be rather an amusement than a labour.
  254. [*Footnote: In contradistinction to the Metaphysic of
  255. Ethics. This work was never published.]
  256. PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787
  257. Whether the treatment of that portion of our knowledge which lies within
  258. the province of pure reason advances with that undeviating certainty
  259. which characterizes the progress of science, we shall be at no loss to
  260. determine. If we find those who are engaged in metaphysical pursuits,
  261. unable to come to an understanding as to the method which they ought
  262. to follow; if we find them, after the most elaborate preparations,
  263. invariably brought to a stand before the goal is reached, and compelled
  264. to retrace their steps and strike into fresh paths, we may then feel
  265. quite sure that they are far from having attained to the certainty of
  266. scientific progress and may rather be said to be merely groping about in
  267. the dark. In these circumstances we shall render an important service to
  268. reason if we succeed in simply indicating the path along which it must
  269. travel, in order to arrive at any results--even if it should be found
  270. necessary to abandon many of those aims which, without reflection, have
  271. been proposed for its attainment.
  272. That logic has advanced in this sure course, even from the earliest
  273. times, is apparent from the fact that, since Aristotle, it has been
  274. unable to advance a step and, thus, to all appearance has reached its
  275. completion. For, if some of the moderns have thought to enlarge its
  276. domain by introducing psychological discussions on the mental faculties,
  277. such as imagination and wit, metaphysical, discussions on the origin
  278. of knowledge and the different kinds of certitude, according to
  279. the difference of the objects (idealism, scepticism, and so on), or
  280. anthropological discussions on prejudices, their causes and remedies:
  281. this attempt, on the part of these authors, only shows their ignorance
  282. of the peculiar nature of logical science. We do not enlarge but
  283. disfigure the sciences when we lose sight of their respective limits and
  284. allow them to run into one another. Now logic is enclosed within limits
  285. which admit of perfectly clear definition; it is a science which has for
  286. its object nothing but the exposition and proof of the formal laws of
  287. all thought, whether it be a priori or empirical, whatever be its
  288. origin or its object, and whatever the difficulties--natural or
  289. accidental--which it encounters in the human mind.
  290. The early success of logic must be attributed exclusively to the
  291. narrowness of its field, in which abstraction may, or rather must,
  292. be made of all the objects of cognition with their characteristic
  293. distinctions, and in which the understanding has only to deal with
  294. itself and with its own forms. It is, obviously, a much more difficult
  295. task for reason to strike into the sure path of science, where it has to
  296. deal not simply with itself, but with objects external to itself. Hence,
  297. logic is properly only a propaedeutic--forms, as it were, the vestibule
  298. of the sciences; and while it is necessary to enable us to form a
  299. correct judgement with regard to the various branches of knowledge,
  300. still the acquisition of real, substantive knowledge is to be sought
  301. only in the sciences properly so called, that is, in the objective
  302. sciences.
  303. Now these sciences, if they can be termed rational at all, must contain
  304. elements of a priori cognition, and this cognition may stand in a
  305. twofold relation to its object. Either it may have to determine the
  306. conception of the object--which must be supplied extraneously, or it
  307. may have to establish its reality. The former is theoretical, the latter
  308. practical, rational cognition. In both, the pure or a priori element
  309. must be treated first, and must be carefully distinguished from that
  310. which is supplied from other sources. Any other method can only lead to
  311. irremediable confusion.
  312. Mathematics and physics are the two theoretical sciences which have to
  313. determine their objects a priori. The former is purely a priori, the
  314. latter is partially so, but is also dependent on other sources of
  315. cognition.
  316. In the earliest times of which history affords us any record,
  317. mathematics had already entered on the sure course of science, among
  318. that wonderful nation, the Greeks. Still it is not to be supposed that
  319. it was as easy for this science to strike into, or rather to construct
  320. for itself, that royal road, as it was for logic, in which reason has
  321. only to deal with itself. On the contrary, I believe that it must
  322. have remained long--chiefly among the Egyptians--in the stage of
  323. blind groping after its true aims and destination, and that it was
  324. revolutionized by the happy idea of one man, who struck out and
  325. determined for all time the path which this science must follow,
  326. and which admits of an indefinite advancement. The history of this
  327. intellectual revolution--much more important in its results than the
  328. discovery of the passage round the celebrated Cape of Good Hope--and of
  329. its author, has not been preserved. But Diogenes Laertius, in naming
  330. the supposed discoverer of some of the simplest elements of geometrical
  331. demonstration--elements which, according to the ordinary opinion, do not
  332. even require to be proved--makes it apparent that the change introduced
  333. by the first indication of this new path, must have seemed of the utmost
  334. importance to the mathematicians of that age, and it has thus been
  335. secured against the chance of oblivion. A new light must have flashed on
  336. the mind of the first man (Thales, or whatever may have been his name)
  337. who demonstrated the properties of the isosceles triangle. For he found
  338. that it was not sufficient to meditate on the figure, as it lay before
  339. his eyes, or the conception of it, as it existed in his mind, and thus
  340. endeavour to get at the knowledge of its properties, but that it was
  341. necessary to produce these properties, as it were, by a positive a
  342. priori construction; and that, in order to arrive with certainty at
  343. a priori cognition, he must not attribute to the object any other
  344. properties than those which necessarily followed from that which he had
  345. himself, in accordance with his conception, placed in the object.
  346. A much longer period elapsed before physics entered on the highway of
  347. science. For it is only about a century and a half since the wise Bacon
  348. gave a new direction to physical studies, or rather--as others were
  349. already on the right track--imparted fresh vigour to the pursuit of
  350. this new direction. Here, too, as in the case of mathematics, we find
  351. evidence of a rapid intellectual revolution. In the remarks which follow
  352. I shall confine myself to the empirical side of natural science.
  353. When Galilei experimented with balls of a definite weight on the
  354. inclined plane, when Torricelli caused the air to sustain a weight which
  355. he had calculated beforehand to be equal to that of a definite column of
  356. water, or when Stahl, at a later period, converted metals into lime, and
  357. reconverted lime into metal, by the addition and subtraction of certain
  358. elements; [Footnote: I do not here follow with exactness the history of
  359. the experimental method, of which, indeed, the first steps are involved
  360. in some obscurity.] a light broke upon all natural philosophers. They
  361. learned that reason only perceives that which it produces after its
  362. own design; that it must not be content to follow, as it were, in the
  363. leading-strings of nature, but must proceed in advance with principles
  364. of judgement according to unvarying laws, and compel nature to reply
  365. its questions. For accidental observations, made according to no
  366. preconceived plan, cannot be united under a necessary law. But it is
  367. this that reason seeks for and requires. It is only the principles of
  368. reason which can give to concordant phenomena the validity of laws, and
  369. it is only when experiment is directed by these rational principles that
  370. it can have any real utility. Reason must approach nature with the view,
  371. indeed, of receiving information from it, not, however, in the character
  372. of a pupil, who listens to all that his master chooses to tell him,
  373. but in that of a judge, who compels the witnesses to reply to those
  374. questions which he himself thinks fit to propose. To this single idea
  375. must the revolution be ascribed, by which, after groping in the dark for
  376. so many centuries, natural science was at length conducted into the path
  377. of certain progress.
  378. We come now to metaphysics, a purely speculative science, which occupies
  379. a completely isolated position and is entirely independent of the
  380. teachings of experience. It deals with mere conceptions--not, like
  381. mathematics, with conceptions applied to intuition--and in it, reason is
  382. the pupil of itself alone. It is the oldest of the sciences, and would
  383. still survive, even if all the rest were swallowed up in the abyss of
  384. an all-destroying barbarism. But it has not yet had the good fortune to
  385. attain to the sure scientific method. This will be apparent; if we
  386. apply the tests which we proposed at the outset. We find that reason
  387. perpetually comes to a stand, when it attempts to gain a priori the
  388. perception even of those laws which the most common experience confirms.
  389. We find it compelled to retrace its steps in innumerable instances, and
  390. to abandon the path on which it had entered, because this does not
  391. lead to the desired result. We find, too, that those who are engaged in
  392. metaphysical pursuits are far from being able to agree among themselves,
  393. but that, on the contrary, this science appears to furnish an arena
  394. specially adapted for the display of skill or the exercise of strength
  395. in mock-contests--a field in which no combatant ever yet succeeded in
  396. gaining an inch of ground, in which, at least, no victory was ever yet
  397. crowned with permanent possession.
  398. This leads us to inquire why it is that, in metaphysics, the sure path
  399. of science has not hitherto been found. Shall we suppose that it is
  400. impossible to discover it? Why then should nature have visited our
  401. reason with restless aspirations after it, as if it were one of our
  402. weightiest concerns? Nay, more, how little cause should we have to place
  403. confidence in our reason, if it abandons us in a matter about which,
  404. most of all, we desire to know the truth--and not only so, but even
  405. allures us to the pursuit of vain phantoms, only to betray us in the
  406. end? Or, if the path has only hitherto been missed, what indications do
  407. we possess to guide us in a renewed investigation, and to enable us to
  408. hope for greater success than has fallen to the lot of our predecessors?
  409. It appears to me that the examples of mathematics and natural
  410. philosophy, which, as we have seen, were brought into their present
  411. condition by a sudden revolution, are sufficiently remarkable to fix our
  412. attention on the essential circumstances of the change which has proved
  413. so advantageous to them, and to induce us to make the experiment of
  414. imitating them, so far as the analogy which, as rational sciences, they
  415. bear to metaphysics may permit. It has hitherto been assumed that our
  416. cognition must conform to the objects; but all attempts to ascertain
  417. anything about these objects a priori, by means of conceptions, and thus
  418. to extend the range of our knowledge, have been rendered abortive by
  419. this assumption. Let us then make the experiment whether we may not
  420. be more successful in metaphysics, if we assume that the objects must
  421. conform to our cognition. This appears, at all events, to accord better
  422. with the possibility of our gaining the end we have in view, that is to
  423. say, of arriving at the cognition of objects a priori, of determining
  424. something with respect to these objects, before they are given to us. We
  425. here propose to do just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain
  426. the celestial movements. When he found that he could make no progress by
  427. assuming that all the heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator,
  428. he reversed the process, and tried the experiment of assuming that the
  429. spectator revolved, while the stars remained at rest. We may make
  430. the same experiment with regard to the intuition of objects. If the
  431. intuition must conform to the nature of the objects, I do not see how
  432. we can know anything of them a priori. If, on the other hand, the object
  433. conforms to the nature of our faculty of intuition, I can then easily
  434. conceive the possibility of such an a priori knowledge. Now as I cannot
  435. rest in the mere intuitions, but--if they are to become cognitions--must
  436. refer them, as representations, to something, as object, and must
  437. determine the latter by means of the former, here again there are two
  438. courses open to me. Either, first, I may assume that the conceptions,
  439. by which I effect this determination, conform to the object--and in this
  440. case I am reduced to the same perplexity as before; or secondly, I may
  441. assume that the objects, or, which is the same thing, that experience,
  442. in which alone as given objects they are cognized, conform to my
  443. conceptions--and then I am at no loss how to proceed. For experience
  444. itself is a mode of cognition which requires understanding. Before
  445. objects, are given to me, that is, a priori, I must presuppose in myself
  446. laws of the understanding which are expressed in conceptions a
  447. priori. To these conceptions, then, all the objects of experience must
  448. necessarily conform. Now there are objects which reason thinks, and
  449. that necessarily, but which cannot be given in experience, or, at least,
  450. cannot be given so as reason thinks them. The attempt to think these
  451. objects will hereafter furnish an excellent test of the new method of
  452. thought which we have adopted, and which is based on the principle that
  453. we only cognize in things a priori that which we ourselves place in
  454. them.*
  455. [*Footnote: This method, accordingly, which we have borrowed
  456. from the natural philosopher, consists in seeking for the
  457. elements of pure reason in that which admits of confirmation
  458. or refutation by experiment. Now the propositions of pure
  459. reason, especially when they transcend the limits of
  460. possible experience, do not admit of our making any
  461. experiment with their objects, as in natural science. Hence,
  462. with regard to those conceptions and principles which we
  463. assume a priori, our only course ill be to view them from
  464. two different sides. We must regard one and the same
  465. conception, on the one hand, in relation to experience as an
  466. object of the senses and of the understanding, on the other
  467. hand, in relation to reason, isolated and transcending the
  468. limits of experience, as an object of mere thought. Now if
  469. we find that, when we regard things from this double point
  470. of view, the result is in harmony with the principle of pure
  471. reason, but that, when we regard them from a single point of
  472. view, reason is involved in self-contradiction, then the
  473. experiment will establish the correctness of this
  474. distinction.]
  475. This attempt succeeds as well as we could desire, and promises to
  476. metaphysics, in its first part--that is, where it is occupied with
  477. conceptions a priori, of which the corresponding objects may be given in
  478. experience--the certain course of science. For by this new method we are
  479. enabled perfectly to explain the possibility of a priori cognition, and,
  480. what is more, to demonstrate satisfactorily the laws which lie a
  481. priori at the foundation of nature, as the sum of the objects of
  482. experience--neither of which was possible according to the procedure
  483. hitherto followed. But from this deduction of the faculty of a priori
  484. cognition in the first part of metaphysics, we derive a surprising
  485. result, and one which, to all appearance, militates against the great
  486. end of metaphysics, as treated in the second part. For we come to the
  487. conclusion that our faculty of cognition is unable to transcend the
  488. limits of possible experience; and yet this is precisely the most
  489. essential object of this science. The estimate of our rational cognition
  490. a priori at which we arrive is that it has only to do with phenomena,
  491. and that things in themselves, while possessing a real existence,
  492. lie beyond its sphere. Here we are enabled to put the justice of this
  493. estimate to the test. For that which of necessity impels us to transcend
  494. the limits of experience and of all phenomena is the unconditioned,
  495. which reason absolutely requires in things as they are in themselves,
  496. in order to complete the series of conditions. Now, if it appears that
  497. when, on the one hand, we assume that our cognition conforms to its
  498. objects as things in themselves, the unconditioned cannot be thought
  499. without contradiction, and that when, on the other hand, we assume that
  500. our representation of things as they are given to us, does not conform
  501. to these things as they are in themselves, but that these objects, as
  502. phenomena, conform to our mode of representation, the contradiction
  503. disappears: we shall then be convinced of the truth of that which we
  504. began by assuming for the sake of experiment; we may look upon it as
  505. established that the unconditioned does not lie in things as we
  506. know them, or as they are given to us, but in things as they are in
  507. themselves, beyond the range of our cognition.*
  508. [*Footnote: This experiment of pure reason has a great
  509. similarity to that of the chemists, which they term the
  510. experiment of reduction, or, more usually, the synthetic
  511. process. The analysis of the metaphysician separates pure
  512. cognition a priori into two heterogeneous elements, viz.,
  513. the cognition of things as phenomena, and of things in
  514. themselves. Dialectic combines these again into harmony with
  515. the necessary rational idea of the unconditioned, and finds
  516. that this harmony never results except through the above
  517. distinction, which is, therefore, concluded to be just.]
  518. But, after we have thus denied the power of speculative reason to make
  519. any progress in the sphere of the supersensible, it still remains for
  520. our consideration whether data do not exist in practical cognition
  521. which may enable us to determine the transcendent conception of the
  522. unconditioned, to rise beyond the limits of all possible experience
  523. from a practical point of view, and thus to satisfy the great ends of
  524. metaphysics. Speculative reason has thus, at least, made room for such
  525. an extension of our knowledge: and, if it must leave this space vacant,
  526. still it does not rob us of the liberty to fill it up, if we can,
  527. by means of practical data--nay, it even challenges us to make the
  528. attempt.*
  529. [*Footnote: So the central laws of the movements of the
  530. heavenly bodies established the truth of that which
  531. Copernicus, first, assumed only as a hypothesis, and, at the
  532. same time, brought to light that invisible force (Newtonian
  533. attraction) which holds the universe together. The latter
  534. would have remained forever undiscovered, if Copernicus had
  535. not ventured on the experiment--contrary to the senses but
  536. still just--of looking for the observed movements not in the
  537. heavenly bodies, but in the spectator. In this Preface I
  538. treat the new metaphysical method as a hypothesis with the
  539. view of rendering apparent the first attempts at such a
  540. change of method, which are always hypothetical. But in the
  541. Critique itself it will be demonstrated, not hypothetically,
  542. but apodeictically, from the nature of our representations
  543. of space and time, and from the elementary conceptions of
  544. the understanding.]
  545. This attempt to introduce a complete revolution in the procedure
  546. of metaphysics, after the example of the geometricians and natural
  547. philosophers, constitutes the aim of the Critique of Pure Speculative
  548. Reason. It is a treatise on the method to be followed, not a system of
  549. the science itself. But, at the same time, it marks out and defines both
  550. the external boundaries and the internal structure of this science.
  551. For pure speculative reason has this peculiarity, that, in choosing the
  552. various objects of thought, it is able to define the limits of its own
  553. faculties, and even to give a complete enumeration of the possible
  554. modes of proposing problems to itself, and thus to sketch out the entire
  555. system of metaphysics. For, on the one hand, in cognition a priori,
  556. nothing must be attributed to the objects but what the thinking subject
  557. derives from itself; and, on the other hand, reason is, in regard to
  558. the principles of cognition, a perfectly distinct, independent unity, in
  559. which, as in an organized body, every member exists for the sake of
  560. the others, and all for the sake of each, so that no principle can be
  561. viewed, with safety, in one relationship, unless it is, at the same
  562. time, viewed in relation to the total use of pure reason. Hence, too,
  563. metaphysics has this singular advantage--an advantage which falls to the
  564. lot of no other science which has to do with objects--that, if once it
  565. is conducted into the sure path of science, by means of this criticism,
  566. it can then take in the whole sphere of its cognitions, and can thus
  567. complete its work, and leave it for the use of posterity, as a capital
  568. which can never receive fresh accessions. For metaphysics has to deal
  569. only with principles and with the limitations of its own employment as
  570. determined by these principles. To this perfection it is, therefore,
  571. bound, as the fundamental science, to attain, and to it the maxim may
  572. justly be applied:
  573. Nil actum reputans, si quid superesset agendum.
  574. But, it will be asked, what kind of a treasure is this that we propose
  575. to bequeath to posterity? What is the real value of this system of
  576. metaphysics, purified by criticism, and thereby reduced to a permanent
  577. condition? A cursory view of the present work will lead to the
  578. supposition that its use is merely negative, that it only serves to
  579. warn us against venturing, with speculative reason, beyond the limits
  580. of experience. This is, in fact, its primary use. But this, at once,
  581. assumes a positive value, when we observe that the principles with which
  582. speculative reason endeavours to transcend its limits lead inevitably,
  583. not to the extension, but to the contraction of the use of reason,
  584. inasmuch as they threaten to extend the limits of sensibility, which
  585. is their proper sphere, over the entire realm of thought and, thus,
  586. to supplant the pure (practical) use of reason. So far, then, as this
  587. criticism is occupied in confining speculative reason within its proper
  588. bounds, it is only negative; but, inasmuch as it thereby, at the same
  589. time, removes an obstacle which impedes and even threatens to destroy
  590. the use of practical reason, it possesses a positive and very important
  591. value. In order to admit this, we have only to be convinced that there
  592. is an absolutely necessary use of pure reason--the moral use--in which
  593. it inevitably transcends the limits of sensibility, without the aid
  594. of speculation, requiring only to be insured against the effects of a
  595. speculation which would involve it in contradiction with itself. To deny
  596. the positive advantage of the service which this criticism renders
  597. us would be as absurd as to maintain that the system of police is
  598. productive of no positive benefit, since its main business is to prevent
  599. the violence which citizen has to apprehend from citizen, that so each
  600. may pursue his vocation in peace and security. That space and time are
  601. only forms of sensible intuition, and hence are only conditions of the
  602. existence of things as phenomena; that, moreover, we have no conceptions
  603. of the understanding, and, consequently, no elements for the cognition
  604. of things, except in so far as a corresponding intuition can be given
  605. to these conceptions; that, accordingly, we can have no cognition of
  606. an object, as a thing in itself, but only as an object of sensible
  607. intuition, that is, as phenomenon--all this is proved in the analytical
  608. part of the Critique; and from this the limitation of all possible
  609. speculative cognition to the mere objects of experience, follows as a
  610. necessary result. At the same time, it must be carefully borne in mind
  611. that, while we surrender the power of cognizing, we still reserve the
  612. power of thinking objects, as things in themselves.* For, otherwise,
  613. we should require to affirm the existence of an appearance, without
  614. something that appears--which would be absurd. Now let us suppose, for a
  615. moment, that we had not undertaken this criticism and, accordingly,
  616. had not drawn the necessary distinction between things as objects
  617. of experience and things as they are in themselves. The principle of
  618. causality, and, by consequence, the mechanism of nature as determined by
  619. causality, would then have absolute validity in relation to all things
  620. as efficient causes. I should then be unable to assert, with regard to
  621. one and the same being, e.g., the human soul, that its will is free, and
  622. yet, at the same time, subject to natural necessity, that is, not free,
  623. without falling into a palpable contradiction, for in both propositions
  624. I should take the soul in the same signification, as a thing in general,
  625. as a thing in itself--as, without previous criticism, I could not but
  626. take it. Suppose now, on the other hand, that we have undertaken this
  627. criticism, and have learnt that an object may be taken in two senses,
  628. first, as a phenomenon, secondly, as a thing in itself; and that,
  629. according to the deduction of the conceptions of the understanding, the
  630. principle of causality has reference only to things in the first sense.
  631. We then see how it does not involve any contradiction to assert, on the
  632. one hand, that the will, in the phenomenal sphere--in visible action--is
  633. necessarily obedient to the law of nature, and, in so far, not free;
  634. and, on the other hand, that, as belonging to a thing in itself, it is
  635. not subject to that law, and, accordingly, is free. Now, it is true that
  636. I cannot, by means of speculative reason, and still less by empirical
  637. observation, cognize my soul as a thing in itself and consequently,
  638. cannot cognize liberty as the property of a being to which I ascribe
  639. effects in the world of sense. For, to do so, I must cognize this being
  640. as existing, and yet not in time, which--since I cannot support my
  641. conception by any intuition--is impossible. At the same time, while
  642. I cannot cognize, I can quite well think freedom, that is to say, my
  643. representation of it involves at least no contradiction, if we bear in
  644. mind the critical distinction of the two modes of representation (the
  645. sensible and the intellectual) and the consequent limitation of the
  646. conceptions of the pure understanding and of the principles which flow
  647. from them. Suppose now that morality necessarily presupposed liberty,
  648. in the strictest sense, as a property of our will; suppose that reason
  649. contained certain practical, original principles a priori, which were
  650. absolutely impossible without this presupposition; and suppose, at the
  651. same time, that speculative reason had proved that liberty was
  652. incapable of being thought at all. It would then follow that the
  653. moral presupposition must give way to the speculative affirmation, the
  654. opposite of which involves an obvious contradiction, and that liberty
  655. and, with it, morality must yield to the mechanism of nature; for
  656. the negation of morality involves no contradiction, except on the
  657. presupposition of liberty. Now morality does not require the speculative
  658. cognition of liberty; it is enough that I can think it, that its
  659. conception involves no contradiction, that it does not interfere with
  660. the mechanism of nature. But even this requirement we could not satisfy,
  661. if we had not learnt the twofold sense in which things may be taken; and
  662. it is only in this way that the doctrine of morality and the doctrine of
  663. nature are confined within their proper limits. For this result,
  664. then, we are indebted to a criticism which warns us of our unavoidable
  665. ignorance with regard to things in themselves, and establishes the
  666. necessary limitation of our theoretical cognition to mere phenomena.
  667. [*Footnote: In order to cognize an object, I must be able to
  668. prove its possibility, either from its reality as attested
  669. by experience, or a priori, by means of reason. But I can
  670. think what I please, provided only I do not contradict
  671. myself; that is, provided my conception is a possible
  672. thought, though I may be unable to answer for the existence
  673. of a corresponding object in the sum of possibilities. But
  674. something more is required before I can attribute to such a
  675. conception objective validity, that is real possibility--the
  676. other possibility being merely logical. We are not, however,
  677. confined to theoretical sources of cognition for the means
  678. of satisfying this additional requirement, but may derive
  679. them from practical sources.]
  680. The positive value of the critical principles of pure reason in relation
  681. to the conception of God and of the simple nature of the soul, admits of
  682. a similar exemplification; but on this point I shall not dwell. I
  683. cannot even make the assumption--as the practical interests of
  684. morality require--of God, freedom, and immortality, if I do not deprive
  685. speculative reason of its pretensions to transcendent insight. For to
  686. arrive at these, it must make use of principles which, in fact, extend
  687. only to the objects of possible experience, and which cannot be applied
  688. to objects beyond this sphere without converting them into phenomena,
  689. and thus rendering the practical extension of pure reason impossible.
  690. I must, therefore, abolish knowledge, to make room for belief. The
  691. dogmatism of metaphysics, that is, the presumption that it is possible
  692. to advance in metaphysics without previous criticism, is the true source
  693. of the unbelief (always dogmatic) which militates against morality.
  694. Thus, while it may be no very difficult task to bequeath a legacy
  695. to posterity, in the shape of a system of metaphysics constructed in
  696. accordance with the Critique of Pure Reason, still the value of such a
  697. bequest is not to be depreciated. It will render an important service
  698. to reason, by substituting the certainty of scientific method for that
  699. random groping after results without the guidance of principles, which
  700. has hitherto characterized the pursuit of metaphysical studies. It will
  701. render an important service to the inquiring mind of youth, by leading
  702. the student to apply his powers to the cultivation of genuine science,
  703. instead of wasting them, as at present, on speculations which can never
  704. lead to any result, or on the idle attempt to invent new ideas and
  705. opinions. But, above all, it will confer an inestimable benefit on
  706. morality and religion, by showing that all the objections urged against
  707. them may be silenced for ever by the Socratic method, that is to say, by
  708. proving the ignorance of the objector. For, as the world has never been,
  709. and, no doubt, never will be without a system of metaphysics of one kind
  710. or another, it is the highest and weightiest concern of philosophy to
  711. render it powerless for harm, by closing up the sources of error.
  712. This important change in the field of the sciences, this loss of its
  713. fancied possessions, to which speculative reason must submit, does not
  714. prove in any way detrimental to the general interests of humanity. The
  715. advantages which the world has derived from the teachings of pure reason
  716. are not at all impaired. The loss falls, in its whole extent, on the
  717. monopoly of the schools, but does not in the slightest degree touch the
  718. interests of mankind. I appeal to the most obstinate dogmatist, whether
  719. the proof of the continued existence of the soul after death, derived
  720. from the simplicity of its substance; of the freedom of the will in
  721. opposition to the general mechanism of nature, drawn from the subtle but
  722. impotent distinction of subjective and objective practical necessity;
  723. or of the existence of God, deduced from the conception of an ens
  724. realissimum--the contingency of the changeable, and the necessity of
  725. a prime mover, has ever been able to pass beyond the limits of the
  726. schools, to penetrate the public mind, or to exercise the slightest
  727. influence on its convictions. It must be admitted that this has not been
  728. the case and that, owing to the unfitness of the common understanding
  729. for such subtle speculations, it can never be expected to take place. On
  730. the contrary, it is plain that the hope of a future life arises from the
  731. feeling, which exists in the breast of every man, that the temporal
  732. is inadequate to meet and satisfy the demands of his nature. In like
  733. manner, it cannot be doubted that the clear exhibition of duties
  734. in opposition to all the claims of inclination, gives rise to the
  735. consciousness of freedom, and that the glorious order, beauty, and
  736. providential care, everywhere displayed in nature, give rise to the
  737. belief in a wise and great Author of the Universe. Such is the genesis
  738. of these general convictions of mankind, so far as they depend on
  739. rational grounds; and this public property not only remains undisturbed,
  740. but is even raised to greater importance, by the doctrine that the
  741. schools have no right to arrogate to themselves a more profound insight
  742. into a matter of general human concernment than that to which the great
  743. mass of men, ever held by us in the highest estimation, can without
  744. difficulty attain, and that the schools should, therefore, confine
  745. themselves to the elaboration of these universally comprehensible and,
  746. from a moral point of view, amply satisfactory proofs. The change,
  747. therefore, affects only the arrogant pretensions of the schools, which
  748. would gladly retain, in their own exclusive possession, the key to the
  749. truths which they impart to the public.
  750. Quod mecum nescit, solus vult scire videri.
  751. At the same time it does not deprive the speculative philosopher of
  752. his just title to be the sole depositor of a science which benefits the
  753. public without its knowledge--I mean, the Critique of Pure Reason. This
  754. can never become popular and, indeed, has no occasion to be so; for
  755. finespun arguments in favour of useful truths make just as little
  756. impression on the public mind as the equally subtle objections brought
  757. against these truths. On the other hand, since both inevitably force
  758. themselves on every man who rises to the height of speculation, it
  759. becomes the manifest duty of the schools to enter upon a thorough
  760. investigation of the rights of speculative reason and, thus, to prevent
  761. the scandal which metaphysical controversies are sure, sooner or later,
  762. to cause even to the masses. It is only by criticism that metaphysicians
  763. (and, as such, theologians too) can be saved from these controversies
  764. and from the consequent perversion of their doctrines. Criticism
  765. alone can strike a blow at the root of materialism, fatalism, atheism,
  766. free-thinking, fanaticism, and superstition, which are universally
  767. injurious--as well as of idealism and scepticism, which are dangerous
  768. to the schools, but can scarcely pass over to the public. If governments
  769. think proper to interfere with the affairs of the learned, it would be
  770. more consistent with a wise regard for the interests of science, as well
  771. as for those of society, to favour a criticism of this kind, by which
  772. alone the labours of reason can be established on a firm basis, than to
  773. support the ridiculous despotism of the schools, which raise a loud cry
  774. of danger to the public over the destruction of cobwebs, of which the
  775. public has never taken any notice, and the loss of which, therefore, it
  776. can never feel.
  777. This critical science is not opposed to the dogmatic procedure of reason
  778. in pure cognition; for pure cognition must always be dogmatic, that is,
  779. must rest on strict demonstration from sure principles a priori--but to
  780. dogmatism, that is, to the presumption that it is possible to make
  781. any progress with a pure cognition, derived from (philosophical)
  782. conceptions, according to the principles which reason has long been in
  783. the habit of employing--without first inquiring in what way and by what
  784. right reason has come into the possession of these principles. Dogmatism
  785. is thus the dogmatic procedure of pure reason without previous criticism
  786. of its own powers, and in opposing this procedure, we must not be
  787. supposed to lend any countenance to that loquacious shallowness which
  788. arrogates to itself the name of popularity, nor yet to scepticism, which
  789. makes short work with the whole science of metaphysics. On the contrary,
  790. our criticism is the necessary preparation for a thoroughly scientific
  791. system of metaphysics which must perform its task entirely a priori, to
  792. the complete satisfaction of speculative reason, and must, therefore,
  793. be treated, not popularly, but scholastically. In carrying out the
  794. plan which the Critique prescribes, that is, in the future system
  795. of metaphysics, we must have recourse to the strict method of the
  796. celebrated Wolf, the greatest of all dogmatic philosophers. He was the
  797. first to point out the necessity of establishing fixed principles, of
  798. clearly defining our conceptions, and of subjecting our demonstrations
  799. to the most severe scrutiny, instead of rashly jumping at conclusions.
  800. The example which he set served to awaken that spirit of profound and
  801. thorough investigation which is not yet extinct in Germany. He would
  802. have been peculiarly well fitted to give a truly scientific character to
  803. metaphysical studies, had it occurred to him to prepare the field by a
  804. criticism of the organum, that is, of pure reason itself. That he failed
  805. to perceive the necessity of such a procedure must be ascribed to the
  806. dogmatic mode of thought which characterized his age, and on this point
  807. the philosophers of his time, as well as of all previous times, have
  808. nothing to reproach each other with. Those who reject at once the method
  809. of Wolf, and of the Critique of Pure Reason, can have no other aim
  810. but to shake off the fetters of science, to change labour into sport,
  811. certainty into opinion, and philosophy into philodoxy.
  812. In this second edition, I have endeavoured, as far as possible, to
  813. remove the difficulties and obscurity which, without fault of mine
  814. perhaps, have given rise to many misconceptions even among acute
  815. thinkers. In the propositions themselves, and in the demonstrations by
  816. which they are supported, as well as in the form and the entire plan of
  817. the work, I have found nothing to alter; which must be attributed
  818. partly to the long examination to which I had subjected the whole before
  819. offering it to the public and partly to the nature of the case. For pure
  820. speculative reason is an organic structure in which there is nothing
  821. isolated or independent, but every Single part is essential to all the
  822. rest; and hence, the slightest imperfection, whether defect or positive
  823. error, could not fail to betray itself in use. I venture, further, to
  824. hope, that this system will maintain the same unalterable character for
  825. the future. I am led to entertain this confidence, not by vanity, but by
  826. the evidence which the equality of the result affords, when we proceed,
  827. first, from the simplest elements up to the complete whole of pure
  828. reason and, and then, backwards from the whole to each part. We find
  829. that the attempt to make the slightest alteration, in any part, leads
  830. inevitably to contradictions, not merely in this system, but in
  831. human reason itself. At the same time, there is still much room for
  832. improvement in the exposition of the doctrines contained in this work.
  833. In the present edition, I have endeavoured to remove misapprehensions of
  834. the aesthetical part, especially with regard to the conception of time;
  835. to clear away the obscurity which has been found in the deduction of
  836. the conceptions of the understanding; to supply the supposed want of
  837. sufficient evidence in the demonstration of the principles of the pure
  838. understanding; and, lastly, to obviate the misunderstanding of the
  839. paralogisms which immediately precede the rational psychology. Beyond
  840. this point--the end of the second main division of the "Transcendental
  841. Dialectic"--I have not extended my alterations,* partly from want
  842. of time, and partly because I am not aware that any portion of the
  843. remainder has given rise to misconceptions among intelligent and
  844. impartial critics, whom I do not here mention with that praise which is
  845. their due, but who will find that their suggestions have been attended
  846. to in the work itself.
  847. [*Footnote: The only addition, properly so called--and that
  848. only in the method of proof--which I have made in the
  849. present edition, consists of a new refutation of
  850. psychological idealism, and a strict demonstration--the only
  851. one possible, as I believe--of the objective reality of
  852. external intuition. However harmless idealism may be
  853. considered--although in reality it is not so--in regard to
  854. the essential ends of metaphysics, it must still remain a
  855. scandal to philosophy and to the general human reason to be
  856. obliged to assume, as an article of mere belief, the
  857. existence of things external to ourselves (from which, yet,
  858. we derive the whole material of cognition for the internal
  859. sense), and not to be able to oppose a satisfactory proof to
  860. any one who may call it in question. As there is some
  861. obscurity of expression in the demonstration as it stands in
  862. the text, I propose to alter the passage in question as
  863. follows: "But this permanent cannot be an intuition in me.
  864. For all the determining grounds of my existence which can be
  865. found in me are representations and, as such, do themselves
  866. require a permanent, distinct from them, which may determine
  867. my existence in relation to their changes, that is, my
  868. existence in time, wherein they change." It may, probably,
  869. be urged in opposition to this proof that, after all, I am
  870. only conscious immediately of that which is in me, that is,
  871. of my representation of external things, and that,
  872. consequently, it must always remain uncertain whether
  873. anything corresponding to this representation does or does
  874. not exist externally to me. But I am conscious, through
  875. internal experience, of my existence in time (consequently,
  876. also, of the determinability of the former in the latter),
  877. and that is more than the simple consciousness of my
  878. representation. It is, in fact, the same as the empirical
  879. consciousness of my existence, which can only be determined
  880. in relation to something, which, while connected with my
  881. existence, is external to me. This consciousness of my
  882. existence in time is, therefore, identical with the
  883. consciousness of a relation to something external to me, and
  884. it is, therefore, experience, not fiction, sense, not
  885. imagination, which inseparably connects the external with my
  886. internal sense. For the external sense is, in itself, the
  887. relation of intuition to something real, external to me; and
  888. the reality of this something, as opposed to the mere
  889. imagination of it, rests solely on its inseparable
  890. connection with internal experience as the condition of its
  891. possibility. If with the intellectual consciousness of my
  892. existence, in the representation: I am, which accompanies
  893. all my judgements, and all the operations of my
  894. understanding, I could, at the same time, connect a
  895. determination of my existence by intellectual intuition,
  896. then the consciousness of a relation to something external
  897. to me would not be necessary. But the internal intuition in
  898. which alone my existence can be determined, though preceded
  899. by that purely intellectual consciousness, is itself
  900. sensible and attached to the condition of time. Hence this
  901. determination of my existence, and consequently my internal
  902. experience itself, must depend on something permanent which
  903. is not in me, which can be, therefore, only in something
  904. external to me, to which I must look upon myself as being
  905. related. Thus the reality of the external sense is
  906. necessarily connected with that of the internal, in order to
  907. the possibility of experience in general; that is, I am just
  908. as certainly conscious that there are things external to me
  909. related to my sense as I am that I myself exist as
  910. determined in time. But in order to ascertain to what given
  911. intuitions objects, external me, really correspond, in other
  912. words, what intuitions belong to the external sense and not
  913. to imagination, I must have recourse, in every particular
  914. case, to those rules according to which experience in
  915. general (even internal experience) is distinguished from
  916. imagination, and which are always based on the proposition
  917. that there really is an external experience. We may add the
  918. remark that the representation of something permanent in
  919. existence, is not the same thing as the permanent
  920. representation; for a representation may be very variable
  921. and changing--as all our representations, even that of
  922. matter, are--and yet refer to something permanent, which
  923. must, therefore, be distinct from all my representations and
  924. external to me, the existence of which is necessarily
  925. included in the determination of my own existence, and with
  926. it constitutes one experience--an experience which would not
  927. even be possible internally, if it were not also at the same
  928. time, in part, external. To the question How? we are no more
  929. able to reply, than we are, in general, to think the
  930. stationary in time, the coexistence of which with the
  931. variable, produces the conception of change.]
  932. In attempting to render the exposition of my views as intelligible as
  933. possible, I have been compelled to leave out or abridge various passages
  934. which were not essential to the completeness of the work, but which many
  935. readers might consider useful in other respects, and might be unwilling
  936. to miss. This trifling loss, which could not be avoided without swelling
  937. the book beyond due limits, may be supplied, at the pleasure of the
  938. reader, by a comparison with the first edition, and will, I hope, be
  939. more than compensated for by the greater clearness of the exposition as
  940. it now stands.
  941. I have observed, with pleasure and thankfulness, in the pages of
  942. various reviews and treatises, that the spirit of profound and thorough
  943. investigation is not extinct in Germany, though it may have been
  944. overborne and silenced for a time by the fashionable tone of a licence
  945. in thinking, which gives itself the airs of genius, and that the
  946. difficulties which beset the paths of criticism have not prevented
  947. energetic and acute thinkers from making themselves masters of the
  948. science of pure reason to which these paths conduct--a science which is
  949. not popular, but scholastic in its character, and which alone can hope
  950. for a lasting existence or possess an abiding value. To these deserving
  951. men, who so happily combine profundity of view with a talent for lucid
  952. exposition--a talent which I myself am not conscious of possessing--I
  953. leave the task of removing any obscurity which may still adhere to the
  954. statement of my doctrines. For, in this case, the danger is not that
  955. of being refuted, but of being misunderstood. For my own part, I must
  956. henceforward abstain from controversy, although I shall carefully attend
  957. to all suggestions, whether from friends or adversaries, which may be
  958. of use in the future elaboration of the system of this propaedeutic. As,
  959. during these labours, I have advanced pretty far in years this month
  960. I reach my sixty-fourth year--it will be necessary for me to economize
  961. time, if I am to carry out my plan of elaborating the metaphysics of
  962. nature as well as of morals, in confirmation of the correctness of the
  963. principles established in this Critique of Pure Reason, both speculative
  964. and practical; and I must, therefore, leave the task of clearing up the
  965. obscurities of the present work--inevitable, perhaps, at the outset--as
  966. well as, the defence of the whole, to those deserving men, who have made
  967. my system their own. A philosophical system cannot come forward armed
  968. at all points like a mathematical treatise, and hence it may be quite
  969. possible to take objection to particular passages, while the organic
  970. structure of the system, considered as a unity, has no danger to
  971. apprehend. But few possess the ability, and still fewer the inclination,
  972. to take a comprehensive view of a new system. By confining the view to
  973. particular passages, taking these out of their connection and comparing
  974. them with one another, it is easy to pick out apparent contradictions,
  975. especially in a work written with any freedom of style. These
  976. contradictions place the work in an unfavourable light in the eyes of
  977. those who rely on the judgement of others, but are easily reconciled
  978. by those who have mastered the idea of the whole. If a theory possesses
  979. stability in itself, the action and reaction which seemed at first to
  980. threaten its existence serve only, in the course of time, to smooth
  981. down any superficial roughness or inequality, and--if men of insight,
  982. impartiality, and truly popular gifts, turn their attention to it--to
  983. secure to it, in a short time, the requisite elegance also.
  984. Konigsberg, April 1787.
  985. INTRODUCTION
  986. I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge
  987. That all our knowledge begins with experience there can be no doubt. For
  988. how is it possible that the faculty of cognition should be awakened into
  989. exercise otherwise than by means of objects which affect our senses, and
  990. partly of themselves produce representations, partly rouse our powers
  991. of understanding into activity, to compare to connect, or to separate
  992. these, and so to convert the raw material of our sensuous impressions
  993. into a knowledge of objects, which is called experience? In respect of
  994. time, therefore, no knowledge of ours is antecedent to experience, but
  995. begins with it.
  996. But, though all our knowledge begins with experience, it by no means
  997. follows that all arises out of experience. For, on the contrary, it is
  998. quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound of that which
  999. we receive through impressions, and that which the faculty of cognition
  1000. supplies from itself (sensuous impressions giving merely the occasion),
  1001. an addition which we cannot distinguish from the original element given
  1002. by sense, till long practice has made us attentive to, and skilful
  1003. in separating it. It is, therefore, a question which requires close
  1004. investigation, and not to be answered at first sight, whether there
  1005. exists a knowledge altogether independent of experience, and even of
  1006. all sensuous impressions? Knowledge of this kind is called a priori,
  1007. in contradistinction to empirical knowledge, which has its sources a
  1008. posteriori, that is, in experience.
  1009. But the expression, "a priori," is not as yet definite enough adequately
  1010. to indicate the whole meaning of the question above started. For, in
  1011. speaking of knowledge which has its sources in experience, we are wont
  1012. to say, that this or that may be known a priori, because we do not
  1013. derive this knowledge immediately from experience, but from a general
  1014. rule, which, however, we have itself borrowed from experience. Thus,
  1015. if a man undermined his house, we say, "he might know a priori that
  1016. it would have fallen;" that is, he needed not to have waited for the
  1017. experience that it did actually fall. But still, a priori, he could not
  1018. know even this much. For, that bodies are heavy, and, consequently, that
  1019. they fall when their supports are taken away, must have been known to
  1020. him previously, by means of experience.
  1021. By the term "knowledge a priori," therefore, we shall in the sequel
  1022. understand, not such as is independent of this or that kind of
  1023. experience, but such as is absolutely so of all experience. Opposed
  1024. to this is empirical knowledge, or that which is possible only a
  1025. posteriori, that is, through experience. Knowledge a priori is either
  1026. pure or impure. Pure knowledge a priori is that with which no empirical
  1027. element is mixed up. For example, the proposition, "Every change has
  1028. a cause," is a proposition a priori, but impure, because change is a
  1029. conception which can only be derived from experience.
  1030. II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in
  1031. Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori".
  1032. The question now is as to a criterion, by which we may securely
  1033. distinguish a pure from an empirical cognition. Experience no doubt
  1034. teaches us that this or that object is constituted in such and such a
  1035. manner, but not that it could not possibly exist otherwise. Now, in
  1036. the first place, if we have a proposition which contains the idea
  1037. of necessity in its very conception, it is priori. If, moreover, it is not
  1038. derived from any other proposition, unless from one equally involving
  1039. the idea of necessity, it is absolutely priori. Secondly, an empirical
  1040. judgement never exhibits strict and absolute, but only assumed and
  1041. comparative universality (by induction); therefore, the most we can say
  1042. is--so far as we have hitherto observed, there is no exception to this
  1043. or that rule. If, on the other hand, a judgement carries with it strict
  1044. and absolute universality, that is, admits of no possible exception, it
  1045. is not derived from experience, but is valid absolutely a priori.
  1046. Empirical universality is, therefore, only an arbitrary extension of
  1047. validity, from that which may be predicated of a proposition valid in
  1048. most cases, to that which is asserted of a proposition which holds good
  1049. in all; as, for example, in the affirmation, "All bodies are heavy."
  1050. When, on the contrary, strict universality characterizes a judgement,
  1051. it necessarily indicates another peculiar source of knowledge, namely,
  1052. a faculty of cognition a priori. Necessity and strict universality,
  1053. therefore, are infallible tests for distinguishing pure from empirical
  1054. knowledge, and are inseparably connected with each other. But as in the
  1055. use of these criteria the empirical limitation is sometimes more
  1056. easily detected than the contingency of the judgement, or the unlimited
  1057. universality which we attach to a judgement is often a more convincing
  1058. proof than its necessity, it may be advisable to use the criteria
  1059. separately, each being by itself infallible.
  1060. Now, that in the sphere of human cognition we have judgements which are
  1061. necessary, and in the strictest sense universal, consequently pure a
  1062. priori, it will be an easy matter to show. If we desire an example from
  1063. the sciences, we need only take any proposition in mathematics. If we
  1064. cast our eyes upon the commonest operations of the understanding, the
  1065. proposition, "Every change must have a cause," will amply serve our
  1066. purpose. In the latter case, indeed, the conception of a cause so
  1067. plainly involves the conception of a necessity of connection with an
  1068. effect, and of a strict universality of the law, that the very notion of
  1069. a cause would entirely disappear, were we to derive it, like Hume, from
  1070. a frequent association of what happens with that which precedes; and the
  1071. habit thence originating of connecting representations--the necessity
  1072. inherent in the judgement being therefore merely subjective. Besides,
  1073. without seeking for such examples of principles existing a priori
  1074. in cognition, we might easily show that such principles are the
  1075. indispensable basis of the possibility of experience itself, and
  1076. consequently prove their existence a priori. For whence could our
  1077. experience itself acquire certainty, if all the rules on which it
  1078. depends were themselves empirical, and consequently fortuitous? No one,
  1079. therefore, can admit the validity of the use of such rules as first
  1080. principles. But, for the present, we may content ourselves with having
  1081. established the fact, that we do possess and exercise a faculty of pure
  1082. a priori cognition; and, secondly, with having pointed out the proper
  1083. tests of such cognition, namely, universality and necessity.
  1084. Not only in judgements, however, but even in conceptions, is an a
  1085. priori origin manifest. For example, if we take away by degrees from
  1086. our conceptions of a body all that can be referred to mere
  1087. sensuous experience--colour, hardness or softness, weight, even
  1088. impenetrability--the body will then vanish; but the space which it
  1089. occupied still remains, and this it is utterly impossible to annihilate
  1090. in thought. Again, if we take away, in like manner, from our empirical
  1091. conception of any object, corporeal or incorporeal, all properties which
  1092. mere experience has taught us to connect with it, still we cannot think
  1093. away those through which we cogitate it as substance, or adhering to
  1094. substance, although our conception of substance is more determined than
  1095. that of an object. Compelled, therefore, by that necessity with which
  1096. the conception of substance forces itself upon us, we must confess that
  1097. it has its seat in our faculty of cognition a priori.
  1098. III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the
  1099. Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human Knowledge "a priori"
  1100. Of far more importance than all that has been above said, is the
  1101. consideration that certain of our cognitions rise completely above the
  1102. sphere of all possible experience, and by means of conceptions, to which
  1103. there exists in the whole extent of experience no corresponding object,
  1104. seem to extend the range of our judgements beyond its bounds. And just
  1105. in this transcendental or supersensible sphere, where experience affords
  1106. us neither instruction nor guidance, lie the investigations of reason,
  1107. which, on account of their importance, we consider far preferable to,
  1108. and as having a far more elevated aim than, all that the understanding
  1109. can achieve within the sphere of sensuous phenomena. So high a value
  1110. do we set upon these investigations, that even at the risk of error, we
  1111. persist in following them out, and permit neither doubt nor disregard
  1112. nor indifference to restrain us from the pursuit. These unavoidable
  1113. problems of mere pure reason are God, freedom (of will), and
  1114. immortality. The science which, with all its preliminaries, has for its
  1115. especial object the solution of these problems is named metaphysics--a
  1116. science which is at the very outset dogmatical, that is, it confidently
  1117. takes upon itself the execution of this task without any previous
  1118. investigation of the ability or inability of reason for such an
  1119. undertaking.
  1120. Now the safe ground of experience being thus abandoned, it seems
  1121. nevertheless natural that we should hesitate to erect a building with
  1122. the cognitions we possess, without knowing whence they come, and on the
  1123. strength of principles, the origin of which is undiscovered. Instead of
  1124. thus trying to build without a foundation, it is rather to be expected
  1125. that we should long ago have put the question, how the understanding can
  1126. arrive at these a priori cognitions, and what is the extent, validity,
  1127. and worth which they may possess? We say, "This is natural enough,"
  1128. meaning by the word natural, that which is consistent with a just and
  1129. reasonable way of thinking; but if we understand by the term, that
  1130. which usually happens, nothing indeed could be more natural and
  1131. more comprehensible than that this investigation should be left
  1132. long unattempted. For one part of our pure knowledge, the science of
  1133. mathematics, has been long firmly established, and thus leads us to form
  1134. flattering expectations with regard to others, though these may be of
  1135. quite a different nature. Besides, when we get beyond the bounds of
  1136. experience, we are of course safe from opposition in that quarter;
  1137. and the charm of widening the range of our knowledge is so great that,
  1138. unless we are brought to a standstill by some evident contradiction, we
  1139. hurry on undoubtingly in our course. This, however, may be avoided, if
  1140. we are sufficiently cautious in the construction of our fictions, which
  1141. are not the less fictions on that account.
  1142. Mathematical science affords us a brilliant example, how far,
  1143. independently of all experience, we may carry our a priori knowledge.
  1144. It is true that the mathematician occupies himself with objects and
  1145. cognitions only in so far as they can be represented by means of
  1146. intuition. But this circumstance is easily overlooked, because the said
  1147. intuition can itself be given a priori, and therefore is hardly to be
  1148. distinguished from a mere pure conception. Deceived by such a proof of
  1149. the power of reason, we can perceive no limits to the extension of our
  1150. knowledge. The light dove cleaving in free flight the thin air, whose
  1151. resistance it feels, might imagine that her movements would be far
  1152. more free and rapid in airless space. Just in the same way did Plato,
  1153. abandoning the world of sense because of the narrow limits it sets to
  1154. the understanding, venture upon the wings of ideas beyond it, into the
  1155. void space of pure intellect. He did not reflect that he made no real
  1156. progress by all his efforts; for he met with no resistance which might
  1157. serve him for a support, as it were, whereon to rest, and on which he
  1158. might apply his powers, in order to let the intellect acquire momentum
  1159. for its progress. It is, indeed, the common fate of human reason in
  1160. speculation, to finish the imposing edifice of thought as rapidly as
  1161. possible, and then for the first time to begin to examine whether the
  1162. foundation is a solid one or no. Arrived at this point, all sorts
  1163. of excuses are sought after, in order to console us for its want of
  1164. stability, or rather, indeed, to enable Us to dispense altogether with
  1165. so late and dangerous an investigation. But what frees us during the
  1166. process of building from all apprehension or suspicion, and flatters
  1167. us into the belief of its solidity, is this. A great part, perhaps the
  1168. greatest part, of the business of our reason consists in the analysation
  1169. of the conceptions which we already possess of objects. By this means we
  1170. gain a multitude of cognitions, which although really nothing more than
  1171. elucidations or explanations of that which (though in a confused manner)
  1172. was already thought in our conceptions, are, at least in respect of
  1173. their form, prized as new introspections; whilst, so far as regards
  1174. their matter or content, we have really made no addition to our
  1175. conceptions, but only disinvolved them. But as this process does furnish
  1176. a real priori knowledge, which has a sure progress and useful results,
  1177. reason, deceived by this, slips in, without being itself aware of it,
  1178. assertions of a quite different kind; in which, to given conceptions it
  1179. adds others, a priori indeed, but entirely foreign to them, without our
  1180. knowing how it arrives at these, and, indeed, without such a question
  1181. ever suggesting itself. I shall therefore at once proceed to examine the
  1182. difference between these two modes of knowledge.
  1183. IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements.
  1184. In all judgements wherein the relation of a subject to the predicate is
  1185. cogitated (I mention affirmative judgements only here; the application
  1186. to negative will be very easy), this relation is possible in two
  1187. different ways. Either the predicate B belongs to the subject A, as
  1188. somewhat which is contained (though covertly) in the conception A; or
  1189. the predicate B lies completely out of the conception A, although
  1190. it stands in connection with it. In the first instance, I term the
  1191. judgement analytical, in the second, synthetical. Analytical judgements
  1192. (affirmative) are therefore those in which the connection of the
  1193. predicate with the subject is cogitated through identity; those in which
  1194. this connection is cogitated without identity, are called synthetical
  1195. judgements. The former may be called explicative, the latter
  1196. augmentative judgements; because the former add in the predicate
  1197. nothing to the conception of the subject, but only analyse it into its
  1198. constituent conceptions, which were thought already in the subject,
  1199. although in a confused manner; the latter add to our conceptions of the
  1200. subject a predicate which was not contained in it, and which no analysis
  1201. could ever have discovered therein. For example, when I say, "All bodies
  1202. are extended," this is an analytical judgement. For I need not go beyond
  1203. the conception of body in order to find extension connected with it, but
  1204. merely analyse the conception, that is, become conscious of the manifold
  1205. properties which I think in that conception, in order to discover this
  1206. predicate in it: it is therefore an analytical judgement. On the other
  1207. hand, when I say, "All bodies are heavy," the predicate is something
  1208. totally different from that which I think in the mere conception of
  1209. a body. By the addition of such a predicate, therefore, it becomes a
  1210. synthetical judgement.
  1211. Judgements of experience, as such, are always synthetical. For it would
  1212. be absurd to think of grounding an analytical judgement on experience,
  1213. because in forming such a judgement I need not go out of the sphere of
  1214. my conceptions, and therefore recourse to the testimony of experience
  1215. is quite unnecessary. That "bodies are extended" is not an empirical
  1216. judgement, but a proposition which stands firm a priori. For before
  1217. addressing myself to experience, I already have in my conception all the
  1218. requisite conditions for the judgement, and I have only to extract
  1219. the predicate from the conception, according to the principle of
  1220. contradiction, and thereby at the same time become conscious of the
  1221. necessity of the judgement, a necessity which I could never learn from
  1222. experience. On the other hand, though at first I do not at all include
  1223. the predicate of weight in my conception of body in general, that
  1224. conception still indicates an object of experience, a part of the
  1225. totality of experience, to which I can still add other parts; and this I
  1226. do when I recognize by observation that bodies are heavy. I can
  1227. cognize beforehand by analysis the conception of body through the
  1228. characteristics of extension, impenetrability, shape, etc., all which
  1229. are cogitated in this conception. But now I extend my knowledge, and
  1230. looking back on experience from which I had derived this conception
  1231. of body, I find weight at all times connected with the above
  1232. characteristics, and therefore I synthetically add to my conceptions
  1233. this as a predicate, and say, "All bodies are heavy." Thus it is
  1234. experience upon which rests the possibility of the synthesis of
  1235. the predicate of weight with the conception of body, because both
  1236. conceptions, although the one is not contained in the other, still
  1237. belong to one another (only contingently, however), as parts of a whole,
  1238. namely, of experience, which is itself a synthesis of intuitions.
  1239. But to synthetical judgements a priori, such aid is entirely wanting. If
  1240. I go out of and beyond the conception A, in order to recognize another
  1241. B as connected with it, what foundation have I to rest on, whereby to
  1242. render the synthesis possible? I have here no longer the advantage of
  1243. looking out in the sphere of experience for what I want. Let us take,
  1244. for example, the proposition, "Everything that happens has a cause." In
  1245. the conception of "something that happens," I indeed think an existence
  1246. which a certain time antecedes, and from this I can derive analytical
  1247. judgements. But the conception of a cause lies quite out of the above
  1248. conception, and indicates something entirely different from "that which
  1249. happens," and is consequently not contained in that conception. How
  1250. then am I able to assert concerning the general conception--"that which
  1251. happens"--something entirely different from that conception, and to
  1252. recognize the conception of cause although not contained in it, yet as
  1253. belonging to it, and even necessarily? what is here the unknown = X,
  1254. upon which the understanding rests when it believes it has found, out of
  1255. the conception A a foreign predicate B, which it nevertheless considers
  1256. to be connected with it? It cannot be experience, because the principle
  1257. adduced annexes the two representations, cause and effect, to the
  1258. representation existence, not only with universality, which experience
  1259. cannot give, but also with the expression of necessity, therefore
  1260. completely a priori and from pure conceptions. Upon such synthetical,
  1261. that is augmentative propositions, depends the whole aim of our
  1262. speculative knowledge a priori; for although analytical judgements are
  1263. indeed highly important and necessary, they are so, only to arrive at
  1264. that clearness of conceptions which is requisite for a sure and extended
  1265. synthesis, and this alone is a real acquisition.
  1266. V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a
  1267. priori" are contained as Principles.
  1268. 1. Mathematical judgements are always synthetical. Hitherto this fact,
  1269. though incontestably true and very important in its consequences, seems
  1270. to have escaped the analysts of the human mind, nay, to be in
  1271. complete opposition to all their conjectures. For as it was found that
  1272. mathematical conclusions all proceed according to the principle of
  1273. contradiction (which the nature of every apodeictic certainty requires),
  1274. people became persuaded that the fundamental principles of the science
  1275. also were recognized and admitted in the same way. But the notion is
  1276. fallacious; for although a synthetical proposition can certainly be
  1277. discerned by means of the principle of contradiction, this is possible
  1278. only when another synthetical proposition precedes, from which the
  1279. latter is deduced, but never of itself.
  1280. Before all, be it observed, that proper mathematical propositions are
  1281. always judgements a priori, and not empirical, because they carry
  1282. along with them the conception of necessity, which cannot be given by
  1283. experience. If this be demurred to, it matters not; I will then limit my
  1284. assertion to pure mathematics, the very conception of which implies that
  1285. it consists of knowledge altogether non-empirical and a priori.
  1286. We might, indeed at first suppose that the proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is a
  1287. merely analytical proposition, following (according to the principle of
  1288. contradiction) from the conception of a sum of seven and five. But if we
  1289. regard it more narrowly, we find that our conception of the sum of seven
  1290. and five contains nothing more than the uniting of both sums into one,
  1291. whereby it cannot at all be cogitated what this single number is which
  1292. embraces both. The conception of twelve is by no means obtained by
  1293. merely cogitating the union of seven and five; and we may analyse our
  1294. conception of such a possible sum as long as we will, still we shall
  1295. never discover in it the notion of twelve. We must go beyond these
  1296. conceptions, and have recourse to an intuition which corresponds to
  1297. one of the two--our five fingers, for example, or like Segner in his
  1298. Arithmetic five points, and so by degrees, add the units contained in
  1299. the five given in the intuition, to the conception of seven. For I first
  1300. take the number 7, and, for the conception of 5 calling in the aid of
  1301. the fingers of my hand as objects of intuition, I add the units, which I
  1302. before took together to make up the number 5, gradually now by means of
  1303. the material image my hand, to the number 7, and by this process, I
  1304. at length see the number 12 arise. That 7 should be added to 5, I have
  1305. certainly cogitated in my conception of a sum = 7 + 5, but not that
  1306. this sum was equal to 12. Arithmetical propositions are therefore always
  1307. synthetical, of which we may become more clearly convinced by trying
  1308. large numbers. For it will thus become quite evident that, turn and
  1309. twist our conceptions as we may, it is impossible, without having
  1310. recourse to intuition, to arrive at the sum total or product by means of
  1311. the mere analysis of our conceptions. Just as little is any principle
  1312. of pure geometry analytical. "A straight line between two points is the
  1313. shortest," is a synthetical proposition. For my conception of straight
  1314. contains no notion of quantity, but is merely qualitative. The
  1315. conception of the shortest is therefore fore wholly an addition, and by
  1316. no analysis can it be extracted from our conception of a straight line.
  1317. Intuition must therefore here lend its aid, by means of which, and thus
  1318. only, our synthesis is possible.
  1319. Some few principles preposited by geometricians are, indeed, really
  1320. analytical, and depend on the principle of contradiction. They serve,
  1321. however, like identical propositions, as links in the chain of method,
  1322. not as principles--for example, a = a, the whole is equal to itself,
  1323. or (a+b) --> a, the whole is greater than its part. And yet even these
  1324. principles themselves, though they derive their validity from pure
  1325. conceptions, are only admitted in mathematics because they can be
  1326. presented in intuition. What causes us here commonly to believe that
  1327. the predicate of such apodeictic judgements is already contained in our
  1328. conception, and that the judgement is therefore analytical, is merely
  1329. the equivocal nature of the expression. We must join in thought a
  1330. certain predicate to a given conception, and this necessity cleaves
  1331. already to the conception. But the question is, not what we must join
  1332. in thought to the given conception, but what we really think therein,
  1333. though only obscurely, and then it becomes manifest that the predicate
  1334. pertains to these conceptions, necessarily indeed, yet not as thought
  1335. in the conception itself, but by virtue of an intuition, which must be
  1336. added to the conception.
  1337. 2. The science of natural philosophy (physics) contains in itself
  1338. synthetical judgements a priori, as principles. I shall adduce two
  1339. propositions. For instance, the proposition, "In all changes of the
  1340. material world, the quantity of matter remains unchanged"; or, that, "In
  1341. all communication of motion, action and reaction must always be equal."
  1342. In both of these, not only is the necessity, and therefore their origin
  1343. a priori clear, but also that they are synthetical propositions. For in
  1344. the conception of matter, I do not cogitate its permanency, but merely
  1345. its presence in space, which it fills. I therefore really go out of and
  1346. beyond the conception of matter, in order to think on to it something
  1347. a priori, which I did not think in it. The proposition is therefore not
  1348. analytical, but synthetical, and nevertheless conceived a priori; and so
  1349. it is with regard to the other propositions of the pure part of natural
  1350. philosophy.
  1351. 3. As to metaphysics, even if we look upon it merely as an attempted
  1352. science, yet, from the nature of human reason, an indispensable one, we
  1353. find that it must contain synthetical propositions a priori. It is not
  1354. merely the duty of metaphysics to dissect, and thereby analytically to
  1355. illustrate the conceptions which we form a priori of things; but we seek
  1356. to widen the range of our a priori knowledge. For this purpose, we must
  1357. avail ourselves of such principles as add something to the original
  1358. conception--something not identical with, nor contained in it, and by
  1359. means of synthetical judgements a priori, leave far behind us the limits
  1360. of experience; for example, in the proposition, "the world must have a
  1361. beginning," and such like. Thus metaphysics, according to the proper aim
  1362. of the science, consists merely of synthetical propositions a priori.
  1363. VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason.
  1364. It is extremely advantageous to be able to bring a number of
  1365. investigations under the formula of a single problem. For in this
  1366. manner, we not only facilitate our own labour, inasmuch as we define it
  1367. clearly to ourselves, but also render it more easy for others to decide
  1368. whether we have done justice to our undertaking. The proper problem of
  1369. pure reason, then, is contained in the question: "How are synthetical
  1370. judgements a priori possible?"
  1371. That metaphysical science has hitherto remained in so vacillating a
  1372. state of uncertainty and contradiction, is only to be attributed to the
  1373. fact that this great problem, and perhaps even the difference between
  1374. analytical and synthetical judgements, did not sooner suggest itself
  1375. to philosophers. Upon the solution of this problem, or upon sufficient
  1376. proof of the impossibility of synthetical knowledge a priori, depends
  1377. the existence or downfall of the science of metaphysics. Among
  1378. philosophers, David Hume came the nearest of all to this problem; yet it
  1379. never acquired in his mind sufficient precision, nor did he regard the
  1380. question in its universality. On the contrary, he stopped short at the
  1381. synthetical proposition of the connection of an effect with its cause
  1382. (principium causalitatis), insisting that such proposition a priori
  1383. was impossible. According to his conclusions, then, all that we term
  1384. metaphysical science is a mere delusion, arising from the fancied
  1385. insight of reason into that which is in truth borrowed from experience,
  1386. and to which habit has given the appearance of necessity. Against
  1387. this assertion, destructive to all pure philosophy, he would have been
  1388. guarded, had he had our problem before his eyes in its universality. For
  1389. he would then have perceived that, according to his own argument, there
  1390. likewise could not be any pure mathematical science, which assuredly
  1391. cannot exist without synthetical propositions a priori--an absurdity
  1392. from which his good understanding must have saved him.
  1393. In the solution of the above problem is at the same time comprehended
  1394. the possibility of the use of pure reason in the foundation and
  1395. construction of all sciences which contain theoretical knowledge
  1396. a priori of objects, that is to say, the answer to the following
  1397. questions:
  1398. How is pure mathematical science possible?
  1399. How is pure natural science possible?
  1400. Respecting these sciences, as they do certainly exist, it may with
  1401. propriety be asked, how they are possible?--for that they must be
  1402. possible is shown by the fact of their really existing.* But as to
  1403. metaphysics, the miserable progress it has hitherto made, and the fact
  1404. that of no one system yet brought forward, far as regards its true
  1405. aim, can it be said that this science really exists, leaves any one at
  1406. liberty to doubt with reason the very possibility of its existence.
  1407. [*Footnote: As to the existence of pure natural science, or
  1408. physics, perhaps many may still express doubts. But we have
  1409. only to look at the different propositions which are
  1410. commonly treated of at the commencement of proper
  1411. (empirical) physical science--those, for example, relating
  1412. to the permanence of the same quantity of matter, the vis
  1413. inertiae, the equality of action and reaction, etc.--to be
  1414. soon convinced that they form a science of pure physics
  1415. (physica pura, or rationalis), which well deserves to be
  1416. separately exposed as a special science, in its whole
  1417. extent, whether that be great or confined.]
  1418. Yet, in a certain sense, this kind of knowledge must unquestionably be
  1419. looked upon as given; in other words, metaphysics must be considered
  1420. as really existing, if not as a science, nevertheless as a natural
  1421. disposition of the human mind (metaphysica naturalis). For human
  1422. reason, without any instigations imputable to the mere vanity of great
  1423. knowledge, unceasingly progresses, urged on by its own feeling of
  1424. need, towards such questions as cannot be answered by any empirical
  1425. application of reason, or principles derived therefrom; and so there
  1426. has ever really existed in every man some system of metaphysics. It will
  1427. always exist, so soon as reason awakes to the exercise of its power
  1428. of speculation. And now the question arises: "How is metaphysics, as a
  1429. natural disposition, possible?" In other words, how, from the nature
  1430. of universal human reason, do those questions arise which pure reason
  1431. proposes to itself, and which it is impelled by its own feeling of need
  1432. to answer as well as it can?
  1433. But as in all the attempts hitherto made to answer the questions which
  1434. reason is prompted by its very nature to propose to itself, for example,
  1435. whether the world had a beginning, or has existed from eternity, it has
  1436. always met with unavoidable contradictions, we must not rest satisfied
  1437. with the mere natural disposition of the mind to metaphysics, that is,
  1438. with the existence of the faculty of pure reason, whence, indeed, some
  1439. sort of metaphysical system always arises; but it must be possible to
  1440. arrive at certainty in regard to the question whether we know or do not
  1441. know the things of which metaphysics treats. We must be able to arrive
  1442. at a decision on the subjects of its questions, or on the ability or
  1443. inability of reason to form any judgement respecting them; and therefore
  1444. either to extend with confidence the bounds of our pure reason, or to
  1445. set strictly defined and safe limits to its action. This last question,
  1446. which arises out of the above universal problem, would properly run
  1447. thus: "How is metaphysics possible as a science?"
  1448. Thus, the critique of reason leads at last, naturally and necessarily,
  1449. to science; and, on the other hand, the dogmatical use of reason without
  1450. criticism leads to groundless assertions, against which others equally
  1451. specious can always be set, thus ending unavoidably in scepticism.
  1452. Besides, this science cannot be of great and formidable prolixity,
  1453. because it has not to do with objects of reason, the variety of which is
  1454. inexhaustible, but merely with Reason herself and her problems; problems
  1455. which arise out of her own bosom, and are not proposed to her by the
  1456. nature of outward things, but by her own nature. And when once Reason
  1457. has previously become able completely to understand her own power in
  1458. regard to objects which she meets with in experience, it will be easy to
  1459. determine securely the extent and limits of her attempted application to
  1460. objects beyond the confines of experience.
  1461. We may and must, therefore, regard the attempts hitherto made to
  1462. establish metaphysical science dogmatically as non-existent. For what of
  1463. analysis, that is, mere dissection of conceptions, is contained in one
  1464. or other, is not the aim of, but only a preparation for metaphysics
  1465. proper, which has for its object the extension, by means of synthesis,
  1466. of our a priori knowledge. And for this purpose, mere analysis is
  1467. of course useless, because it only shows what is contained in these
  1468. conceptions, but not how we arrive, a priori, at them; and this it is
  1469. her duty to show, in order to be able afterwards to determine their
  1470. valid use in regard to all objects of experience, to all knowledge in
  1471. general. But little self-denial, indeed, is needed to give up these
  1472. pretensions, seeing the undeniable, and in the dogmatic mode of
  1473. procedure, inevitable contradictions of Reason with herself, have long
  1474. since ruined the reputation of every system of metaphysics that has
  1475. appeared up to this time. It will require more firmness to remain
  1476. undeterred by difficulty from within, and opposition from without, from
  1477. endeavouring, by a method quite opposed to all those hitherto followed,
  1478. to further the growth and fruitfulness of a science indispensable to
  1479. human reason--a science from which every branch it has borne may be cut
  1480. away, but whose roots remain indestructible.
  1481. VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a
  1482. Critique of Pure Reason.
  1483. From all that has been said, there results the idea of a particular
  1484. science, which may be called the Critique of Pure Reason. For reason
  1485. is the faculty which furnishes us with the principles of knowledge a
  1486. priori. Hence, pure reason is the faculty which contains the principles
  1487. of cognizing anything absolutely a priori. An organon of pure reason
  1488. would be a compendium of those principles according to which alone
  1489. all pure cognitions a priori can be obtained. The completely extended
  1490. application of such an organon would afford us a system of pure reason.
  1491. As this, however, is demanding a great deal, and it is yet doubtful
  1492. whether any extension of our knowledge be here possible, or, if so,
  1493. in what cases; we can regard a science of the mere criticism of pure
  1494. reason, its sources and limits, as the propaedeutic to a system of
  1495. pure reason. Such a science must not be called a doctrine, but only a
  1496. critique of pure reason; and its use, in regard to speculation, would be
  1497. only negative, not to enlarge the bounds of, but to purify, our reason,
  1498. and to shield it against error--which alone is no little gain. I apply
  1499. the term transcendental to all knowledge which is not so much occupied
  1500. with objects as with the mode of our cognition of these objects, so
  1501. far as this mode of cognition is possible a priori. A system of such
  1502. conceptions would be called transcendental philosophy. But this, again,
  1503. is still beyond the bounds of our present essay. For as such a science
  1504. must contain a complete exposition not only of our synthetical a priori,
  1505. but of our analytical a priori knowledge, it is of too wide a range for
  1506. our present purpose, because we do not require to carry our analysis
  1507. any farther than is necessary to understand, in their full extent, the
  1508. principles of synthesis a priori, with which alone we have to do. This
  1509. investigation, which we cannot properly call a doctrine, but only a
  1510. transcendental critique, because it aims not at the enlargement, but
  1511. at the correction and guidance, of our knowledge, and is to serve as a
  1512. touchstone of the worth or worthlessness of all knowledge a priori, is
  1513. the sole object of our present essay. Such a critique is consequently,
  1514. as far as possible, a preparation for an organon; and if this new
  1515. organon should be found to fail, at least for a canon of pure reason,
  1516. according to which the complete system of the philosophy of pure reason,
  1517. whether it extend or limit the bounds of that reason, might one day
  1518. be set forth both analytically and synthetically. For that this is
  1519. possible, nay, that such a system is not of so great extent as to
  1520. preclude the hope of its ever being completed, is evident. For we have
  1521. not here to do with the nature of outward objects, which is infinite,
  1522. but solely with the mind, which judges of the nature of objects, and,
  1523. again, with the mind only in respect of its cognition a priori. And the
  1524. object of our investigations, as it is not to be sought without, but,
  1525. altogether within, ourselves, cannot remain concealed, and in all
  1526. probability is limited enough to be completely surveyed and fairly
  1527. estimated, according to its worth or worthlessness. Still less let the
  1528. reader here expect a critique of books and systems of pure reason; our
  1529. present object is exclusively a critique of the faculty of pure reason
  1530. itself. Only when we make this critique our foundation, do we possess
  1531. a pure touchstone for estimating the philosophical value of ancient
  1532. and modern writings on this subject; and without this criterion, the
  1533. incompetent historian or judge decides upon and corrects the groundless
  1534. assertions of others with his own, which have themselves just as little
  1535. foundation.
  1536. Transcendental philosophy is the idea of a science, for which the
  1537. Critique of Pure Reason must sketch the whole plan architectonically,
  1538. that is, from principles, with a full guarantee for the validity and
  1539. stability of all the parts which enter into the building. It is the
  1540. system of all the principles of pure reason. If this Critique itself
  1541. does not assume the title of transcendental philosophy, it is only
  1542. because, to be a complete system, it ought to contain a full analysis of
  1543. all human knowledge a priori. Our critique must, indeed, lay before us a
  1544. complete enumeration of all the radical conceptions which constitute the
  1545. said pure knowledge. But from the complete analysis of these conceptions
  1546. themselves, as also from a complete investigation of those derived from
  1547. them, it abstains with reason; partly because it would be deviating from
  1548. the end in view to occupy itself with this analysis, since this process
  1549. is not attended with the difficulty and insecurity to be found in the
  1550. synthesis, to which our critique is entirely devoted, and partly because
  1551. it would be inconsistent with the unity of our plan to burden this
  1552. essay with the vindication of the completeness of such an analysis and
  1553. deduction, with which, after all, we have at present nothing to do. This
  1554. completeness of the analysis of these radical conceptions, as well as
  1555. of the deduction from the conceptions a priori which may be given by the
  1556. analysis, we can, however, easily attain, provided only that we are
  1557. in possession of all these radical conceptions, which are to serve as
  1558. principles of the synthesis, and that in respect of this main purpose
  1559. nothing is wanting.
  1560. To the Critique of Pure Reason, therefore, belongs all that constitutes
  1561. transcendental philosophy; and it is the complete idea of transcendental
  1562. philosophy, but still not the science itself; because it only proceeds
  1563. so far with the analysis as is necessary to the power of judging
  1564. completely of our synthetical knowledge a priori.
  1565. The principal thing we must attend to, in the division of the parts of
  1566. a science like this, is that no conceptions must enter it which contain
  1567. aught empirical; in other words, that the knowledge a priori must be
  1568. completely pure. Hence, although the highest principles and fundamental
  1569. conceptions of morality are certainly cognitions a priori, yet they do
  1570. not belong to transcendental philosophy; because, though they certainly
  1571. do not lay the conceptions of pain, pleasure, desires, inclinations,
  1572. etc. (which are all of empirical origin), at the foundation of its
  1573. precepts, yet still into the conception of duty--as an obstacle to
  1574. be overcome, or as an incitement which should not be made into a
  1575. motive--these empirical conceptions must necessarily enter, in the
  1576. construction of a system of pure morality. Transcendental philosophy is
  1577. consequently a philosophy of the pure and merely speculative reason.
  1578. For all that is practical, so far as it contains motives, relates to
  1579. feelings, and these belong to empirical sources of cognition.
  1580. If we wish to divide this science from the universal point of view of
  1581. a science in general, it ought to comprehend, first, a Doctrine of the
  1582. Elements, and, secondly, a Doctrine of the Method of pure reason. Each
  1583. of these main divisions will have its subdivisions, the separate reasons
  1584. for which we cannot here particularize. Only so much seems necessary, by
  1585. way of introduction of premonition, that there are two sources of human
  1586. knowledge (which probably spring from a common, but to us unknown root),
  1587. namely, sense and understanding. By the former, objects are given to
  1588. us; by the latter, thought. So far as the faculty of sense may contain
  1589. representations a priori, which form the conditions under which objects
  1590. are given, in so far it belongs to transcendental philosophy. The
  1591. transcendental doctrine of sense must form the first part of our science
  1592. of elements, because the conditions under which alone the objects
  1593. of human knowledge are given must precede those under which they are
  1594. thought.
  1595. I. TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS.
  1596. FIRST PART. TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC.
  1597. SS I. Introductory.
  1598. In whatsoever mode, or by whatsoever means, our knowledge may relate
  1599. to objects, it is at least quite clear that the only manner in which it
  1600. immediately relates to them is by means of an intuition. To this as the
  1601. indispensable groundwork, all thought points. But an intuition can take
  1602. place only in so far as the object is given to us. This, again, is only
  1603. possible, to man at least, on condition that the object affect the
  1604. mind in a certain manner. The capacity for receiving representations
  1605. (receptivity) through the mode in which we are affected by objects,
  1606. objects, is called sensibility. By means of sensibility, therefore,
  1607. objects are given to us, and it alone furnishes us with intuitions; by
  1608. the understanding they are thought, and from it arise conceptions. But
  1609. an thought must directly, or indirectly, by means of certain signs,
  1610. relate ultimately to intuitions; consequently, with us, to sensibility,
  1611. because in no other way can an object be given to us.
  1612. The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far as
  1613. we are affected by the said object, is sensation. That sort of intuition
  1614. which relates to an object by means of sensation is called an empirical
  1615. intuition. The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is called
  1616. phenomenon. That which in the phenomenon corresponds to the sensation,
  1617. I term its matter; but that which effects that the content of the
  1618. phenomenon can be arranged under certain relations, I call its form. But
  1619. that in which our sensations are merely arranged, and by which they are
  1620. susceptible of assuming a certain form, cannot be itself sensation. It
  1621. is, then, the matter of all phenomena that is given to us a posteriori;
  1622. the form must lie ready a priori for them in the mind, and consequently
  1623. can be regarded separately from all sensation.
  1624. I call all representations pure, in the transcendental meaning of
  1625. the word, wherein nothing is met with that belongs to sensation. And
  1626. accordingly we find existing in the mind a priori, the pure form of
  1627. sensuous intuitions in general, in which all the manifold content of the
  1628. phenomenal world is arranged and viewed under certain relations. This
  1629. pure form of sensibility I shall call pure intuition. Thus, if I take
  1630. away from our representation of a body all that the understanding thinks
  1631. as belonging to it, as substance, force, divisibility, etc., and also
  1632. whatever belongs to sensation, as impenetrability, hardness, colour,
  1633. etc.; yet there is still something left us from this empirical
  1634. intuition, namely, extension and shape. These belong to pure intuition,
  1635. which exists a priori in the mind, as a mere form of sensibility, and
  1636. without any real object of the senses or any sensation.
  1637. The science of all the principles of sensibility a priori, I call
  1638. transcendental aesthetic.* There must, then, be such a science
  1639. forming the first part of the transcendental doctrine of elements, in
  1640. contradistinction to that part which contains the principles of pure
  1641. thought, and which is called transcendental logic.
  1642. [Footnote: The Germans are the only people who at present
  1643. use this word to indicate what others call the critique of
  1644. taste. At the foundation of this term lies the disappointed
  1645. hope, which the eminent analyst, Baumgarten, conceived, of
  1646. subjecting the criticism of the beautiful to principles of
  1647. reason, and so of elevating its rules into a science. But
  1648. his endeavours were vain. For the said rules or criteria
  1649. are, in respect to their chief sources, merely empirical,
  1650. consequently never can serve as determinate laws a priori,
  1651. by which our judgement in matters of taste is to be
  1652. directed. It is rather our judgement which forms the proper
  1653. test as to the correctness of the principles. On this
  1654. account it is advisable to give up the use of the term as
  1655. designating the critique of taste, and to apply it solely to
  1656. that doctrine, which is true science--the science of the
  1657. laws of sensibility--and thus come nearer to the language
  1658. and the sense of the ancients in their well-known division
  1659. of the objects of cognition into aiotheta kai noeta, or to
  1660. share it with speculative philosophy, and employ it partly
  1661. in a transcendental, partly in a psychological
  1662. signification.]
  1663. In the science of transcendental aesthetic accordingly, we shall first
  1664. isolate sensibility or the sensuous faculty, by separating from it all
  1665. that is annexed to its perceptions by the conceptions of understanding,
  1666. so that nothing be left but empirical intuition. In the next place we
  1667. shall take away from this intuition all that belongs to sensation,
  1668. so that nothing may remain but pure intuition, and the mere form of
  1669. phenomena, which is all that the sensibility can afford a priori. From
  1670. this investigation it will be found that there are two pure forms of
  1671. sensuous intuition, as principles of knowledge a priori, namely, space
  1672. and time. To the consideration of these we shall now proceed.
  1673. SECTION I. Of Space.
  1674. SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.
  1675. By means of the external sense (a property of the mind), we represent
  1676. to ourselves objects as without us, and these all in space. Herein alone
  1677. are their shape, dimensions, and relations to each other determined
  1678. or determinable. The internal sense, by means of which the mind
  1679. contemplates itself or its internal state, gives, indeed, no intuition
  1680. of the soul as an object; yet there is nevertheless a determinate form,
  1681. under which alone the contemplation of our internal state is possible,
  1682. so that all which relates to the inward determinations of the mind is
  1683. represented in relations of time. Of time we cannot have any external
  1684. intuition, any more than we can have an internal intuition of space.
  1685. What then are time and space? Are they real existences? Or, are they
  1686. merely relations or determinations of things, such, however, as would
  1687. equally belong to these things in themselves, though they should never
  1688. become objects of intuition; or, are they such as belong only to the
  1689. form of intuition, and consequently to the subjective constitution of
  1690. the mind, without which these predicates of time and space could not be
  1691. attached to any object? In order to become informed on these points,
  1692. we shall first give an exposition of the conception of space. By
  1693. exposition, I mean the clear, though not detailed, representation of
  1694. that which belongs to a conception; and an exposition is metaphysical
  1695. when it contains that which represents the conception as given a priori.
  1696. 1. Space is not a conception which has been derived from outward
  1697. experiences. For, in order that certain sensations may relate to
  1698. something without me (that is, to something which occupies a different
  1699. part of space from that in which I am); in like manner, in order that
  1700. I may represent them not merely as without, of, and near to each other,
  1701. but also in separate places, the representation of space must already
  1702. exist as a foundation. Consequently, the representation of space cannot
  1703. be borrowed from the relations of external phenomena through experience;
  1704. but, on the contrary, this external experience is itself only possible
  1705. through the said antecedent representation.
  1706. 2. Space then is a necessary representation a priori, which serves for
  1707. the foundation of all external intuitions. We never can imagine or make
  1708. a representation to ourselves of the non-existence of space, though
  1709. we may easily enough think that no objects are found in it. It must,
  1710. therefore, be considered as the condition of the possibility of
  1711. phenomena, and by no means as a determination dependent on them, and
  1712. is a representation a priori, which necessarily supplies the basis for
  1713. external phenomena.
  1714. 3. Space is no discursive, or as we say, general conception of the
  1715. relations of things, but a pure intuition. For, in the first place, we
  1716. can only represent to ourselves one space, and, when we talk of divers
  1717. spaces, we mean only parts of one and the same space. Moreover, these
  1718. parts cannot antecede this one all-embracing space, as the component
  1719. parts from which the aggregate can be made up, but can be cogitated only
  1720. as existing in it. Space is essentially one, and multiplicity in it,
  1721. consequently the general notion of spaces, of this or that space,
  1722. depends solely upon limitations. Hence it follows that an a priori
  1723. intuition (which is not empirical) lies at the root of all our
  1724. conceptions of space. Thus, moreover, the principles of geometry--for
  1725. example, that "in a triangle, two sides together are greater than the
  1726. third," are never deduced from general conceptions of line and triangle,
  1727. but from intuition, and this a priori, with apodeictic certainty.
  1728. 4. Space is represented as an infinite given quantity. Now every
  1729. conception must indeed be considered as a representation which
  1730. is contained in an infinite multitude of different possible
  1731. representations, which, therefore, comprises these under itself; but
  1732. no conception, as such, can be so conceived, as if it contained within
  1733. itself an infinite multitude of representations. Nevertheless, space
  1734. is so conceived of, for all parts of space are equally capable of being
  1735. produced to infinity. Consequently, the original representation of space
  1736. is an intuition a priori, and not a conception.
  1737. SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space.
  1738. By a transcendental exposition, I mean the explanation of a conception,
  1739. as a principle, whence can be discerned the possibility of other
  1740. synthetical a priori cognitions. For this purpose, it is requisite,
  1741. firstly, that such cognitions do really flow from the given conception;
  1742. and, secondly, that the said cognitions are only possible under the
  1743. presupposition of a given mode of explaining this conception.
  1744. Geometry is a science which determines the properties of space
  1745. synthetically, and yet a priori. What, then, must be our representation
  1746. of space, in order that such a cognition of it may be possible? It must
  1747. be originally intuition, for from a mere conception, no propositions can
  1748. be deduced which go out beyond the conception, and yet this happens in
  1749. geometry. (Introd. V.) But this intuition must be found in the mind a
  1750. priori, that is, before any perception of objects, consequently must be
  1751. pure, not empirical, intuition. For geometrical principles are always
  1752. apodeictic, that is, united with the consciousness of their necessity,
  1753. as: "Space has only three dimensions." But propositions of this kind
  1754. cannot be empirical judgements, nor conclusions from them. (Introd. II.)
  1755. Now, how can an external intuition anterior to objects themselves, and
  1756. in which our conception of objects can be determined a priori, exist
  1757. in the human mind? Obviously not otherwise than in so far as it has its
  1758. seat in the subject only, as the formal capacity of the subject's being
  1759. affected by objects, and thereby of obtaining immediate representation,
  1760. that is, intuition; consequently, only as the form of the external sense
  1761. in general.
  1762. Thus it is only by means of our explanation that the possibility of
  1763. geometry, as a synthetical science a priori, becomes comprehensible.
  1764. Every mode of explanation which does not show us this possibility,
  1765. although in appearance it may be similar to ours, can with the utmost
  1766. certainty be distinguished from it by these marks.
  1767. SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions.
  1768. (a) Space does not represent any property of objects as things in
  1769. themselves, nor does it represent them in their relations to each other;
  1770. in other words, space does not represent to us any determination of
  1771. objects such as attaches to the objects themselves, and would remain,
  1772. even though all subjective conditions of the intuition were abstracted.
  1773. For neither absolute nor relative determinations of objects can be
  1774. intuited prior to the existence of the things to which they belong, and
  1775. therefore not a priori.
  1776. (b) Space is nothing else than the form of all phenomena of the external
  1777. sense, that is, the subjective condition of the sensibility, under which
  1778. alone external intuition is possible. Now, because the receptivity or
  1779. capacity of the subject to be affected by objects necessarily antecedes
  1780. all intuitions of these objects, it is easily understood how the form
  1781. of all phenomena can be given in the mind previous to all actual
  1782. perceptions, therefore a priori, and how it, as a pure intuition, in
  1783. which all objects must be determined, can contain principles of the
  1784. relations of these objects prior to all experience.
  1785. It is therefore from the human point of view only that we can speak
  1786. of space, extended objects, etc. If we depart from the subjective
  1787. condition, under which alone we can obtain external intuition, or,
  1788. in other words, by means of which we are affected by objects, the
  1789. representation of space has no meaning whatsoever. This predicate is
  1790. only applicable to things in so far as they appear to us, that is, are
  1791. objects of sensibility. The constant form of this receptivity, which
  1792. we call sensibility, is a necessary condition of all relations in which
  1793. objects can be intuited as existing without us, and when abstraction of
  1794. these objects is made, is a pure intuition, to which we give the name
  1795. of space. It is clear that we cannot make the special conditions of
  1796. sensibility into conditions of the possibility of things, but only of
  1797. the possibility of their existence as far as they are phenomena. And
  1798. so we may correctly say that space contains all which can appear to us
  1799. externally, but not all things considered as things in themselves,
  1800. be they intuited or not, or by whatsoever subject one will. As to the
  1801. intuitions of other thinking beings, we cannot judge whether they are or
  1802. are not bound by the same conditions which limit our own intuition,
  1803. and which for us are universally valid. If we join the limitation of
  1804. a judgement to the conception of the subject, then the judgement will
  1805. possess unconditioned validity. For example, the proposition, "All
  1806. objects are beside each other in space," is valid only under the
  1807. limitation that these things are taken as objects of our sensuous
  1808. intuition. But if I join the condition to the conception and say, "All
  1809. things, as external phenomena, are beside each other in space," then the
  1810. rule is valid universally, and without any limitation. Our expositions,
  1811. consequently, teach the reality (i.e., the objective validity) of space
  1812. in regard of all which can be presented to us externally as object, and
  1813. at the same time also the ideality of space in regard to objects when
  1814. they are considered by means of reason as things in themselves, that is,
  1815. without reference to the constitution of our sensibility. We maintain,
  1816. therefore, the empirical reality of space in regard to all possible
  1817. external experience, although we must admit its transcendental ideality;
  1818. in other words, that it is nothing, so soon as we withdraw the condition
  1819. upon which the possibility of all experience depends and look upon space
  1820. as something that belongs to things in themselves.
  1821. But, with the exception of space, there is no representation, subjective
  1822. and referring to something external to us, which could be called
  1823. objective a priori. For there are no other subjective representations
  1824. from which we can deduce synthetical propositions a priori, as we can
  1825. from the intuition of space. (See SS 3.) Therefore, to speak accurately,
  1826. no ideality whatever belongs to these, although they agree in this
  1827. respect with the representation of space, that they belong merely to the
  1828. subjective nature of the mode of sensuous perception; such a mode, for
  1829. example, as that of sight, of hearing, and of feeling, by means of the
  1830. sensations of colour, sound, and heat, but which, because they are
  1831. only sensations and not intuitions, do not of themselves give us
  1832. the cognition of any object, least of all, an a priori cognition. My
  1833. purpose, in the above remark, is merely this: to guard any one
  1834. against illustrating the asserted ideality of space by examples quite
  1835. insufficient, for example, by colour, taste, etc.; for these must be
  1836. contemplated not as properties of things, but only as changes in the
  1837. subject, changes which may be different in different men. For, in such
  1838. a case, that which is originally a mere phenomenon, a rose, for example,
  1839. is taken by the empirical understanding for a thing in itself, though to
  1840. every different eye, in respect of its colour, it may appear different.
  1841. On the contrary, the transcendental conception of phenomena in space is
  1842. a critical admonition, that, in general, nothing which is intuited in
  1843. space is a thing in itself, and that space is not a form which belongs
  1844. as a property to things; but that objects are quite unknown to us in
  1845. themselves, and what we call outward objects, are nothing else but mere
  1846. representations of our sensibility, whose form is space, but whose
  1847. real correlate, the thing in itself, is not known by means of these
  1848. representations, nor ever can be, but respecting which, in experience,
  1849. no inquiry is ever made.
  1850. SECTION II. Of Time.
  1851. SS 5. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.
  1852. 1. Time is not an empirical conception. For neither coexistence nor
  1853. succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did
  1854. not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition we could
  1855. not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the
  1856. same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in
  1857. succession.
  1858. 2. Time is a necessary representation, lying at the foundation of all
  1859. our intuitions. With regard to phenomena in general, we cannot think
  1860. away time from them, and represent them to ourselves as out of and
  1861. unconnected with time, but we can quite well represent to ourselves time
  1862. void of phenomena. Time is therefore given a priori. In it alone is all
  1863. reality of phenomena possible. These may all be annihilated in thought,
  1864. but time itself, as the universal condition of their possibility, cannot
  1865. be so annulled.
  1866. 3. On this necessity a priori is also founded the possibility of
  1867. apodeictic principles of the relations of time, or axioms of time in
  1868. general, such as: "Time has only one dimension," "Different times are
  1869. not coexistent but successive" (as different spaces are not successive
  1870. but coexistent). These principles cannot be derived from experience, for
  1871. it would give neither strict universality, nor apodeictic certainty. We
  1872. should only be able to say, "so common experience teaches us," but not
  1873. "it must be so." They are valid as rules, through which, in general,
  1874. experience is possible; and they instruct us respecting experience, and
  1875. not by means of it.
  1876. 4. Time is not a discursive, or as it is called, general conception, but
  1877. a pure form of the sensuous intuition. Different times are merely parts
  1878. of one and the same time. But the representation which can only be
  1879. given by a single object is an intuition. Besides, the proposition that
  1880. different times cannot be coexistent could not be derived from a general
  1881. conception. For this proposition is synthetical, and therefore cannot
  1882. spring out of conceptions alone. It is therefore contained immediately
  1883. in the intuition and representation of time.
  1884. 5. The infinity of time signifies nothing more than that every
  1885. determined quantity of time is possible only through limitations of one
  1886. time lying at the foundation. Consequently, the original representation,
  1887. time, must be given as unlimited. But as the determinate representation
  1888. of the parts of time and of every quantity of an object can only be
  1889. obtained by limitation, the complete representation of time must not
  1890. be furnished by means of conceptions, for these contain only partial
  1891. representations. Conceptions, on the contrary, must have immediate
  1892. intuition for their basis.
  1893. SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time.
  1894. I may here refer to what is said above (SS 5, 3), where, for or sake of
  1895. brevity, I have placed under the head of metaphysical exposition, that
  1896. which is properly transcendental. Here I shall add that the conception
  1897. of change, and with it the conception of motion, as change of place, is
  1898. possible only through and in the representation of time; that if this
  1899. representation were not an intuition (internal) a priori, no conception,
  1900. of whatever kind, could render comprehensible the possibility of change,
  1901. in other words, of a conjunction of contradictorily opposed predicates
  1902. in one and the same object, for example, the presence of a thing in a
  1903. place and the non-presence of the same thing in the same place. It
  1904. is only in time that it is possible to meet with two contradictorily
  1905. opposed determinations in one thing, that is, after each other. Thus
  1906. our conception of time explains the possibility of so much synthetical
  1907. knowledge a priori, as is exhibited in the general doctrine of motion,
  1908. which is not a little fruitful.
  1909. SS 7. Conclusions from the above Conceptions.
  1910. (a) Time is not something which subsists of itself, or which inheres
  1911. in things as an objective determination, and therefore remains, when
  1912. abstraction is made of the subjective conditions of the intuition of
  1913. things. For in the former case, it would be something real, yet without
  1914. presenting to any power of perception any real object. In the latter
  1915. case, as an order or determination inherent in things themselves, it
  1916. could not be antecedent to things, as their condition, nor discerned or
  1917. intuited by means of synthetical propositions a priori. But all this is
  1918. quite possible when we regard time as merely the subjective condition
  1919. under which all our intuitions take place. For in that case, this form
  1920. of the inward intuition can be represented prior to the objects, and
  1921. consequently a priori.
  1922. (b) Time is nothing else than the form of the internal sense, that is,
  1923. of the intuitions of self and of our internal state. For time cannot be
  1924. any determination of outward phenomena. It has to do neither with
  1925. shape nor position; on the contrary, it determines the relation of
  1926. representations in our internal state. And precisely because this
  1927. internal intuition presents to us no shape or form, we endeavour to
  1928. supply this want by analogies, and represent the course of time by a
  1929. line progressing to infinity, the content of which constitutes a series
  1930. which is only of one dimension; and we conclude from the properties of
  1931. this line as to all the properties of time, with this single exception,
  1932. that the parts of the line are coexistent, whilst those of time are
  1933. successive. From this it is clear also that the representation of time
  1934. is itself an intuition, because all its relations can be expressed in an
  1935. external intuition.
  1936. (c) Time is the formal condition a priori of all phenomena whatsoever.
  1937. Space, as the pure form of external intuition, is limited as a condition
  1938. a priori to external phenomena alone. On the other hand, because all
  1939. representations, whether they have or have not external things for their
  1940. objects, still in themselves, as determinations of the mind, belong to
  1941. our internal state; and because this internal state is subject to the
  1942. formal condition of the internal intuition, that is, to time--time is a
  1943. condition a priori of all phenomena whatsoever--the immediate condition
  1944. of all internal, and thereby the mediate condition of all external
  1945. phenomena. If I can say a priori, "All outward phenomena are in space,
  1946. and determined a priori according to the relations of space," I can
  1947. also, from the principle of the internal sense, affirm universally, "All
  1948. phenomena in general, that is, all objects of the senses, are in time
  1949. and stand necessarily in relations of time."
  1950. If we abstract our internal intuition of ourselves and all external
  1951. intuitions, possible only by virtue of this internal intuition and
  1952. presented to us by our faculty of representation, and consequently take
  1953. objects as they are in themselves, then time is nothing. It is only
  1954. of objective validity in regard to phenomena, because these are things
  1955. which we regard as objects of our senses. It no longer objective we,
  1956. make abstraction of the sensuousness of our intuition, in other words,
  1957. of that mode of representation which is peculiar to us, and speak of
  1958. things in general. Time is therefore merely a subjective condition of
  1959. our (human) intuition (which is always sensuous, that is, so far as we
  1960. are affected by objects), and in itself, independently of the mind
  1961. or subject, is nothing. Nevertheless, in respect of all phenomena,
  1962. consequently of all things which come within the sphere of our
  1963. experience, it is necessarily objective. We cannot say, "All things are
  1964. in time," because in this conception of things in general, we abstract
  1965. and make no mention of any sort of intuition of things. But this is
  1966. the proper condition under which time belongs to our representation
  1967. of objects. If we add the condition to the conception, and say, "All
  1968. things, as phenomena, that is, objects of sensuous intuition, are
  1969. in time," then the proposition has its sound objective validity and
  1970. universality a priori.
  1971. What we have now set forth teaches, therefore, the empirical reality of
  1972. time; that is, its objective validity in reference to all objects which
  1973. can ever be presented to our senses. And as our intuition is always
  1974. sensuous, no object ever can be presented to us in experience, which
  1975. does not come under the conditions of time. On the other hand, we deny
  1976. to time all claim to absolute reality; that is, we deny that it, without
  1977. having regard to the form of our sensuous intuition, absolutely inheres
  1978. in things as a condition or property. Such properties as belong to
  1979. objects as things in themselves never can be presented to us through
  1980. the medium of the senses. Herein consists, therefore, the transcendental
  1981. ideality of time, according to which, if we abstract the subjective
  1982. conditions of sensuous intuition, it is nothing, and cannot be
  1983. reckoned as subsisting or inhering in objects as things in themselves,
  1984. independently of its relation to our intuition. This ideality, like that
  1985. of space, is not to be proved or illustrated by fallacious analogies
  1986. with sensations, for this reason--that in such arguments or
  1987. illustrations, we make the presupposition that the phenomenon, in which
  1988. such and such predicates inhere, has objective reality, while in this
  1989. case we can only find such an objective reality as is itself empirical,
  1990. that is, regards the object as a mere phenomenon. In reference to this
  1991. subject, see the remark in Section I (SS 4)
  1992. SS 8. Elucidation.
  1993. Against this theory, which grants empirical reality to time, but denies
  1994. to it absolute and transcendental reality, I have heard from intelligent
  1995. men an objection so unanimously urged that I conclude that it must
  1996. naturally present itself to every reader to whom these considerations
  1997. are novel. It runs thus: "Changes are real" (this the continual change
  1998. in our own representations demonstrates, even though the existence of
  1999. all external phenomena, together with their changes, is denied). Now,
  2000. changes are only possible in time, and therefore time must be something
  2001. real. But there is no difficulty in answering this. I grant the whole
  2002. argument. Time, no doubt, is something real, that is, it is the real
  2003. form of our internal intuition. It therefore has subjective reality,
  2004. in reference to our internal experience, that is, I have really
  2005. the representation of time and of my determinations therein. Time,
  2006. therefore, is not to be regarded as an object, but as the mode of
  2007. representation of myself as an object. But if I could intuite myself,
  2008. or be intuited by another being, without this condition of sensibility,
  2009. then those very determinations which we now represent to ourselves as
  2010. changes, would present to us a knowledge in which the representation
  2011. of time, and consequently of change, would not appear. The empirical
  2012. reality of time, therefore, remains, as the condition of all our
  2013. experience. But absolute reality, according to what has been said above,
  2014. cannot be granted it. Time is nothing but the form of our internal
  2015. intuition.* If we take away from it the special condition of our
  2016. sensibility, the conception of time also vanishes; and it inheres not
  2017. in the objects themselves, but solely in the subject (or mind) which
  2018. intuites them.
  2019. [*Footnote: I can indeed say "my representations follow one
  2020. another, or are successive"; but this means only that we are
  2021. conscious of them as in a succession, that is, according to
  2022. the form of the internal sense. Time, therefore, is not a
  2023. thing in itself, nor is it any objective determination
  2024. pertaining to, or inherent in things.]
  2025. But the reason why this objection is so unanimously brought against
  2026. our doctrine of time, and that too by disputants who cannot start any
  2027. intelligible arguments against the doctrine of the ideality of space,
  2028. is this--they have no hope of demonstrating apodeictically the absolute
  2029. reality of space, because the doctrine of idealism is against them,
  2030. according to which the reality of external objects is not capable of
  2031. any strict proof. On the other hand, the reality of the object of
  2032. our internal sense (that is, myself and my internal state) is clear
  2033. immediately through consciousness. The former--external objects in
  2034. space--might be a mere delusion, but the latter--the object of my
  2035. internal perception--is undeniably real. They do not, however, reflect
  2036. that both, without question of their reality as representations, belong
  2037. only to the genus phenomenon, which has always two aspects, the one, the
  2038. object considered as a thing in itself, without regard to the mode
  2039. of intuiting it, and the nature of which remains for this very reason
  2040. problematical, the other, the form of our intuition of the object,
  2041. which must be sought not in the object as a thing in itself, but in
  2042. the subject to which it appears--which form of intuition nevertheless
  2043. belongs really and necessarily to the phenomenal object.
  2044. Time and space are, therefore, two sources of knowledge, from which, a
  2045. priori, various synthetical cognitions can be drawn. Of this we find
  2046. a striking example in the cognitions of space and its relations, which
  2047. form the foundation of pure mathematics. They are the two pure forms
  2048. of all intuitions, and thereby make synthetical propositions a priori
  2049. possible. But these sources of knowledge being merely conditions of our
  2050. sensibility, do therefore, and as such, strictly determine their own
  2051. range and purpose, in that they do not and cannot present objects as
  2052. things in themselves, but are applicable to them solely in so far as
  2053. they are considered as sensuous phenomena. The sphere of phenomena is
  2054. the only sphere of their validity, and if we venture out of this, no
  2055. further objective use can be made of them. For the rest, this formal
  2056. reality of time and space leaves the validity of our empirical knowledge
  2057. unshaken; for our certainty in that respect is equally firm, whether
  2058. these forms necessarily inhere in the things themselves, or only in our
  2059. intuitions of them. On the other hand, those who maintain the absolute
  2060. reality of time and space, whether as essentially subsisting, or only
  2061. inhering, as modifications, in things, must find themselves at utter
  2062. variance with the principles of experience itself. For, if they decide
  2063. for the first view, and make space and time into substances, this being
  2064. the side taken by mathematical natural philosophers, they must admit
  2065. two self-subsisting nonentities, infinite and eternal, which exist (yet
  2066. without there being anything real) for the purpose of containing in
  2067. themselves everything that is real. If they adopt the second view of
  2068. inherence, which is preferred by some metaphysical natural philosophers,
  2069. and regard space and time as relations (contiguity in space or
  2070. succession in time), abstracted from experience, though represented
  2071. confusedly in this state of separation, they find themselves in that
  2072. case necessitated to deny the validity of mathematical doctrines a
  2073. priori in reference to real things (for example, in space)--at all
  2074. events their apodeictic certainty. For such certainty cannot be found in
  2075. an a posteriori proposition; and the conceptions a priori of space and
  2076. time are, according to this opinion, mere creations of the imagination,
  2077. having their source really in experience, inasmuch as, out of relations
  2078. abstracted from experience, imagination has made up something which
  2079. contains, indeed, general statements of these relations, yet of which
  2080. no application can be made without the restrictions attached thereto by
  2081. nature. The former of these parties gains this advantage, that they
  2082. keep the sphere of phenomena free for mathematical science. On the other
  2083. hand, these very conditions (space and time) embarrass them greatly,
  2084. when the understanding endeavours to pass the limits of that sphere. The
  2085. latter has, indeed, this advantage, that the representations of space
  2086. and time do not come in their way when they wish to judge of objects,
  2087. not as phenomena, but merely in their relation to the understanding.
  2088. Devoid, however, of a true and objectively valid a priori intuition,
  2089. they can neither furnish any basis for the possibility of mathematical
  2090. cognitions a priori, nor bring the propositions of experience into
  2091. necessary accordance with those of mathematics. In our theory of
  2092. the true nature of these two original forms of the sensibility, both
  2093. difficulties are surmounted.
  2094. In conclusion, that transcendental aesthetic cannot contain any more
  2095. than these two elements--space and time, is sufficiently obvious from
  2096. the fact that all other conceptions appertaining to sensibility,
  2097. even that of motion, which unites in itself both elements, presuppose
  2098. something empirical. Motion, for example, presupposes the perception
  2099. of something movable. But space considered in itself contains nothing
  2100. movable, consequently motion must be something which is found in space
  2101. only through experience--in other words, an empirical datum. In like
  2102. manner, transcendental aesthetic cannot number the conception of change
  2103. among its data a priori; for time itself does not change, but only
  2104. something which is in time. To acquire the conception of change,
  2105. therefore, the perception of some existing object and of the succession
  2106. of its determinations, in one word, experience, is necessary.
  2107. SS 9. General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic.
  2108. I. In order to prevent any misunderstanding, it will be requisite,
  2109. in the first place, to recapitulate, as clearly as possible, what
  2110. our opinion is with respect to the fundamental nature of our sensuous
  2111. cognition in general. We have intended, then, to say that all our
  2112. intuition is nothing but the representation of phenomena; that
  2113. the things which we intuite, are not in themselves the same as our
  2114. representations of them in intuition, nor are their relations in
  2115. themselves so constituted as they appear to us; and that if we take away
  2116. the subject, or even only the subjective constitution of our senses in
  2117. general, then not only the nature and relations of objects in space and
  2118. time, but even space and time themselves disappear; and that these, as
  2119. phenomena, cannot exist in themselves, but only in us. What may be
  2120. the nature of objects considered as things in themselves and without
  2121. reference to the receptivity of our sensibility is quite unknown to us.
  2122. We know nothing more than our mode of perceiving them, which is peculiar
  2123. to us, and which, though not of necessity pertaining to every animated
  2124. being, is so to the whole human race. With this alone we have to do.
  2125. Space and time are the pure forms thereof; sensation the matter. The
  2126. former alone can we cognize a priori, that is, antecedent to all actual
  2127. perception; and for this reason such cognition is called pure intuition.
  2128. The latter is that in our cognition which is called cognition a
  2129. posteriori, that is, empirical intuition. The former appertain
  2130. absolutely and necessarily to our sensibility, of whatsoever kind our
  2131. sensations may be; the latter may be of very diversified character.
  2132. Supposing that we should carry our empirical intuition even to the very
  2133. highest degree of clearness, we should not thereby advance one step
  2134. nearer to a knowledge of the constitution of objects as things in
  2135. themselves. For we could only, at best, arrive at a complete cognition
  2136. of our own mode of intuition, that is of our sensibility, and this
  2137. always under the conditions originally attaching to the subject, namely,
  2138. the conditions of space and time; while the question: "What are objects
  2139. considered as things in themselves?" remains unanswerable even after the
  2140. most thorough examination of the phenomenal world.
  2141. To say, then, that all our sensibility is nothing but the confused
  2142. representation of things containing exclusively that which belongs
  2143. to them as things in themselves, and this under an accumulation of
  2144. characteristic marks and partial representations which we cannot
  2145. distinguish in consciousness, is a falsification of the conception
  2146. of sensibility and phenomenization, which renders our whole doctrine
  2147. thereof empty and useless. The difference between a confused and a clear
  2148. representation is merely logical and has nothing to do with content.
  2149. No doubt the conception of right, as employed by a sound understanding,
  2150. contains all that the most subtle investigation could unfold from
  2151. it, although, in the ordinary practical use of the word, we are not
  2152. conscious of the manifold representations comprised in the conception.
  2153. But we cannot for this reason assert that the ordinary conception is a
  2154. sensuous one, containing a mere phenomenon, for right cannot appear as
  2155. a phenomenon; but the conception of it lies in the understanding, and
  2156. represents a property (the moral property) of actions, which belongs to
  2157. them in themselves. On the other hand, the representation in intuition
  2158. of a body contains nothing which could belong to an object considered as
  2159. a thing in itself, but merely the phenomenon or appearance of something,
  2160. and the mode in which we are affected by that appearance; and this
  2161. receptivity of our faculty of cognition is called sensibility, and
  2162. remains toto caelo different from the cognition of an object in itself,
  2163. even though we should examine the content of the phenomenon to the very
  2164. bottom.
  2165. It must be admitted that the Leibnitz-Wolfian philosophy has assigned an
  2166. entirely erroneous point of view to all investigations into the nature
  2167. and origin of our cognitions, inasmuch as it regards the distinction
  2168. between the sensuous and the intellectual as merely logical, whereas
  2169. it is plainly transcendental, and concerns not merely the clearness
  2170. or obscurity, but the content and origin of both. For the faculty of
  2171. sensibility not only does not present us with an indistinct and confused
  2172. cognition of objects as things in themselves, but, in fact, gives us no
  2173. knowledge of these at all. On the contrary, so soon as we abstract in
  2174. thought our own subjective nature, the object represented, with the
  2175. properties ascribed to it by sensuous intuition, entirely disappears,
  2176. because it was only this subjective nature that determined the form of
  2177. the object as a phenomenon.
  2178. In phenomena, we commonly, indeed, distinguish that which essentially
  2179. belongs to the intuition of them, and is valid for the sensuous faculty
  2180. of every human being, from that which belongs to the same intuition
  2181. accidentally, as valid not for the sensuous faculty in general, but for
  2182. a particular state or organization of this or that sense. Accordingly,
  2183. we are accustomed to say that the former is a cognition which represents
  2184. the object itself, whilst the latter presents only a particular
  2185. appearance or phenomenon thereof. This distinction, however, is
  2186. only empirical. If we stop here (as is usual), and do not regard the
  2187. empirical intuition as itself a mere phenomenon (as we ought to do), in
  2188. which nothing that can appertain to a thing in itself is to be found,
  2189. our transcendental distinction is lost, and we believe that we cognize
  2190. objects as things in themselves, although in the whole range of the
  2191. sensuous world, investigate the nature of its objects as profoundly
  2192. as we may, we have to do with nothing but phenomena. Thus, we call the
  2193. rainbow a mere appearance of phenomenon in a sunny shower, and the
  2194. rain, the reality or thing in itself; and this is right enough, if we
  2195. understand the latter conception in a merely physical sense, that is,
  2196. as that which in universal experience, and under whatever conditions of
  2197. sensuous perception, is known in intuition to be so and so determined,
  2198. and not otherwise. But if we consider this empirical datum generally,
  2199. and inquire, without reference to its accordance with all our senses,
  2200. whether there can be discovered in it aught which represents an object
  2201. as a thing in itself (the raindrops of course are not such, for they
  2202. are, as phenomena, empirical objects), the question of the relation of
  2203. the representation to the object is transcendental; and not only are the
  2204. raindrops mere phenomena, but even their circular form, nay, the space
  2205. itself through which they fall, is nothing in itself, but both are mere
  2206. modifications or fundamental dispositions of our sensuous intuition,
  2207. whilst the transcendental object remains for us utterly unknown.
  2208. The second important concern of our aesthetic is that it does not obtain
  2209. favour merely as a plausible hypothesis, but possess as undoubted a
  2210. character of certainty as can be demanded of any theory which is to
  2211. serve for an organon. In order fully to convince the reader of this
  2212. certainty, we shall select a case which will serve to make its validity
  2213. apparent, and also to illustrate what has been said in SS 3.
  2214. Suppose, then, that space and time are in themselves objective, and
  2215. conditions of the--possibility of objects as things in themselves. In
  2216. the first place, it is evident that both present us, with very
  2217. many apodeictic and synthetic propositions a priori, but especially
  2218. space--and for this reason we shall prefer it for investigation at
  2219. present. As the propositions of geometry are cognized synthetically a
  2220. priori, and with apodeictic certainty, I inquire: Whence do you obtain
  2221. propositions of this kind, and on what basis does the understanding
  2222. rest, in order to arrive at such absolutely necessary and universally
  2223. valid truths?
  2224. There is no other way than through intuitions or conceptions, as such;
  2225. and these are given either a priori or a posteriori. The latter, namely,
  2226. empirical conceptions, together with the empirical intuition on which
  2227. they are founded, cannot afford any synthetical proposition, except such
  2228. as is itself also empirical, that is, a proposition of experience. But
  2229. an empirical proposition cannot possess the qualities of necessity and
  2230. absolute universality, which, nevertheless, are the characteristics of
  2231. all geometrical propositions. As to the first and only means to arrive
  2232. at such cognitions, namely, through mere conceptions or intuitions a
  2233. priori, it is quite clear that from mere conceptions no synthetical
  2234. cognitions, but only analytical ones, can be obtained. Take, for
  2235. example, the proposition: "Two straight lines cannot enclose a space,
  2236. and with these alone no figure is possible," and try to deduce it
  2237. from the conception of a straight line and the number two; or take the
  2238. proposition: "It is possible to construct a figure with three straight
  2239. lines," and endeavour, in like manner, to deduce it from the mere
  2240. conception of a straight line and the number three. All your endeavours
  2241. are in vain, and you find yourself forced to have recourse to intuition,
  2242. as, in fact, geometry always does. You therefore give yourself an object
  2243. in intuition. But of what kind is this intuition? Is it a pure a
  2244. priori, or is it an empirical intuition? If the latter, then neither an
  2245. universally valid, much less an apodeictic proposition can arise from
  2246. it, for experience never can give us any such proposition. You must,
  2247. therefore, give yourself an object a priori in intuition, and upon that
  2248. ground your synthetical proposition. Now if there did not exist within
  2249. you a faculty of intuition a priori; if this subjective condition were
  2250. not in respect to its form also the universal condition a priori under
  2251. which alone the object of this external intuition is itself possible;
  2252. if the object (that is, the triangle) were something in itself, without
  2253. relation to you the subject; how could you affirm that that which
  2254. lies necessarily in your subjective conditions in order to construct a
  2255. triangle, must also necessarily belong to the triangle in itself? For
  2256. to your conceptions of three lines, you could not add anything new (that
  2257. is, the figure); which, therefore, must necessarily be found in the
  2258. object, because the object is given before your cognition, and not by
  2259. means of it. If, therefore, space (and time also) were not a mere form
  2260. of your intuition, which contains conditions a priori, under which alone
  2261. things can become external objects for you, and without which subjective
  2262. conditions the objects are in themselves nothing, you could not
  2263. construct any synthetical proposition whatsoever regarding external
  2264. objects. It is therefore not merely possible or probable, but
  2265. indubitably certain, that space and time, as the necessary conditions
  2266. of all our external and internal experience, are merely subjective
  2267. conditions of all our intuitions, in relation to which all objects are
  2268. therefore mere phenomena, and not things in themselves, presented to us
  2269. in this particular manner. And for this reason, in respect to the form
  2270. of phenomena, much may be said a priori, whilst of the thing in itself,
  2271. which may lie at the foundation of these phenomena, it is impossible to
  2272. say anything.
  2273. II. In confirmation of this theory of the ideality of the external as
  2274. well as internal sense, consequently of all objects of sense, as mere
  2275. phenomena, we may especially remark that all in our cognition that
  2276. belongs to intuition contains nothing more than mere relations. (The
  2277. feelings of pain and pleasure, and the will, which are not cognitions,
  2278. are excepted.) The relations, to wit, of place in an intuition
  2279. (extension), change of place (motion), and laws according to which this
  2280. change is determined (moving forces). That, however, which is present in
  2281. this or that place, or any operation going on, or result taking place
  2282. in the things themselves, with the exception of change of place, is not
  2283. given to us by intuition. Now by means of mere relations, a thing cannot
  2284. be known in itself; and it may therefore be fairly concluded, that, as
  2285. through the external sense nothing but mere representations of relations
  2286. are given us, the said external sense in its representation can contain
  2287. only the relation of the object to the subject, but not the essential
  2288. nature of the object as a thing in itself.
  2289. The same is the case with the internal intuition, not only because,
  2290. in the internal intuition, the representation of the external senses
  2291. constitutes the material with which the mind is occupied; but because
  2292. time, in which we place, and which itself antecedes the consciousness
  2293. of, these representations in experience, and which, as the formal
  2294. condition of the mode according to which objects are placed in the mind,
  2295. lies at the foundation of them, contains relations of the successive,
  2296. the coexistent, and of that which always must be coexistent with
  2297. succession, the permanent. Now that which, as representation, can
  2298. antecede every exercise of thought (of an object), is intuition; and
  2299. when it contains nothing but relations, it is the form of the intuition,
  2300. which, as it presents us with no representation, except in so far as
  2301. something is placed in the mind, can be nothing else than the mode in
  2302. which the mind is affected by its own activity, to wit--its presenting
  2303. to itself representations, consequently the mode in which the mind is
  2304. affected by itself; that is, it can be nothing but an internal sense in
  2305. respect to its form. Everything that is represented through the medium
  2306. of sense is so far phenomenal; consequently, we must either refuse
  2307. altogether to admit an internal sense, or the subject, which is the
  2308. object of that sense, could only be represented by it as phenomenon, and
  2309. not as it would judge of itself, if its intuition were pure spontaneous
  2310. activity, that is, were intellectual. The difficulty here lies wholly in
  2311. the question: How can the subject have an internal intuition of itself?
  2312. But this difficulty is common to every theory. The consciousness of
  2313. self (apperception) is the simple representation of the "ego"; and if by
  2314. means of that representation alone, all the manifold representations in
  2315. the subject were spontaneously given, then our internal intuition
  2316. would be intellectual. This consciousness in man requires an internal
  2317. perception of the manifold representations which are previously given in
  2318. the subject; and the manner in which these representations are given in
  2319. the mind without spontaneity, must, on account of this difference
  2320. (the want of spontaneity), be called sensibility. If the faculty of
  2321. self-consciousness is to apprehend what lies in the mind, it must all
  2322. act that and can in this way alone produce an intuition of self. But the
  2323. form of this intuition, which lies in the original constitution of the
  2324. mind, determines, in the representation of time, the manner in which the
  2325. manifold representations are to combine themselves in the mind;
  2326. since the subject intuites itself, not as it would represent itself
  2327. immediately and spontaneously, but according to the manner in which the
  2328. mind is internally affected, consequently, as it appears, and not as it
  2329. is.
  2330. III. When we say that the intuition of external objects, and also the
  2331. self-intuition of the subject, represent both, objects and subject, in
  2332. space and time, as they affect our senses, that is, as they appear--this
  2333. is by no means equivalent to asserting that these objects are mere
  2334. illusory appearances. For when we speak of things as phenomena, the
  2335. objects, nay, even the properties which we ascribe to them, are looked
  2336. upon as really given; only that, in so far as this or that property
  2337. depends upon the mode of intuition of the subject, in the relation
  2338. of the given object to the subject, the object as phenomenon is to be
  2339. distinguished from the object as a thing in itself. Thus I do not say
  2340. that bodies seem or appear to be external to me, or that my soul seems
  2341. merely to be given in my self-consciousness, although I maintain that
  2342. the properties of space and time, in conformity to which I set both, as
  2343. the condition of their existence, abide in my mode of intuition, and not
  2344. in the objects in themselves. It would be my own fault, if out of that
  2345. which I should reckon as phenomenon, I made mere illusory appearance.*
  2346. But this will not happen, because of our principle of the ideality
  2347. of all sensuous intuitions. On the contrary, if we ascribe objective
  2348. reality to these forms of representation, it becomes impossible to avoid
  2349. changing everything into mere appearance. For if we regard space
  2350. and time as properties, which must be found in objects as things in
  2351. themselves, as sine quibus non of the possibility of their existence,
  2352. and reflect on the absurdities in which we then find ourselves involved,
  2353. inasmuch as we are compelled to admit the existence of two infinite
  2354. things, which are nevertheless not substances, nor anything really
  2355. inhering in substances, nay, to admit that they are the necessary
  2356. conditions of the existence of all things, and moreover, that they must
  2357. continue to exist, although all existing things were annihilated--we
  2358. cannot blame the good Berkeley for degrading bodies to mere illusory
  2359. appearances. Nay, even our own existence, which would in this case
  2360. depend upon the self-existent reality of such a mere nonentity as time,
  2361. would necessarily be changed with it into mere appearance--an absurdity
  2362. which no one has as yet been guilty of.
  2363. [*Footnote: The predicates of the phenomenon can be affixed
  2364. to the object itself in relation to our sensuous faculty;
  2365. for example, the red colour or the perfume to the rose. But
  2366. (illusory) appearance never can be attributed as a predicate
  2367. to an object, for this very reason, that it attributes to
  2368. this object in itself that which belongs to it only in
  2369. relation to our sensuous faculty, or to the subject in
  2370. general, e.g., the two handles which were formerly ascribed
  2371. to Saturn. That which is never to be found in the object
  2372. itself, but always in the relation of the object to the
  2373. subject, and which moreover is inseparable from our
  2374. representation of the object, we denominate phenomenon. Thus
  2375. the predicates of space and time are rightly attributed to
  2376. objects of the senses as such, and in this there is no
  2377. illusion. On the contrary, if I ascribe redness of the rose
  2378. as a thing in itself, or to Saturn his handles, or extension
  2379. to all external objects, considered as things in themselves,
  2380. without regarding the determinate relation of these objects
  2381. to the subject, and without limiting my judgement to that
  2382. relation--then, and then only, arises illusion.]
  2383. IV. In natural theology, where we think of an object--God--which never
  2384. can be an object of intuition to us, and even to himself can never be
  2385. an object of sensuous intuition, we carefully avoid attributing to
  2386. his intuition the conditions of space and time--and intuition all his
  2387. cognition must be, and not thought, which always includes limitation.
  2388. But with what right can we do this if we make them forms of objects as
  2389. things in themselves, and such, moreover, as would continue to exist as
  2390. a priori conditions of the existence of things, even though the things
  2391. themselves were annihilated? For as conditions of all existence in
  2392. general, space and time must be conditions of the existence of the
  2393. Supreme Being also. But if we do not thus make them objective forms
  2394. of all things, there is no other way left than to make them subjective
  2395. forms of our mode of intuition--external and internal; which is called
  2396. sensuous, because it is not primitive, that is, is not such as gives in
  2397. itself the existence of the object of the intuition (a mode of intuition
  2398. which, so far as we can judge, can belong only to the Creator), but is
  2399. dependent on the existence of the object, is possible, therefore, only
  2400. on condition that the representative faculty of the subject is affected
  2401. by the object.
  2402. It is, moreover, not necessary that we should limit the mode of
  2403. intuition in space and time to the sensuous faculty of man. It may well
  2404. be that all finite thinking beings must necessarily in this respect
  2405. agree with man (though as to this we cannot decide), but sensibility
  2406. does not on account of this universality cease to be sensibility, for
  2407. this very reason, that it is a deduced (intuitus derivativus), and not
  2408. an original (intuitus originarius), consequently not an intellectual
  2409. intuition, and this intuition, as such, for reasons above mentioned,
  2410. seems to belong solely to the Supreme Being, but never to a being
  2411. dependent, quoad its existence, as well as its intuition (which its
  2412. existence determines and limits relatively to given objects). This
  2413. latter remark, however, must be taken only as an illustration, and not
  2414. as any proof of the truth of our aesthetical theory.
  2415. SS 10. Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic.
  2416. We have now completely before us one part of the solution of the grand
  2417. general problem of transcendental philosophy, namely, the question: "How
  2418. are synthetical propositions a priori possible?" That is to say, we have
  2419. shown that we are in possession of pure a priori intuitions, namely,
  2420. space and time, in which we find, when in a judgement a priori we pass
  2421. out beyond the given conception, something which is not discoverable in
  2422. that conception, but is certainly found a priori in the intuition which
  2423. corresponds to the conception, and can be united synthetically with it.
  2424. But the judgements which these pure intuitions enable us to make, never
  2425. reach farther than to objects of the senses, and are valid only for
  2426. objects of possible experience.
  2427. SECOND PART. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC.
  2428. INTRODUCTION. Idea of a Transcendental Logic.
  2429. I. Of Logic in General.
  2430. Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind, first of which
  2431. is the faculty or power of receiving representations (receptivity for
  2432. impressions); the second is the power of cognizing by means of these
  2433. representations (spontaneity in the production of conceptions). Through
  2434. the first an object is given to us; through the second, it is, in
  2435. relation to the representation (which is a mere determination of the
  2436. mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions constitute, therefore, the
  2437. elements of all our knowledge, so that neither conceptions without
  2438. an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without
  2439. conceptions, can afford us a cognition. Both are either pure or
  2440. empirical. They are empirical, when sensation (which presupposes the
  2441. actual presence of the object) is contained in them; and pure, when no
  2442. sensation is mixed with the representation. Sensations we may call
  2443. the matter of sensuous cognition. Pure intuition consequently contains
  2444. merely the form under which something is intuited, and pure conception
  2445. only the form of the thought of an object. Only pure intuitions and pure
  2446. conceptions are possible a priori; the empirical only a posteriori.
  2447. We apply the term sensibility to the receptivity of the mind for
  2448. impressions, in so far as it is in some way affected; and, on the other
  2449. hand, we call the faculty of spontaneously producing representations,
  2450. or the spontaneity of cognition, understanding. Our nature is so
  2451. constituted that intuition with us never can be other than sensuous,
  2452. that is, it contains only the mode in which we are affected by objects.
  2453. On the other hand, the faculty of thinking the object of sensuous
  2454. intuition is the understanding. Neither of these faculties has a
  2455. preference over the other. Without the sensuous faculty no object
  2456. would be given to us, and without the understanding no object would
  2457. be thought. Thoughts without content are void; intuitions without
  2458. conceptions, blind. Hence it is as necessary for the mind to make its
  2459. conceptions sensuous (that is, to join to them the object in intuition),
  2460. as to make its intuitions intelligible (that is, to bring them under
  2461. conceptions). Neither of these faculties can exchange its proper
  2462. function. Understanding cannot intuite, and the sensuous faculty cannot
  2463. think. In no other way than from the united operation of both, can
  2464. knowledge arise. But no one ought, on this account, to overlook the
  2465. difference of the elements contributed by each; we have rather great
  2466. reason carefully to separate and distinguish them. We therefore
  2467. distinguish the science of the laws of sensibility, that is, aesthetic,
  2468. from the science of the laws of the understanding, that is, logic.
  2469. Now, logic in its turn may be considered as twofold--namely, as logic
  2470. of the general, or of the particular use of the understanding. The first
  2471. contains the absolutely necessary laws of thought, without which no use
  2472. whatsoever of the understanding is possible, and gives laws therefore to
  2473. the understanding, without regard to the difference of objects on which
  2474. it may be employed. The logic of the particular use of the understanding
  2475. contains the laws of correct thinking upon a particular class of
  2476. objects. The former may be called elemental logic--the latter, the
  2477. organon of this or that particular science. The latter is for the
  2478. most part employed in the schools, as a propaedeutic to the sciences,
  2479. although, indeed, according to the course of human reason, it is the
  2480. last thing we arrive at, when the science has been already matured, and
  2481. needs only the finishing touches towards its correction and completion;
  2482. for our knowledge of the objects of our attempted science must be
  2483. tolerably extensive and complete before we can indicate the laws by
  2484. which a science of these objects can be established.
  2485. General logic is again either pure or applied. In the former, we
  2486. abstract all the empirical conditions under which the understanding is
  2487. exercised; for example, the influence of the senses, the play of the
  2488. fantasy or imagination, the laws of the memory, the force of habit, of
  2489. inclination, etc., consequently also, the sources of prejudice--in a
  2490. word, we abstract all causes from which particular cognitions
  2491. arise, because these causes regard the understanding under certain
  2492. circumstances of its application, and, to the knowledge of them
  2493. experience is required. Pure general logic has to do, therefore, merely
  2494. with pure a priori principles, and is a canon of understanding and
  2495. reason, but only in respect of the formal part of their use, be the
  2496. content what it may, empirical or transcendental. General logic is
  2497. called applied, when it is directed to the laws of the use of the
  2498. understanding, under the subjective empirical conditions which
  2499. psychology teaches us. It has therefore empirical principles, although,
  2500. at the same time, it is in so far general, that it applies to the
  2501. exercise of the understanding, without regard to the difference of
  2502. objects. On this account, moreover, it is neither a canon of the
  2503. understanding in general, nor an organon of a particular science, but
  2504. merely a cathartic of the human understanding.
  2505. In general logic, therefore, that part which constitutes pure logic must
  2506. be carefully distinguished from that which constitutes applied (though
  2507. still general) logic. The former alone is properly science, although
  2508. short and dry, as the methodical exposition of an elemental doctrine of
  2509. the understanding ought to be. In this, therefore, logicians must always
  2510. bear in mind two rules:
  2511. 1. As general logic, it makes abstraction of all content of the
  2512. cognition of the understanding, and of the difference of objects, and
  2513. has to do with nothing but the mere form of thought.
  2514. 2. As pure logic, it has no empirical principles, and consequently
  2515. draws nothing (contrary to the common persuasion) from psychology, which
  2516. therefore has no influence on the canon of the understanding. It is a
  2517. demonstrated doctrine, and everything in it must be certain completely a
  2518. priori.
  2519. What I called applied logic (contrary to the common acceptation of this
  2520. term, according to which it should contain certain exercises for the
  2521. scholar, for which pure logic gives the rules), is a representation
  2522. of the understanding, and of the rules of its necessary employment
  2523. in concreto, that is to say, under the accidental conditions of the
  2524. subject, which may either hinder or promote this employment, and which
  2525. are all given only empirically. Thus applied logic treats of attention,
  2526. its impediments and consequences, of the origin of error, of the state
  2527. of doubt, hesitation, conviction, etc., and to it is related pure
  2528. general logic in the same way that pure morality, which contains only
  2529. the necessary moral laws of a free will, is related to practical ethics,
  2530. which considers these laws under all the impediments of feelings,
  2531. inclinations, and passions to which men are more or less subjected, and
  2532. which never can furnish us with a true and demonstrated science, because
  2533. it, as well as applied logic, requires empirical and psychological
  2534. principles.
  2535. II. Of Transcendental Logic.
  2536. General logic, as we have seen, makes abstraction of all content of
  2537. cognition, that is, of all relation of cognition to its object, and
  2538. regards only the logical form in the relation of cognitions to each
  2539. other, that is, the form of thought in general. But as we have both pure
  2540. and empirical intuitions (as transcendental aesthetic proves), in like
  2541. manner a distinction might be drawn between pure and empirical thought
  2542. (of objects). In this case, there would exist a kind of logic, in which
  2543. we should not make abstraction of all content of cognition; for or logic
  2544. which should comprise merely the laws of pure thought (of an object),
  2545. would of course exclude all those cognitions which were of empirical
  2546. content. This kind of logic would also examine the origin of our
  2547. cognitions of objects, so far as that origin cannot be ascribed to the
  2548. objects themselves; while, on the contrary, general logic has nothing
  2549. to do with the origin of our cognitions, but contemplates our
  2550. representations, be they given primitively a priori in ourselves, or be
  2551. they only of empirical origin, solely according to the laws which the
  2552. understanding observes in employing them in the process of thought, in
  2553. relation to each other. Consequently, general logic treats of the form
  2554. of the understanding only, which can be applied to representations, from
  2555. whatever source they may have arisen.
  2556. And here I shall make a remark, which the reader must bear well in mind
  2557. in the course of the following considerations, to wit, that not every
  2558. cognition a priori, but only those through which we cognize that and how
  2559. certain representations (intuitions or conceptions) are applied or are
  2560. possible only a priori; that is to say, the a priori possibility of
  2561. cognition and the a priori use of it are transcendental. Therefore
  2562. neither is space, nor any a priori geometrical determination of space,
  2563. a transcendental Representation, but only the knowledge that such a
  2564. representation is not of empirical origin, and the possibility of its
  2565. relating to objects of experience, although itself a priori, can be
  2566. called transcendental. So also, the application of space to objects
  2567. in general would be transcendental; but if it be limited to objects of
  2568. sense it is empirical. Thus, the distinction of the transcendental
  2569. and empirical belongs only to the critique of cognitions, and does not
  2570. concern the relation of these to their object.
  2571. Accordingly, in the expectation that there may perhaps be conceptions
  2572. which relate a priori to objects, not as pure or sensuous intuitions,
  2573. but merely as acts of pure thought (which are therefore conceptions,
  2574. but neither of empirical nor aesthetical origin)--in this expectation,
  2575. I say, we form to ourselves, by anticipation, the idea of a science
  2576. of pure understanding and rational cognition, by means of which we may
  2577. cogitate objects entirely a priori. A science of this kind, which should
  2578. determine the origin, the extent, and the objective validity of such
  2579. cognitions, must be called transcendental logic, because it has not,
  2580. like general logic, to do with the laws of understanding and reason
  2581. in relation to empirical as well as pure rational cognitions without
  2582. distinction, but concerns itself with these only in an a priori relation
  2583. to objects.
  2584. III. Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic.
  2585. The old question with which people sought to push logicians into a
  2586. corner, so that they must either have recourse to pitiful sophisms or
  2587. confess their ignorance, and consequently the vanity of their whole art,
  2588. is this: "What is truth?" The definition of the word truth, to wit,
  2589. "the accordance of the cognition with its object," is presupposed in
  2590. the question; but we desire to be told, in the answer to it, what is the
  2591. universal and secure criterion of the truth of every cognition.
  2592. To know what questions we may reasonably propose is in itself a strong
  2593. evidence of sagacity and intelligence. For if a question be in itself
  2594. absurd and unsusceptible of a rational answer, it is attended with the
  2595. danger--not to mention the shame that falls upon the person who proposes
  2596. it--of seducing the unguarded listener into making absurd answers, and
  2597. we are presented with the ridiculous spectacle of one (as the ancients
  2598. said) "milking the he-goat, and the other holding a sieve."
  2599. If truth consists in the accordance of a cognition with its object,
  2600. this object must be, ipso facto, distinguished from all others; for a
  2601. cognition is false if it does not accord with the object to which it
  2602. relates, although it contains something which may be affirmed of other
  2603. objects. Now an universal criterion of truth would be that which is
  2604. valid for all cognitions, without distinction of their objects. But
  2605. it is evident that since, in the case of such a criterion, we make
  2606. abstraction of all the content of a cognition (that is, of all relation
  2607. to its object), and truth relates precisely to this content, it must
  2608. be utterly absurd to ask for a mark of the truth of this content of
  2609. cognition; and that, accordingly, a sufficient, and at the same time
  2610. universal, test of truth cannot possibly be found. As we have already
  2611. termed the content of a cognition its matter, we shall say: "Of the
  2612. truth of our cognitions in respect of their matter, no universal test
  2613. can be demanded, because such a demand is self-contradictory."
  2614. On the other hand, with regard to our cognition in respect of its mere
  2615. form (excluding all content), it is equally manifest that logic, in
  2616. so far as it exhibits the universal and necessary laws of the
  2617. understanding, must in these very laws present us with criteria of
  2618. truth. Whatever contradicts these rules is false, because thereby the
  2619. understanding is made to contradict its own universal laws of thought;
  2620. that is, to contradict itself. These criteria, however, apply solely to
  2621. the form of truth, that is, of thought in general, and in so far they
  2622. are perfectly accurate, yet not sufficient. For although a cognition
  2623. may be perfectly accurate as to logical form, that is, not
  2624. self-contradictory, it is notwithstanding quite possible that it may
  2625. not stand in agreement with its object. Consequently, the merely logical
  2626. criterion of truth, namely, the accordance of a cognition with the
  2627. universal and formal laws of understanding and reason, is nothing more
  2628. than the conditio sine qua non, or negative condition of all truth.
  2629. Farther than this logic cannot go, and the error which depends not
  2630. on the form, but on the content of the cognition, it has no test to
  2631. discover.
  2632. General logic, then, resolves the whole formal business of understanding
  2633. and reason into its elements, and exhibits them as principles of all
  2634. logical judging of our cognitions. This part of logic may, therefore, be
  2635. called analytic, and is at least the negative test of truth, because all
  2636. cognitions must first of an be estimated and tried according to these
  2637. laws before we proceed to investigate them in respect of their content,
  2638. in order to discover whether they contain positive truth in regard to
  2639. their object. Because, however, the mere form of a cognition, accurately
  2640. as it may accord with logical laws, is insufficient to supply us with
  2641. material (objective) truth, no one, by means of logic alone, can venture
  2642. to predicate anything of or decide concerning objects, unless he has
  2643. obtained, independently of logic, well-grounded information about them,
  2644. in order afterwards to examine, according to logical laws, into the use
  2645. and connection, in a cohering whole, of that information, or, what is
  2646. still better, merely to test it by them. Notwithstanding, there lies so
  2647. seductive a charm in the possession of a specious art like this--an
  2648. art which gives to all our cognitions the form of the understanding,
  2649. although with respect to the content thereof we may be sadly
  2650. deficient--that general logic, which is merely a canon of judgement, has
  2651. been employed as an organon for the actual production, or rather for
  2652. the semblance of production, of objective assertions, and has thus
  2653. been grossly misapplied. Now general logic, in its assumed character of
  2654. organon, is called dialectic.
  2655. Different as are the significations in which the ancients used this
  2656. term for a science or an art, we may safely infer, from their actual
  2657. employment of it, that with them it was nothing else than a logic of
  2658. illusion--a sophistical art for giving ignorance, nay, even intentional
  2659. sophistries, the colouring of truth, in which the thoroughness of
  2660. procedure which logic requires was imitated, and their topic employed
  2661. to cloak the empty pretensions. Now it may be taken as a safe and useful
  2662. warning, that general logic, considered as an organon, must always be
  2663. a logic of illusion, that is, be dialectical, for, as it teaches us
  2664. nothing whatever respecting the content of our cognitions, but merely
  2665. the formal conditions of their accordance with the understanding, which
  2666. do not relate to and are quite indifferent in respect of objects, any
  2667. attempt to employ it as an instrument (organon) in order to extend and
  2668. enlarge the range of our knowledge must end in mere prating; any one
  2669. being able to maintain or oppose, with some appearance of truth, any
  2670. single assertion whatever.
  2671. Such instruction is quite unbecoming the dignity of philosophy. For
  2672. these reasons we have chosen to denominate this part of logic dialectic,
  2673. in the sense of a critique of dialectical illusion, and we wish the term
  2674. to be so understood in this place.
  2675. IV. Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Transcendental
  2676. Analytic and Dialectic.
  2677. In transcendental logic we isolate the understanding (as in
  2678. transcendental aesthetic the sensibility) and select from our cognition
  2679. merely that part of thought which has its origin in the understanding
  2680. alone. The exercise of this pure cognition, however, depends upon this
  2681. as its condition, that objects to which it may be applied be given to
  2682. us in intuition, for without intuition the whole of our cognition
  2683. is without objects, and is therefore quite void. That part of
  2684. transcendental logic, then, which treats of the elements of pure
  2685. cognition of the understanding, and of the principles without which no
  2686. object at all can be thought, is transcendental analytic, and at the
  2687. same time a logic of truth. For no cognition can contradict it, without
  2688. losing at the same time all content, that is, losing all reference to an
  2689. object, and therefore all truth. But because we are very easily seduced
  2690. into employing these pure cognitions and principles of the understanding
  2691. by themselves, and that even beyond the boundaries of experience, which
  2692. yet is the only source whence we can obtain matter (objects) on which
  2693. those pure conceptions may be employed--understanding runs the risk of
  2694. making, by means of empty sophisms, a material and objective use of
  2695. the mere formal principles of the pure understanding, and of passing
  2696. judgements on objects without distinction--objects which are not given
  2697. to us, nay, perhaps cannot be given to us in any way. Now, as it ought
  2698. properly to be only a canon for judging of the empirical use of the
  2699. understanding, this kind of logic is misused when we seek to employ
  2700. it as an organon of the universal and unlimited exercise of the
  2701. understanding, and attempt with the pure understanding alone to judge
  2702. synthetically, affirm, and determine respecting objects in general. In
  2703. this case the exercise of the pure understanding becomes dialectical.
  2704. The second part of our transcendental logic must therefore be a critique
  2705. of dialectical illusion, and this critique we shall term transcendental
  2706. dialectic--not meaning it as an art of producing dogmatically
  2707. such illusion (an art which is unfortunately too current among
  2708. the practitioners of metaphysical juggling), but as a critique of
  2709. understanding and reason in regard to their hyperphysical use. This
  2710. critique will expose the groundless nature of the pretensions of
  2711. these two faculties, and invalidate their claims to the discovery
  2712. and enlargement of our cognitions merely by means of transcendental
  2713. principles, and show that the proper employment of these faculties is to
  2714. test the judgements made by the pure understanding, and to guard it from
  2715. sophistical delusion.
  2716. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC. FIRST DIVISION.
  2717. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC.
  2718. SS I.
  2719. Transcendental analytic is the dissection of the whole of our a priori
  2720. knowledge into the elements of the pure cognition of the understanding.
  2721. In order to effect our purpose, it is necessary: (1) That the
  2722. conceptions be pure and not empirical; (2) That they belong not to
  2723. intuition and sensibility, but to thought and understanding; (3) That
  2724. they be elementary conceptions, and as such, quite different from
  2725. deduced or compound conceptions; (4) That our table of these elementary
  2726. conceptions be complete, and fill up the whole sphere of the pure
  2727. understanding. Now this completeness of a science cannot be accepted
  2728. with confidence on the guarantee of a mere estimate of its existence in
  2729. an aggregate formed only by means of repeated experiments and attempts.
  2730. The completeness which we require is possible only by means of an idea
  2731. of the totality of the a priori cognition of the understanding, and
  2732. through the thereby determined division of the conceptions which form
  2733. the said whole; consequently, only by means of their connection in
  2734. a system. Pure understanding distinguishes itself not merely from
  2735. everything empirical, but also completely from all sensibility. It is
  2736. a unity self-subsistent, self-sufficient, and not to be enlarged by any
  2737. additions from without. Hence the sum of its cognition constitutes
  2738. a system to be determined by and comprised under an idea; and the
  2739. completeness and articulation of this system can at the same time
  2740. serve as a test of the correctness and genuineness of all the parts of
  2741. cognition that belong to it. The whole of this part of transcendental
  2742. logic consists of two books, of which the one contains the conceptions,
  2743. and the other the principles of pure understanding.
  2744. BOOK I.
  2745. SS 2. Analytic of Conceptions.
  2746. By the term Analytic of Conceptions, I do not understand the analysis
  2747. of these, or the usual process in philosophical investigations of
  2748. dissecting the conceptions which present themselves, according to
  2749. their content, and so making them clear; but I mean the hitherto little
  2750. attempted dissection of the faculty of understanding itself, in order to
  2751. investigate the possibility of conceptions a priori, by looking for them
  2752. in the understanding alone, as their birthplace, and analysing the pure
  2753. use of this faculty. For this is the proper duty of a transcendental
  2754. philosophy; what remains is the logical treatment of the conceptions in
  2755. philosophy in general. We shall therefore follow up the pure conceptions
  2756. even to their germs and beginnings in the human understanding, in which
  2757. they lie, until they are developed on occasions presented by experience,
  2758. and, freed by the same understanding from the empirical conditions
  2759. attaching to them, are set forth in their unalloyed purity.
  2760. CHAPTER I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure
  2761. Conceptions of the Understanding.
  2762. SS 3. Introductory.
  2763. When we call into play a faculty of cognition, different conceptions
  2764. manifest themselves according to the different circumstances, and
  2765. make known this faculty, and assemble themselves into a more or less
  2766. extensive collection, according to the time or penetration that has been
  2767. applied to the consideration of them. Where this process, conducted as
  2768. it is mechanically, so to speak, will end, cannot be determined with
  2769. certainty. Besides, the conceptions which we discover in this haphazard
  2770. manner present themselves by no means in order and systematic unity,
  2771. but are at last coupled together only according to resemblances to
  2772. each other, and arranged in series, according to the quantity of their
  2773. content, from the simpler to the more complex--series which are anything
  2774. but systematic, though not altogether without a certain kind of method
  2775. in their construction.
  2776. Transcendental philosophy has the advantage, and moreover the duty, of
  2777. searching for its conceptions according to a principle; because these
  2778. conceptions spring pure and unmixed out of the understanding as
  2779. an absolute unity, and therefore must be connected with each other
  2780. according to one conception or idea. A connection of this kind, however,
  2781. furnishes us with a ready prepared rule, by which its proper place
  2782. may be assigned to every pure conception of the understanding, and the
  2783. completeness of the system of all be determined a priori--both which
  2784. would otherwise have been dependent on mere choice or chance.
  2785. SS 4. SECTION 1. Of defined above Use of understanding in General.
  2786. The understanding was defined above only negatively, as a non-sensuous
  2787. faculty of cognition. Now, independently of sensibility, we cannot
  2788. possibly have any intuition; consequently, the understanding is no
  2789. faculty of intuition. But besides intuition there is no other mode of
  2790. cognition, except through conceptions; consequently, the cognition of
  2791. every, at least of every human, understanding is a cognition through
  2792. conceptions--not intuitive, but discursive. All intuitions, as sensuous,
  2793. depend on affections; conceptions, therefore, upon functions. By the
  2794. word function I understand the unity of the act of arranging diverse
  2795. representations under one common representation. Conceptions, then, are
  2796. based on the spontaneity of thought, as sensuous intuitions are on the
  2797. receptivity of impressions. Now, the understanding cannot make any
  2798. other use of these conceptions than to judge by means of them. As no
  2799. representation, except an intuition, relates immediately to its object,
  2800. a conception never relates immediately to an object, but only to
  2801. some other representation thereof, be that an intuition or itself a
  2802. conception. A judgement, therefore, is the mediate cognition of an
  2803. object, consequently the representation of a representation of it. In
  2804. every judgement there is a conception which applies to, and is valid for
  2805. many other conceptions, and which among these comprehends also a given
  2806. representation, this last being immediately connected with an object.
  2807. For example, in the judgement--"All bodies are divisible," our
  2808. conception of divisible applies to various other conceptions; among
  2809. these, however, it is here particularly applied to the conception of
  2810. body, and this conception of body relates to certain phenomena which
  2811. occur to us. These objects, therefore, are mediately represented by the
  2812. conception of divisibility. All judgements, accordingly, are functions
  2813. of unity in our representations, inasmuch as, instead of an immediate, a
  2814. higher representation, which comprises this and various others, is used
  2815. for our cognition of the object, and thereby many possible cognitions
  2816. are collected into one. But we can reduce all acts of the understanding
  2817. to judgements, so that understanding may be represented as the faculty
  2818. of judging. For it is, according to what has been said above, a faculty
  2819. of thought. Now thought is cognition by means of conceptions. But
  2820. conceptions, as predicates of possible judgements, relate to some
  2821. representation of a yet undetermined object. Thus the conception of body
  2822. indicates something--for example, metal--which can be cognized by means
  2823. of that conception. It is therefore a conception, for the reason alone
  2824. that other representations are contained under it, by means of which
  2825. it can relate to objects. It is therefore the predicate to a possible
  2826. judgement; for example: "Every metal is a body." All the functions of
  2827. the understanding therefore can be discovered, when we can completely
  2828. exhibit the functions of unity in judgements. And that this may be
  2829. effected very easily, the following section will show.
  2830. SS 5. SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in
  2831. Judgements.
  2832. If we abstract all the content of a judgement, and consider only the
  2833. intellectual form thereof, we find that the function of thought in a
  2834. judgement can be brought under four heads, of which each contains three
  2835. momenta. These may be conveniently represented in the following table:
  2836. 1
  2837. Quantity of judgements
  2838. Universal
  2839. Particular
  2840. Singular
  2841. 2 3
  2842. Quality Relation
  2843. Affirmative Categorical
  2844. Negative Hypothetical
  2845. Infinite Disjunctive
  2846. 4
  2847. Modality
  2848. Problematical
  2849. Assertorical
  2850. Apodeictical
  2851. As this division appears to differ in some, though not essential points,
  2852. from the usual technique of logicians, the following observations,
  2853. for the prevention of otherwise possible misunderstanding, will not be
  2854. without their use.
  2855. 1. Logicians say, with justice, that in the use of judgements in
  2856. syllogisms, singular judgements may be treated like universal ones.
  2857. For, precisely because a singular judgement has no extent at all, its
  2858. predicate cannot refer to a part of that which is contained in the
  2859. conception of the subject and be excluded from the rest. The predicate
  2860. is valid for the whole conception just as if it were a general
  2861. conception, and had extent, to the whole of which the predicate applied.
  2862. On the other hand, let us compare a singular with a general judgement,
  2863. merely as a cognition, in regard to quantity. The singular judgement
  2864. relates to the general one, as unity to infinity, and is therefore in
  2865. itself essentially different. Thus, if we estimate a singular judgement
  2866. (judicium singulare) not merely according to its intrinsic validity as a
  2867. judgement, but also as a cognition generally, according to its quantity
  2868. in comparison with that of other cognitions, it is then entirely
  2869. different from a general judgement (judicium commune), and in a complete
  2870. table of the momenta of thought deserves a separate place--though,
  2871. indeed, this would not be necessary in a logic limited merely to the
  2872. consideration of the use of judgements in reference to each other.
  2873. 2. In like manner, in transcendental logic, infinite must be
  2874. distinguished from affirmative judgements, although in general logic
  2875. they are rightly enough classed under affirmative. General logic
  2876. abstracts all content of the predicate (though it be negative), and
  2877. only considers whether the said predicate be affirmed or denied of the
  2878. subject. But transcendental logic considers also the worth or content of
  2879. this logical affirmation--an affirmation by means of a merely negative
  2880. predicate, and inquires how much the sum total of our cognition gains
  2881. by this affirmation. For example, if I say of the soul, "It is not
  2882. mortal"--by this negative judgement I should at least ward off error.
  2883. Now, by the proposition, "The soul is not mortal," I have, in respect of
  2884. the logical form, really affirmed, inasmuch as I thereby place the soul
  2885. in the unlimited sphere of immortal beings. Now, because of the whole
  2886. sphere of possible existences, the mortal occupies one part, and the
  2887. immortal the other, neither more nor less is affirmed by the proposition
  2888. than that the soul is one among the infinite multitude of things
  2889. which remain over, when I take away the whole mortal part. But by this
  2890. proceeding we accomplish only this much, that the infinite sphere of
  2891. all possible existences is in so far limited that the mortal is excluded
  2892. from it, and the soul is placed in the remaining part of the extent
  2893. of this sphere. But this part remains, notwithstanding this exception,
  2894. infinite, and more and more parts may be taken away from the whole
  2895. sphere, without in the slightest degree thereby augmenting or
  2896. affirmatively determining our conception of the soul. These judgements,
  2897. therefore, infinite in respect of their logical extent, are, in
  2898. respect of the content of their cognition, merely limitative; and are
  2899. consequently entitled to a place in our transcendental table of all
  2900. the momenta of thought in judgements, because the function of the
  2901. understanding exercised by them may perhaps be of importance in the
  2902. field of its pure a priori cognition.
  2903. 3. All relations of thought in judgements are those (a) of the predicate
  2904. to the subject; (b) of the principle to its consequence; (c) of the
  2905. divided cognition and all the members of the division to each other. In
  2906. the first of these three classes, we consider only two conceptions; in
  2907. the second, two judgements; in the third, several judgements in relation
  2908. to each other. The hypothetical proposition, "If perfect justice exists,
  2909. the obstinately wicked are punished," contains properly the relation to
  2910. each other of two propositions, namely, "Perfect justice exists," and
  2911. "The obstinately wicked are punished." Whether these propositions are in
  2912. themselves true is a question not here decided. Nothing is cogitated
  2913. by means of this judgement except a certain consequence. Finally, the
  2914. disjunctive judgement contains a relation of two or more propositions to
  2915. each other--a relation not of consequence, but of logical opposition, in
  2916. so far as the sphere of the one proposition excludes that of the other.
  2917. But it contains at the same time a relation of community, in so far as
  2918. all the propositions taken together fill up the sphere of the cognition.
  2919. The disjunctive judgement contains, therefore, the relation of the parts
  2920. of the whole sphere of a cognition, since the sphere of each part is a
  2921. complemental part of the sphere of the other, each contributing to
  2922. form the sum total of the divided cognition. Take, for example, the
  2923. proposition, "The world exists either through blind chance, or through
  2924. internal necessity, or through an external cause." Each of these
  2925. propositions embraces a part of the sphere of our possible cognition
  2926. as to the existence of a world; all of them taken together, the whole
  2927. sphere. To take the cognition out of one of these spheres, is equivalent
  2928. to placing it in one of the others; and, on the other hand, to place
  2929. it in one sphere is equivalent to taking it out of the rest. There is,
  2930. therefore, in a disjunctive judgement a certain community of cognitions,
  2931. which consists in this, that they mutually exclude each other, yet
  2932. thereby determine, as a whole, the true cognition, inasmuch as, taken
  2933. together, they make up the complete content of a particular given
  2934. cognition. And this is all that I find necessary, for the sake of what
  2935. follows, to remark in this place.
  2936. 4. The modality of judgements is a quite peculiar function, with this
  2937. distinguishing characteristic, that it contributes nothing to the
  2938. content of a judgement (for besides quantity, quality, and relation,
  2939. there is nothing more that constitutes the content of a judgement), but
  2940. concerns itself only with the value of the copula in relation to thought
  2941. in general. Problematical judgements are those in which the affirmation
  2942. or negation is accepted as merely possible (ad libitum). In the
  2943. assertorical, we regard the proposition as real (true); in the
  2944. apodeictical, we look on it as necessary.* Thus the two judgements
  2945. (antecedens et consequens), the relation of which constitutes a
  2946. hypothetical judgement, likewise those (the members of the division) in
  2947. whose reciprocity the disjunctive consists, are only problematical. In
  2948. the example above given the proposition, "There exists perfect justice,"
  2949. is not stated assertorically, but as an ad libitum judgement, which
  2950. someone may choose to adopt, and the consequence alone is assertorical.
  2951. Hence such judgements may be obviously false, and yet, taken
  2952. problematically, be conditions of our cognition of the truth. Thus
  2953. the proposition, "The world exists only by blind chance," is in the
  2954. disjunctive judgement of problematical import only: that is to say, one
  2955. may accept it for the moment, and it helps us (like the indication of
  2956. the wrong road among all the roads that one can take) to find out the
  2957. true proposition. The problematical proposition is, therefore, that
  2958. which expresses only logical possibility (which is not objective);
  2959. that is, it expresses a free choice to admit the validity of such a
  2960. proposition--a merely arbitrary reception of it into the understanding.
  2961. The assertorical speaks of logical reality or truth; as, for example,
  2962. in a hypothetical syllogism, the antecedens presents itself in a
  2963. problematical form in the major, in an assertorical form in the minor,
  2964. and it shows that the proposition is in harmony with the laws of the
  2965. understanding. The apodeictical proposition cogitates the assertorical
  2966. as determined by these very laws of the understanding, consequently as
  2967. affirming a priori, and in this manner it expresses logical
  2968. necessity. Now because all is here gradually incorporated with the
  2969. understanding--inasmuch as in the first place we judge problematically;
  2970. then accept assertorically our judgement as true; lastly, affirm it as
  2971. inseparably united with the understanding, that is, as necessary and
  2972. apodeictical--we may safely reckon these three functions of modality as
  2973. so many momenta of thought.
  2974. [*Footnote: Just as if thought were in the first instance a
  2975. function of the understanding; in the second, of judgement;
  2976. in the third, of reason. A remark which will be explained in
  2977. the sequel.]
  2978. SS 6. SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories.
  2979. General logic, as has been repeatedly said, makes abstraction of all
  2980. content of cognition, and expects to receive representations from some
  2981. other quarter, in order, by means of analysis, to convert them into
  2982. conceptions. On the contrary, transcendental logic has lying before
  2983. it the manifold content of a priori sensibility, which transcendental
  2984. aesthetic presents to it in order to give matter to the pure conceptions
  2985. of the understanding, without which transcendental logic would have no
  2986. content, and be therefore utterly void. Now space and time contain an
  2987. infinite diversity of determinations of pure a priori intuition, but are
  2988. nevertheless the condition of the mind's receptivity, under which alone
  2989. it can obtain representations of objects, and which, consequently, must
  2990. always affect the conception of these objects. But the spontaneity of
  2991. thought requires that this diversity be examined after a certain manner,
  2992. received into the mind, and connected, in order afterwards to form a
  2993. cognition out of it. This Process I call synthesis.
  2994. By the word synthesis, in its most general signification, I understand
  2995. the process of joining different representations to each other and of
  2996. comprehending their diversity in one cognition. This synthesis is pure
  2997. when the diversity is not given empirically but a priori (as that in
  2998. space and time). Our representations must be given previously to any
  2999. analysis of them; and no conceptions can arise, quoad their content,
  3000. analytically. But the synthesis of a diversity (be it given a priori or
  3001. empirically) is the first requisite for the production of a cognition,
  3002. which in its beginning, indeed, may be crude and confused, and therefore
  3003. in need of analysis--still, synthesis is that by which alone the
  3004. elements of our cognitions are collected and united into a certain
  3005. content, consequently it is the first thing on which we must fix our
  3006. attention, if we wish to investigate the origin of our knowledge.
  3007. Synthesis, generally speaking, is, as we shall afterwards see, the mere
  3008. operation of the imagination--a blind but indispensable function of the
  3009. soul, without which we should have no cognition whatever, but of the
  3010. working of which we are seldom even conscious. But to reduce this
  3011. synthesis to conceptions is a function of the understanding, by means of
  3012. which we attain to cognition, in the proper meaning of the term.
  3013. Pure synthesis, represented generally, gives us the pure conception of
  3014. the understanding. But by this pure synthesis, I mean that which rests
  3015. upon a basis of a priori synthetical unity. Thus, our numeration (and
  3016. this is more observable in large numbers) is a synthesis according to
  3017. conceptions, because it takes place according to a common basis of unity
  3018. (for example, the decade). By means of this conception, therefore, the
  3019. unity in the synthesis of the manifold becomes necessary.
  3020. By means of analysis different representations are brought under one
  3021. conception--an operation of which general logic treats. On the other
  3022. hand, the duty of transcendental logic is to reduce to conceptions, not
  3023. representations, but the pure synthesis of representations. The first
  3024. thing which must be given to us for the sake of the a priori cognition
  3025. of all objects, is the diversity of the pure intuition; the synthesis
  3026. of this diversity by means of the imagination is the second; but this
  3027. gives, as yet, no cognition. The conceptions which give unity to this
  3028. pure synthesis, and which consist solely in the representation of
  3029. this necessary synthetical unity, furnish the third requisite for
  3030. the cognition of an object, and these conceptions are given by the
  3031. understanding.
  3032. The same function which gives unity to the different representation in
  3033. a judgement, gives also unity to the mere synthesis of different
  3034. representations in an intuition; and this unity we call the pure
  3035. conception of the understanding. Thus, the same understanding, and by
  3036. the same operations, whereby in conceptions, by means of analytical
  3037. unity, it produced the logical form of a judgement, introduces, by means
  3038. of the synthetical unity of the manifold in intuition, a transcendental
  3039. content into its representations, on which account they are called pure
  3040. conceptions of the understanding, and they apply a priori to objects, a
  3041. result not within the power of general logic.
  3042. In this manner, there arise exactly so many pure conceptions of the
  3043. understanding, applying a priori to objects of intuition in general, as
  3044. there are logical functions in all possible judgements. For there is no
  3045. other function or faculty existing in the understanding besides those
  3046. enumerated in that table. These conceptions we shall, with Aristotle,
  3047. call categories, our purpose being originally identical with his,
  3048. notwithstanding the great difference in the execution.
  3049. TABLE OF THE CATEGORIES
  3050. 1 2
  3051. Of Quantity Of Quality
  3052. Unity Reality
  3053. Plurality Negation
  3054. Totality Limitation
  3055. 3
  3056. Of Relation
  3057. Of Inherence and Subsistence (substantia et accidens)
  3058. Of Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)
  3059. Of Community (reciprocity between the agent and patient)
  3060. 4
  3061. Of Modality
  3062. Possibility--Impossibility
  3063. Existence--Non-existence
  3064. Necessity--Contingence
  3065. This, then, is a catalogue of all the originally pure conceptions of
  3066. the synthesis which the understanding contains a priori, and these
  3067. conceptions alone entitle it to be called a pure understanding; inasmuch
  3068. as only by them it can render the manifold of intuition conceivable,
  3069. in other words, think an object of intuition. This division is made
  3070. systematically from a common principle, namely the faculty of judgement
  3071. (which is just the same as the power of thought), and has not arisen
  3072. rhapsodically from a search at haphazard after pure conceptions,
  3073. respecting the full number of which we never could be certain, inasmuch
  3074. as we employ induction alone in our search, without considering that in
  3075. this way we can never understand wherefore precisely these conceptions,
  3076. and none others, abide in the pure understanding. It was a design worthy
  3077. of an acute thinker like Aristotle, to search for these fundamental
  3078. conceptions. Destitute, however, of any guiding principle, he picked
  3079. them up just as they occurred to him, and at first hunted out ten, which
  3080. he called categories (predicaments). Afterwards be believed that he
  3081. had discovered five others, which were added under the name of post
  3082. predicaments. But his catalogue still remained defective. Besides,
  3083. there are to be found among them some of the modes of pure sensibility
  3084. (quando, ubi, situs, also prius, simul), and likewise an empirical
  3085. conception (motus)--which can by no means belong to this genealogical
  3086. register of the pure understanding. Moreover, there are deduced
  3087. conceptions (actio, passio) enumerated among the original conceptions,
  3088. and, of the latter, some are entirely wanting.
  3089. With regard to these, it is to be remarked, that the categories, as the
  3090. true primitive conceptions of the pure understanding, have also their
  3091. pure deduced conceptions, which, in a complete system of transcendental
  3092. philosophy, must by no means be passed over; though in a merely critical
  3093. essay we must be contented with the simple mention of the fact.
  3094. Let it be allowed me to call these pure, but deduced conceptions of
  3095. the understanding, the predicables of the pure understanding, in
  3096. contradistinction to predicaments. If we are in possession of the
  3097. original and primitive, the deduced and subsidiary conceptions can
  3098. easily be added, and the genealogical tree of the understanding
  3099. completely delineated. As my present aim is not to set forth a complete
  3100. system, but merely the principles of one, I reserve this task for
  3101. another time. It may be easily executed by any one who will refer to the
  3102. ontological manuals, and subordinate to the category of causality,
  3103. for example, the predicables of force, action, passion; to that of
  3104. community, those of presence and resistance; to the categories of
  3105. modality, those of origination, extinction, change; and so with the
  3106. rest. The categories combined with the modes of pure sensibility, or
  3107. with one another, afford a great number of deduced a priori conceptions;
  3108. a complete enumeration of which would be a useful and not unpleasant,
  3109. but in this place a perfectly dispensable, occupation.
  3110. I purposely omit the definitions of the categories in this treatise.
  3111. I shall analyse these conceptions only so far as is necessary for the
  3112. doctrine of method, which is to form a part of this critique. In
  3113. a system of pure reason, definitions of them would be with justice
  3114. demanded of me, but to give them here would only bide from our view
  3115. the main aim of our investigation, at the same time raising doubts and
  3116. objections, the consideration of which, without injustice to our main
  3117. purpose, may be very well postponed till another opportunity. Meanwhile,
  3118. it ought to be sufficiently clear, from the little we have already said
  3119. on this subject, that the formation of a complete vocabulary of pure
  3120. conceptions, accompanied by all the requisite explanations, is not only
  3121. a possible, but an easy undertaking. The compartments already exist;
  3122. it is only necessary to fill them up; and a systematic topic like the
  3123. present, indicates with perfect precision the proper place to which each
  3124. conception belongs, while it readily points out any that have not yet
  3125. been filled up.
  3126. SS 7.
  3127. Our table of the categories suggests considerations of some importance,
  3128. which may perhaps have significant results in regard to the scientific
  3129. form of all rational cognitions. For, that this table is useful in the
  3130. theoretical part of philosophy, nay, indispensable for the sketching
  3131. of the complete plan of a science, so far as that science rests upon
  3132. conceptions a priori, and for dividing it mathematically, according to
  3133. fixed principles, is most manifest from the fact that it contains all
  3134. the elementary conceptions of the understanding, nay, even the form of a
  3135. system of these in the understanding itself, and consequently indicates
  3136. all the momenta, and also the internal arrangement of a projected
  3137. speculative science, as I have elsewhere shown. [Footnote: In the
  3138. Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science.] Here follow some of these
  3139. observations.
  3140. I. This table, which contains four classes of conceptions of the
  3141. understanding, may, in the first instance, be divided into two classes,
  3142. the first of which relates to objects of intuition--pure as well as
  3143. empirical; the second, to the existence of these objects, either in
  3144. relation to one another, or to the understanding.
  3145. The former of these classes of categories I would entitle the
  3146. mathematical, and the latter the dynamical categories. The former, as we
  3147. see, has no correlates; these are only to be found in the second
  3148. class. This difference must have a ground in the nature of the human
  3149. understanding.
  3150. II. The number of the categories in each class is always the same,
  3151. namely, three--a fact which also demands some consideration, because
  3152. in all other cases division a priori through conceptions is necessarily
  3153. dichotomy. It is to be added, that the third category in each triad
  3154. always arises from the combination of the second with the first.
  3155. Thus totality is nothing else but plurality contemplated as unity;
  3156. limitation is merely reality conjoined with negation; community is the
  3157. causality of a substance, reciprocally determining, and determined by
  3158. other substances; and finally, necessity is nothing but existence,
  3159. which is given through the possibility itself. Let it not be supposed,
  3160. however, that the third category is merely a deduced, and not a
  3161. primitive conception of the pure understanding. For the conjunction of
  3162. the first and second, in order to produce the third conception, requires
  3163. a particular function of the understanding, which is by no means
  3164. identical with those which are exercised in the first and second. Thus,
  3165. the conception of a number (which belongs to the category of totality)
  3166. is not always possible, where the conceptions of multitude and unity
  3167. exist (for example, in the representation of the infinite). Or, if I
  3168. conjoin the conception of a cause with that of a substance, it does not
  3169. follow that the conception of influence, that is, how one substance can
  3170. be the cause of something in another substance, will be understood from
  3171. that. Thus it is evident that a particular act of the understanding is
  3172. here necessary; and so in the other instances.
  3173. III. With respect to one category, namely, that of community, which is
  3174. found in the third class, it is not so easy as with the others to
  3175. detect its accordance with the form of the disjunctive judgement which
  3176. corresponds to it in the table of the logical functions.
  3177. In order to assure ourselves of this accordance, we must observe that in
  3178. every disjunctive judgement, the sphere of the judgement (that is,
  3179. the complex of all that is contained in it) is represented as a whole
  3180. divided into parts; and, since one part cannot be contained in the
  3181. other, they are cogitated as co-ordinated with, not subordinated to each
  3182. other, so that they do not determine each other unilaterally, as in a
  3183. linear series, but reciprocally, as in an aggregate--(if one member of
  3184. the division is posited, all the rest are excluded; and conversely).
  3185. Now a like connection is cogitated in a whole of things; for one thing
  3186. is not subordinated, as effect, to another as cause of its existence,
  3187. but, on the contrary, is co-ordinated contemporaneously and
  3188. reciprocally, as a cause in relation to the determination of the others
  3189. (for example, in a body--the parts of which mutually attract and repel
  3190. each other). And this is an entirely different kind of connection from
  3191. that which we find in the mere relation of the cause to the effect (the
  3192. principle to the consequence), for in such a connection the consequence
  3193. does not in its turn determine the principle, and therefore does not
  3194. constitute, with the latter, a whole--just as the Creator does not with
  3195. the world make up a whole. The process of understanding by which it
  3196. represents to itself the sphere of a divided conception, is employed
  3197. also when we think of a thing as divisible; and in the same manner as
  3198. the members of the division in the former exclude one another, and yet
  3199. are connected in one sphere, so the understanding represents to itself
  3200. the parts of the latter, as having--each of them--an existence (as
  3201. substances), independently of the others, and yet as united in one
  3202. whole.
  3203. SS 8.
  3204. In the transcendental philosophy of the ancients there exists one more
  3205. leading division, which contains pure conceptions of the understanding,
  3206. and which, although not numbered among the categories, ought, according
  3207. to them, as conceptions a priori, to be valid of objects. But in this
  3208. case they would augment the number of the categories; which cannot
  3209. be. These are set forth in the proposition, so renowned among the
  3210. schoolmen--"Quodlibet ens est UNUM, VERUM, BONUM." Now, though the
  3211. inferences from this principle were mere tautological propositions,
  3212. and though it is allowed only by courtesy to retain a place in modern
  3213. metaphysics, yet a thought which maintained itself for such a length
  3214. of time, however empty it seems to be, deserves an investigation of its
  3215. origin, and justifies the conjecture that it must be grounded in some
  3216. law of the understanding, which, as is often the case, has only been
  3217. erroneously interpreted. These pretended transcendental predicates are,
  3218. in fact, nothing but logical requisites and criteria of all cognition
  3219. of objects, and they employ, as the basis for this cognition, the
  3220. categories of quantity, namely, unity, plurality, and totality. But
  3221. these, which must be taken as material conditions, that is, as belonging
  3222. to the possibility of things themselves, they employed merely in a
  3223. formal signification, as belonging to the logical requisites of all
  3224. cognition, and yet most unguardedly changed these criteria of thought
  3225. into properties of objects, as things in themselves. Now, in every
  3226. cognition of an object, there is unity of conception, which may be
  3227. called qualitative unity, so far as by this term we understand only the
  3228. unity in our connection of the manifold; for example, unity of the theme
  3229. in a play, an oration, or a story. Secondly, there is truth in respect
  3230. of the deductions from it. The more true deductions we have from a given
  3231. conception, the more criteria of its objective reality. This we might
  3232. call the qualitative plurality of characteristic marks, which belong
  3233. to a conception as to a common foundation, but are not cogitated as a
  3234. quantity in it. Thirdly, there is perfection--which consists in this,
  3235. that the plurality falls back upon the unity of the conception, and
  3236. accords completely with that conception and with no other. This we may
  3237. denominate qualitative completeness. Hence it is evident that these
  3238. logical criteria of the possibility of cognition are merely the three
  3239. categories of quantity modified and transformed to suit an unauthorized
  3240. manner of applying them. That is to say, the three categories, in
  3241. which the unity in the production of the quantum must be homogeneous
  3242. throughout, are transformed solely with a view to the connection of
  3243. heterogeneous parts of cognition in one act of consciousness, by
  3244. means of the quality of the cognition, which is the principle of that
  3245. connection. Thus the criterion of the possibility of a conception
  3246. (not of its object) is the definition of it, in which the unity of the
  3247. conception, the truth of all that may be immediately deduced from it,
  3248. and finally, the completeness of what has been thus deduced, constitute
  3249. the requisites for the reproduction of the whole conception. Thus also,
  3250. the criterion or test of an hypothesis is the intelligibility of the
  3251. received principle of explanation, or its unity (without help from any
  3252. subsidiary hypothesis)--the truth of our deductions from it (consistency
  3253. with each other and with experience)--and lastly, the completeness of
  3254. the principle of the explanation of these deductions, which refer
  3255. to neither more nor less than what was admitted in the hypothesis,
  3256. restoring analytically and a posteriori, what was cogitated
  3257. synthetically and a priori. By the conceptions, therefore, of unity,
  3258. truth, and perfection, we have made no addition to the transcendental
  3259. table of the categories, which is complete without them. We have, on
  3260. the contrary, merely employed the three categories of quantity, setting
  3261. aside their application to objects of experience, as general logical
  3262. laws of the consistency of cognition with itself.
  3263. CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the
  3264. Understanding.
  3265. SS 9. SECTION I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in
  3266. general.
  3267. Teachers of jurisprudence, when speaking of rights and claims,
  3268. distinguish in a cause the question of right (quid juris) from the
  3269. question of fact (quid facti), and while they demand proof of both, they
  3270. give to the proof of the former, which goes to establish right or claim
  3271. in law, the name of deduction. Now we make use of a great number of
  3272. empirical conceptions, without opposition from any one; and consider
  3273. ourselves, even without any attempt at deduction, justified in attaching
  3274. to them a sense, and a supposititious signification, because we have
  3275. always experience at hand to demonstrate their objective reality. There
  3276. exist also, however, usurped conceptions, such as fortune, fate, which
  3277. circulate with almost universal indulgence, and yet are occasionally
  3278. challenged by the question, "quid juris?" In such cases, we have great
  3279. difficulty in discovering any deduction for these terms, inasmuch as we
  3280. cannot produce any manifest ground of right, either from experience or
  3281. from reason, on which the claim to employ them can be founded.
  3282. Among the many conceptions, which make up the very variegated web of
  3283. human cognition, some are destined for pure use a priori, independent
  3284. of all experience; and their title to be so employed always requires
  3285. a deduction, inasmuch as, to justify such use of them, proofs from
  3286. experience are not sufficient; but it is necessary to know how these
  3287. conceptions can apply to objects without being derived from experience.
  3288. I term, therefore, an examination of the manner in which conceptions can
  3289. apply a priori to objects, the transcendental deduction of conceptions,
  3290. and I distinguish it from the empirical deduction, which indicates the
  3291. mode in which conception is obtained through experience and reflection
  3292. thereon; consequently, does not concern itself with the right, but only
  3293. with the fact of our obtaining conceptions in such and such a manner. We
  3294. have already seen that we are in possession of two perfectly different
  3295. kinds of conceptions, which nevertheless agree with each other in this,
  3296. that they both apply to objects completely a priori. These are
  3297. the conceptions of space and time as forms of sensibility, and the
  3298. categories as pure conceptions of the understanding. To attempt an
  3299. empirical deduction of either of these classes would be labour in vain,
  3300. because the distinguishing characteristic of their nature consists in
  3301. this, that they apply to their objects, without having borrowed anything
  3302. from experience towards the representation of them. Consequently, if
  3303. a deduction of these conceptions is necessary, it must always be
  3304. transcendental.
  3305. Meanwhile, with respect to these conceptions, as with respect to all our
  3306. cognition, we certainly may discover in experience, if not the principle
  3307. of their possibility, yet the occasioning causes of their production. It
  3308. will be found that the impressions of sense give the first occasion
  3309. for bringing into action the whole faculty of cognition, and for the
  3310. production of experience, which contains two very dissimilar elements,
  3311. namely, a matter for cognition, given by the senses, and a certain form
  3312. for the arrangement of this matter, arising out of the inner fountain
  3313. of pure intuition and thought; and these, on occasion given by sensuous
  3314. impressions, are called into exercise and produce conceptions. Such
  3315. an investigation into the first efforts of our faculty of cognition to
  3316. mount from particular perceptions to general conceptions is undoubtedly
  3317. of great utility; and we have to thank the celebrated Locke for having
  3318. first opened the way for this inquiry. But a deduction of the pure a
  3319. priori conceptions of course never can be made in this way, seeing that,
  3320. in regard to their future employment, which must be entirely independent
  3321. of experience, they must have a far different certificate of birth
  3322. to show from that of a descent from experience. This attempted
  3323. physiological derivation, which cannot properly be called deduction,
  3324. because it relates merely to a quaestio facti, I shall entitle an
  3325. explanation of the possession of a pure cognition. It is therefore
  3326. manifest that there can only be a transcendental deduction of these
  3327. conceptions and by no means an empirical one; also, that all attempts
  3328. at an empirical deduction, in regard to pure a priori conceptions, are
  3329. vain, and can only be made by one who does not understand the altogether
  3330. peculiar nature of these cognitions.
  3331. But although it is admitted that the only possible deduction of pure
  3332. a priori cognition is a transcendental deduction, it is not, for
  3333. that reason, perfectly manifest that such a deduction is absolutely
  3334. necessary. We have already traced to their sources the conceptions of
  3335. space and time, by means of a transcendental deduction, and we have
  3336. explained and determined their objective validity a priori. Geometry,
  3337. nevertheless, advances steadily and securely in the province of pure
  3338. a priori cognitions, without needing to ask from philosophy any
  3339. certificate as to the pure and legitimate origin of its fundamental
  3340. conception of space. But the use of the conception in this science
  3341. extends only to the external world of sense, the pure form of the
  3342. intuition of which is space; and in this world, therefore, all
  3343. geometrical cognition, because it is founded upon a priori intuition,
  3344. possesses immediate evidence, and the objects of this cognition are
  3345. given a priori (as regards their form) in intuition by and through the
  3346. cognition itself. With the pure conceptions of understanding, on the
  3347. contrary, commences the absolute necessity of seeking a transcendental
  3348. deduction, not only of these conceptions themselves, but likewise of
  3349. space, because, inasmuch as they make affirmations concerning objects
  3350. not by means of the predicates of intuition and sensibility, but of pure
  3351. thought a priori, they apply to objects without any of the conditions
  3352. of sensibility. Besides, not being founded on experience, they are not
  3353. presented with any object in a priori intuition upon which, antecedently
  3354. to experience, they might base their synthesis. Hence results, not only
  3355. doubt as to the objective validity and proper limits of their use, but
  3356. that even our conception of space is rendered equivocal; inasmuch as we
  3357. are very ready with the aid of the categories, to carry the use of this
  3358. conception beyond the conditions of sensuous intuition--and, for this
  3359. reason, we have already found a transcendental deduction of it needful.
  3360. The reader, then, must be quite convinced of the absolute necessity of
  3361. a transcendental deduction, before taking a single step in the field of
  3362. pure reason; because otherwise he goes to work blindly, and after he
  3363. has wondered about in all directions, returns to the state of utter
  3364. ignorance from which he started. He ought, moreover, clearly to
  3365. recognize beforehand the unavoidable difficulties in his undertaking,
  3366. so that he may not afterwards complain of the obscurity in which the
  3367. subject itself is deeply involved, or become too soon impatient of
  3368. the obstacles in his path; because we have a choice of only two
  3369. things--either at once to give up all pretensions to knowledge
  3370. beyond the limits of possible experience, or to bring this critical
  3371. investigation to completion.
  3372. We have been able, with very little trouble, to make it comprehensible
  3373. how the conceptions of space and time, although a priori cognitions,
  3374. must necessarily apply to external objects, and render a synthetical
  3375. cognition of these possible, independently of all experience. For
  3376. inasmuch as only by means of such pure form of sensibility an object can
  3377. appear to us, that is, be an object of empirical intuition, space and
  3378. time are pure intuitions, which contain a priori the condition of the
  3379. possibility of objects as phenomena, and an a priori synthesis in these
  3380. intuitions possesses objective validity.
  3381. On the other hand, the categories of the understanding do not represent
  3382. the conditions under which objects are given to us in intuition; objects
  3383. can consequently appear to us without necessarily connecting themselves
  3384. with these, and consequently without any necessity binding on the
  3385. understanding to contain a priori the conditions of these objects. Thus
  3386. we find ourselves involved in a difficulty which did not present itself
  3387. in the sphere of sensibility, that is to say, we cannot discover how the
  3388. subjective conditions of thought can have objective validity, in other
  3389. words, can become conditions of the possibility of all cognition of
  3390. objects; for phenomena may certainly be given to us in intuition without
  3391. any help from the functions of the understanding. Let us take, for
  3392. example, the conception of cause, which indicates a peculiar kind of
  3393. synthesis, namely, that with something, A, something entirely different,
  3394. B, is connected according to a law. It is not a priori manifest why
  3395. phenomena should contain anything of this kind (we are of course
  3396. debarred from appealing for proof to experience, for the objective
  3397. validity of this conception must be demonstrated a priori), and it hence
  3398. remains doubtful a priori, whether such a conception be not quite void
  3399. and without any corresponding object among phenomena. For that objects
  3400. of sensuous intuition must correspond to the formal conditions of
  3401. sensibility existing a priori in the mind is quite evident, from the
  3402. fact that without these they could not be objects for us; but that they
  3403. must also correspond to the conditions which understanding requires for
  3404. the synthetical unity of thought is an assertion, the grounds for
  3405. which are not so easily to be discovered. For phenomena might be so
  3406. constituted as not to correspond to the conditions of the unity of
  3407. thought; and all things might lie in such confusion that, for example,
  3408. nothing could be met with in the sphere of phenomena to suggest a law of
  3409. synthesis, and so correspond to the conception of cause and effect;
  3410. so that this conception would be quite void, null, and without
  3411. significance. Phenomena would nevertheless continue to present objects
  3412. to our intuition; for mere intuition does not in any respect stand in
  3413. need of the functions of thought.
  3414. If we thought to free ourselves from the labour of these investigations
  3415. by saying: "Experience is constantly offering us examples of the
  3416. relation of cause and effect in phenomena, and presents us with abundant
  3417. opportunity of abstracting the conception of cause, and so at the same
  3418. time of corroborating the objective validity of this conception"; we
  3419. should in this case be overlooking the fact, that the conception of
  3420. cause cannot arise in this way at all; that, on the contrary, it must
  3421. either have an a priori basis in the understanding, or be rejected as a
  3422. mere chimera. For this conception demands that something, A, should
  3423. be of such a nature that something else, B, should follow from it
  3424. necessarily, and according to an absolutely universal law. We may
  3425. certainly collect from phenomena a law, according to which this or that
  3426. usually happens, but the element of necessity is not to be found in it.
  3427. Hence it is evident that to the synthesis of cause and effect belongs a
  3428. dignity, which is utterly wanting in any empirical synthesis; for it is
  3429. no mere mechanical synthesis, by means of addition, but a dynamical one;
  3430. that is to say, the effect is not to be cogitated as merely annexed to
  3431. the cause, but as posited by and through the cause, and resulting from
  3432. it. The strict universality of this law never can be a characteristic
  3433. of empirical laws, which obtain through induction only a comparative
  3434. universality, that is, an extended range of practical application. But
  3435. the pure conceptions of the understanding would entirely lose all their
  3436. peculiar character, if we treated them merely as the productions of
  3437. experience.
  3438. SS 10. Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.
  3439. There are only two possible ways in which synthetical representation and
  3440. its objects can coincide with and relate necessarily to each other,
  3441. and, as it were, meet together. Either the object alone makes the
  3442. representation possible, or the representation alone makes the object
  3443. possible. In the former case, the relation between them is only
  3444. empirical, and an a priori representation is impossible. And this is the
  3445. case with phenomena, as regards that in them which is referable to mere
  3446. sensation. In the latter case--although representation alone (for of its
  3447. causality, by means of the will, we do not here speak) does not produce
  3448. the object as to its existence, it must nevertheless be a priori
  3449. determinative in regard to the object, if it is only by means of the
  3450. representation that we can cognize anything as an object. Now there
  3451. are only two conditions of the possibility of a cognition of objects;
  3452. firstly, intuition, by means of which the object, though only as
  3453. phenomenon, is given; secondly, conception, by means of which the object
  3454. which corresponds to this intuition is thought. But it is evident from
  3455. what has been said on aesthetic that the first condition, under which
  3456. alone objects can be intuited, must in fact exist, as a formal basis for
  3457. them, a priori in the mind. With this formal condition of sensibility,
  3458. therefore, all phenomena necessarily correspond, because it is
  3459. only through it that they can be phenomena at all; that is, can be
  3460. empirically intuited and given. Now the question is whether there do
  3461. not exist, a priori in the mind, conceptions of understanding also, as
  3462. conditions under which alone something, if not intuited, is yet thought
  3463. as object. If this question be answered in the affirmative, it follows
  3464. that all empirical cognition of objects is necessarily conformable to
  3465. such conceptions, since, if they are not presupposed, it is impossible
  3466. that anything can be an object of experience. Now all experience
  3467. contains, besides the intuition of the senses through which an object
  3468. is given, a conception also of an object that is given in intuition.
  3469. Accordingly, conceptions of objects in general must lie as a
  3470. priori conditions at the foundation of all empirical cognition; and
  3471. consequently, the objective validity of the categories, as a priori
  3472. conceptions, will rest upon this, that experience (as far as regards the
  3473. form of thought) is possible only by their means. For in that case they
  3474. apply necessarily and a priori to objects of experience, because only
  3475. through them can an object of experience be thought.
  3476. The whole aim of the transcendental deduction of all a priori
  3477. conceptions is to show that these conceptions are a priori conditions
  3478. of the possibility of all experience. Conceptions which afford us the
  3479. objective foundation of the possibility of experience are for that very
  3480. reason necessary. But the analysis of the experiences in which they are
  3481. met with is not deduction, but only an illustration of them, because
  3482. from experience they could never derive the attribute of necessity.
  3483. Without their original applicability and relation to all possible
  3484. experience, in which all objects of cognition present themselves, the
  3485. relation of the categories to objects, of whatever nature, would be
  3486. quite incomprehensible.
  3487. The celebrated Locke, for want of due reflection on these points, and
  3488. because he met with pure conceptions of the understanding in experience,
  3489. sought also to deduce them from experience, and yet proceeded so
  3490. inconsequently as to attempt, with their aid, to arrive it cognitions
  3491. which lie far beyond the limits of all experience. David Hume perceived
  3492. that, to render this possible, it was necessary that the conceptions
  3493. should have an a priori origin. But as he could not explain how it was
  3494. possible that conceptions which are not connected with each other in the
  3495. understanding must nevertheless be thought as necessarily connected in
  3496. the object--and it never occurred to him that the understanding itself
  3497. might, perhaps, by means of these conceptions, be the author of the
  3498. experience in which its objects were presented to it--he was forced
  3499. to drive these conceptions from experience, that is, from a subjective
  3500. necessity arising from repeated association of experiences erroneously
  3501. considered to be objective--in one word, from habit. But he proceeded
  3502. with perfect consequence and declared it to be impossible, with such
  3503. conceptions and the principles arising from them, to overstep the limits
  3504. of experience. The empirical derivation, however, which both of these
  3505. philosophers attributed to these conceptions, cannot possibly be
  3506. reconciled with the fact that we do possess scientific a priori
  3507. cognitions, namely, those of pure mathematics and general physics.
  3508. The former of these two celebrated men opened a wide door to
  3509. extravagance--(for if reason has once undoubted right on its side,
  3510. it will not allow itself to be confined to set limits, by vague
  3511. recommendations of moderation); the latter gave himself up entirely
  3512. to scepticism--a natural consequence, after having discovered, as he
  3513. thought, that the faculty of cognition was not trustworthy. We now
  3514. intend to make a trial whether it be not possible safely to conduct
  3515. reason between these two rocks, to assign her determinate limits, and
  3516. yet leave open for her the entire sphere of her legitimate activity.
  3517. I shall merely premise an explanation of what the categories are. They
  3518. are conceptions of an object in general, by means of which its intuition
  3519. is contemplated as determined in relation to one of the logical
  3520. functions of judgement. The following will make this plain. The function
  3521. of the categorical judgement is that of the relation of subject to
  3522. predicate; for example, in the proposition: "All bodies are divisible."
  3523. But in regard to the merely logical use of the understanding, it still
  3524. remains undetermined to which Of these two conceptions belongs the
  3525. function Of subject and to which that of predicate. For we could also
  3526. say: "Some divisible is a body." But the category of substance, when
  3527. the conception of a body is brought under it, determines that; and its
  3528. empirical intuition in experience must be contemplated always as subject
  3529. and never as mere predicate. And so with all the other categories.
  3530. SS 11. SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of
  3531. the Understanding.
  3532. Of the Possibility of a Conjunction of the manifold representations
  3533. given by Sense.
  3534. The manifold content in our representations can be given in an intuition
  3535. which is merely sensuous--in other words, is nothing but susceptibility;
  3536. and the form of this intuition can exist a priori in our faculty of
  3537. representation, without being anything else but the mode in which the
  3538. subject is affected. But the conjunction (conjunctio) of a manifold in
  3539. intuition never can be given us by the senses; it cannot therefore
  3540. be contained in the pure form of sensuous intuition, for it is a
  3541. spontaneous act of the faculty of representation. And as we must, to
  3542. distinguish it from sensibility, entitle this faculty understanding; so
  3543. all conjunction whether conscious or unconscious, be it of the manifold
  3544. in intuition, sensuous or non-sensuous, or of several conceptions--is
  3545. an act of the understanding. To this act we shall give the general
  3546. appellation of synthesis, thereby to indicate, at the same time, that
  3547. we cannot represent anything as conjoined in the object without having
  3548. previously conjoined it ourselves. Of all mental notions, that of
  3549. conjunction is the only one which cannot be given through objects, but
  3550. can be originated only by the subject itself, because it is an act of
  3551. its purely spontaneous activity. The reader will easily enough perceive
  3552. that the possibility of conjunction must be grounded in the very nature
  3553. of this act, and that it must be equally valid for all conjunction, and
  3554. that analysis, which appears to be its contrary, must, nevertheless,
  3555. always presuppose it; for where the understanding has not previously
  3556. conjoined, it cannot dissect or analyse, because only as conjoined by
  3557. it, must that which is to be analysed have been given to our faculty of
  3558. representation.
  3559. But the conception of conjunction includes, besides the conception of
  3560. the manifold and of the synthesis of it, that of the unity of it also.
  3561. Conjunction is the representation of the synthetical unity of the
  3562. manifold.* This idea of unity, therefore, cannot arise out of that of
  3563. conjunction; much rather does that idea, by combining itself with the
  3564. representation of the manifold, render the conception of conjunction
  3565. possible. This unity, which a priori precedes all conceptions of
  3566. conjunction, is not the category of unity (SS 6); for all the categories
  3567. are based upon logical functions of judgement, and in these functions we
  3568. already have conjunction, and consequently unity of given conceptions.
  3569. It is therefore evident that the category of unity presupposes
  3570. conjunction. We must therefore look still higher for this unity (as
  3571. qualitative, SS 8), in that, namely, which contains the ground of the
  3572. unity of diverse conceptions in judgements, the ground, consequently, of
  3573. the possibility of the existence of the understanding, even in regard to
  3574. its logical use.
  3575. [*Footnote: Whether the representations are in themselves
  3576. identical, and consequently whether one can be thought
  3577. analytically by means of and through the other, is a
  3578. question which we need not at present consider. Our
  3579. Consciousness of the one, when we speak of the manifold, is
  3580. always distinguishable from our consciousness of the other;
  3581. and it is only respecting the synthesis of this (possible)
  3582. consciousness that we here treat.]
  3583. SS 12. Of the Originally Synthetical Unity of Apperception.
  3584. The "I think" must accompany all my representations, for otherwise
  3585. something would be represented in me which could not be thought; in
  3586. other words, the representation would either be impossible, or at least
  3587. be, in relation to me, nothing. That representation which can be given
  3588. previously to all thought is called intuition. All the diversity or
  3589. manifold content of intuition, has, therefore, a necessary relation to
  3590. the "I think," in the subject in which this diversity is found. But this
  3591. representation, "I think," is an act of spontaneity; that is to say,
  3592. it cannot be regarded as belonging to mere sensibility. I call it pure
  3593. apperception, in order to distinguish it from empirical; or primitive
  3594. apperception, because it is self-consciousness which, whilst it gives
  3595. birth to the representation "I think," must necessarily be capable of
  3596. accompanying all our representations. It is in all acts of consciousness
  3597. one and the same, and unaccompanied by it, no representation can exist
  3598. for me. The unity of this apperception I call the transcendental unity
  3599. of self-consciousness, in order to indicate the possibility of a priori
  3600. cognition arising from it. For the manifold representations which are
  3601. given in an intuition would not all of them be my representations,
  3602. if they did not all belong to one self-consciousness, that is, as my
  3603. representations (even although I am not conscious of them as such), they
  3604. must conform to the condition under which alone they can exist together
  3605. in a common self-consciousness, because otherwise they would not all
  3606. without exception belong to me. From this primitive conjunction follow
  3607. many important results.
  3608. For example, this universal identity of the apperception of the manifold
  3609. given in intuition contains a synthesis of representations and is
  3610. possible only by means of the consciousness of this synthesis. For the
  3611. empirical consciousness which accompanies different representations
  3612. is in itself fragmentary and disunited, and without relation to the
  3613. identity of the subject. This relation, then, does not exist because I
  3614. accompany every representation with consciousness, but because I join
  3615. one representation to another, and am conscious of the synthesis of
  3616. them. Consequently, only because I can connect a variety of given
  3617. representations in one consciousness, is it possible that I
  3618. can represent to myself the identity of consciousness in these
  3619. representations; in other words, the analytical unity of apperception
  3620. is possible only under the presupposition of a synthetical unity.* The
  3621. thought, "These representations given in intuition belong all of them
  3622. to me," is accordingly just the same as, "I unite them in one
  3623. self-consciousness, or can at least so unite them"; and although
  3624. this thought is not itself the consciousness of the synthesis of
  3625. representations, it presupposes the possibility of it; that is to
  3626. say, for the reason alone that I can comprehend the variety of my
  3627. representations in one consciousness, do I call them my representations,
  3628. for otherwise I must have as many-coloured and various a self as are
  3629. the representations of which I am conscious. Synthetical unity of the
  3630. manifold in intuitions, as given a priori, is therefore the foundation
  3631. of the identity of apperception itself, which antecedes a priori all
  3632. determinate thought. But the conjunction of representations into a
  3633. conception is not to be found in objects themselves, nor can it be,
  3634. as it were, borrowed from them and taken up into the understanding by
  3635. perception, but it is on the contrary an operation of the understanding
  3636. itself, which is nothing more than the faculty of conjoining a priori
  3637. and of bringing the variety of given representations under the unity of
  3638. apperception. This principle is the highest in all human cognition.
  3639. [*Footnote: All general conceptions--as such--depend, for
  3640. their existence, on the analytical unity of consciousness.
  3641. For example, when I think of red in general, I thereby think
  3642. to myself a property which (as a characteristic mark) can be
  3643. discovered somewhere, or can be united with other
  3644. representations; consequently, it is only by means of a
  3645. forethought possible synthetical unity that I can think to
  3646. myself the analytical. A representation which is cogitated
  3647. as common to different representations, is regarded as
  3648. belonging to such as, besides this common representation,
  3649. contain something different; consequently it must be
  3650. previously thought in synthetical unity with other although
  3651. only possible representations, before I can think in it the
  3652. analytical unity of consciousness which makes it a conceptas
  3653. communis. And thus the synthetical unity of apperception is
  3654. the highest point with which we must connect every operation
  3655. of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and after it
  3656. our transcendental philosophy; indeed, this faculty is the
  3657. understanding itself.]
  3658. This fundamental principle of the necessary unity of apperception is
  3659. indeed an identical, and therefore analytical, proposition; but it
  3660. nevertheless explains the necessity for a synthesis of the manifold
  3661. given in an intuition, without which the identity of self-consciousness
  3662. would be incogitable. For the ego, as a simple representation, presents
  3663. us with no manifold content; only in intuition, which is quite different
  3664. from the representation ego, can it be given us, and by means of
  3665. conjunction it is cogitated in one self-consciousness. An understanding,
  3666. in which all the manifold should be given by means of consciousness
  3667. itself, would be intuitive; our understanding can only think and must
  3668. look for its intuition to sense. I am, therefore, conscious of my
  3669. identical self, in relation to all the variety of representations given
  3670. to me in an intuition, because I call all of them my representations. In
  3671. other words, I am conscious myself of a necessary a priori synthesis of
  3672. my representations, which is called the original synthetical unity of
  3673. apperception, under which rank all the representations presented to me,
  3674. but that only by means of a synthesis.
  3675. SS 13. The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception is the
  3676. highest Principle of all exercise of the Understanding.
  3677. The supreme principle of the possibility of all intuition in relation to
  3678. sensibility was, according to our transcendental aesthetic, that all the
  3679. manifold in intuition be subject to the formal conditions of space and
  3680. time. The supreme principle of the possibility of it in relation to the
  3681. understanding is that all the manifold in it be subject to conditions
  3682. of the originally synthetical unity or apperception.* To the former
  3683. of these two principles are subject all the various representations of
  3684. intuition, in so far as they are given to us; to the latter, in so far
  3685. as they must be capable of conjunction in one consciousness; for
  3686. without this nothing can be thought or cognized, because the given
  3687. representations would not have in common the act Of the apperception "I
  3688. think" and therefore could not be connected in one self-consciousness.
  3689. [*Footnote: Space and time, and all portions thereof, are
  3690. intuitions; consequently are, with a manifold for their
  3691. content, single representations. (See the Transcendental
  3692. Aesthetic.) Consequently, they are not pure conceptions, by
  3693. means of which the same consciousness is found in a great
  3694. number of representations; but, on the contrary, they are
  3695. many representations contained in one, the consciousness of
  3696. which is, so to speak, compounded. The unity of
  3697. consciousness is nevertheless synthetical and, therefore,
  3698. primitive. From this peculiar character of consciousness
  3699. follow many important consequences. (See SS 21.)]
  3700. Understanding is, to speak generally, the faculty Of cognitions. These
  3701. consist in the determined relation of given representation to an object.
  3702. But an object is that, in the conception of which the manifold in a
  3703. given intuition is united. Now all union of representations requires
  3704. unity of consciousness in the synthesis of them. Consequently, it is
  3705. the unity of consciousness alone that constitutes the possibility of
  3706. representations relating to an object, and therefore of their objective
  3707. validity, and of their becoming cognitions, and consequently, the
  3708. possibility of the existence of the understanding itself.
  3709. The first pure cognition of understanding, then, upon which is founded
  3710. all its other exercise, and which is at the same time perfectly
  3711. independent of all conditions of mere sensuous intuition, is the
  3712. principle of the original synthetical unity of apperception. Thus the
  3713. mere form of external sensuous intuition, namely, space, affords us,
  3714. per se, no cognition; it merely contributes the manifold in a priori
  3715. intuition to a possible cognition. But, in order to cognize something
  3716. in space (for example, a line), I must draw it, and thus produce
  3717. synthetically a determined conjunction of the given manifold, so that
  3718. the unity of this act is at the same time the unity of consciousness
  3719. (in the conception of a line), and by this means alone is an object (a
  3720. determinate space) cognized. The synthetical unity of consciousness
  3721. is, therefore, an objective condition of all cognition, which I do
  3722. not merely require in order to cognize an object, but to which every
  3723. intuition must necessarily be subject, in order to become an object for
  3724. me; because in any other way, and without this synthesis, the manifold
  3725. in intuition could not be united in one consciousness.
  3726. This proposition is, as already said, itself analytical, although it
  3727. constitutes the synthetical unity, the condition of all thought; for
  3728. it states nothing more than that all my representations in any given
  3729. intuition must be subject to the condition which alone enables me to
  3730. connect them, as my representation with the identical self, and so to
  3731. unite them synthetically in one apperception, by means of the general
  3732. expression, "I think."
  3733. But this principle is not to be regarded as a principle for every
  3734. possible understanding, but only for the understanding by means of whose
  3735. pure apperception in the thought I am, no manifold content is given. The
  3736. understanding or mind which contained the manifold in intuition, in and
  3737. through the act itself of its own self-consciousness, in other words, an
  3738. understanding by and in the representation of which the objects of
  3739. the representation should at the same time exist, would not require a
  3740. special act of synthesis of the manifold as the condition of the unity
  3741. of its consciousness, an act of which the human understanding, which
  3742. thinks only and cannot intuite, has absolute need. But this principle is
  3743. the first principle of all the operations of our understanding, so that
  3744. we cannot form the least conception of any other possible understanding,
  3745. either of one such as should be itself intuition, or possess a sensuous
  3746. intuition, but with forms different from those of space and time.
  3747. SS 14. What Objective Unity of Self-consciousness is.
  3748. It is by means of the transcendental unity of apperception that all
  3749. the manifold, given in an intuition is united into a conception of
  3750. the object. On this account it is called objective, and must be
  3751. distinguished from the subjective unity of consciousness, which is a
  3752. determination of the internal sense, by means of which the said manifold
  3753. in intuition is given empirically to be so united. Whether I can be
  3754. empirically conscious of the manifold as coexistent or as successive,
  3755. depends upon circumstances, or empirical conditions. Hence the empirical
  3756. unity of consciousness by means of association of representations,
  3757. itself relates to a phenomenal world and is wholly contingent. On the
  3758. contrary, the pure form of intuition in time, merely as an intuition,
  3759. which contains a given manifold, is subject to the original unity of
  3760. consciousness, and that solely by means of the necessary relation of
  3761. the manifold in intuition to the "I think," consequently by means of
  3762. the pure synthesis of the understanding, which lies a priori at the
  3763. foundation of all empirical synthesis. The transcendental unity of
  3764. apperception is alone objectively valid; the empirical which we do not
  3765. consider in this essay, and which is merely a unity deduced from the
  3766. former under given conditions in concreto, possesses only subjective
  3767. validity. One person connects the notion conveyed in a word with one
  3768. thing, another with another thing; and the unity of consciousness in
  3769. that which is empirical, is, in relation to that which is given by
  3770. experience, not necessarily and universally valid.
  3771. SS 15. The Logical Form of all Judgements consists in the Objective
  3772. Unity of Apperception of the Conceptions contained therein.
  3773. I could never satisfy myself with the definition which logicians give of
  3774. a judgement. It is, according to them, the representation of a relation
  3775. between two conceptions. I shall not dwell here on the faultiness of
  3776. this definition, in that it suits only for categorical and not for
  3777. hypothetical or disjunctive judgements, these latter containing a
  3778. relation not of conceptions but of judgements themselves--a blunder from
  3779. which many evil results have followed.* It is more important for our
  3780. present purpose to observe, that this definition does not determine in
  3781. what the said relation consists.
  3782. [*Footnote: The tedious doctrine of the four syllogistic
  3783. figures concerns only categorical syllogisms; and although
  3784. it is nothing more than an artifice by surreptitiously
  3785. introducing immediate conclusions (consequentiae immediatae)
  3786. among the premises of a pure syllogism, to give ism' give
  3787. rise to an appearance of more modes of drawing a conclusion
  3788. than that in the first figure, the artifice would not have
  3789. had much success, had not its authors succeeded in bringing
  3790. categorical judgements into exclusive respect, as those to
  3791. which all others must be referred--a doctrine, however,
  3792. which, according to SS 5, is utterly false.]
  3793. But if I investigate more closely the relation of given cognitions in
  3794. every judgement, and distinguish it, as belonging to the understanding,
  3795. from the relation which is produced according to laws of the
  3796. reproductive imagination (which has only subjective validity), I find
  3797. that judgement is nothing but the mode of bringing given cognitions
  3798. under the objective unit of apperception. This is plain from our use
  3799. of the term of relation is in judgements, in order to distinguish the
  3800. objective unity of given representations from the subjective unity.
  3801. For this term indicates the relation of these representations to the
  3802. original apperception, and also their necessary unity, even although the
  3803. judgement is empirical, therefore contingent, as in the judgement: "All
  3804. bodies are heavy." I do not mean by this, that these representations
  3805. do necessarily belong to each other in empirical intuition, but that by
  3806. means of the necessary unity of appreciation they belong to each other
  3807. in the synthesis of intuitions, that is to say, they belong to each
  3808. other according to principles of the objective determination of all
  3809. our representations, in so far as cognition can arise from them,
  3810. these principles being all deduced from the main principle of the
  3811. transcendental unity of apperception. In this way alone can there arise
  3812. from this relation a judgement, that is, a relation which has objective
  3813. validity, and is perfectly distinct from that relation of the very same
  3814. representations which has only subjective validity--a relation, to wit,
  3815. which is produced according to laws of association. According to these
  3816. laws, I could only say: "When I hold in my hand or carry a body, I feel
  3817. an impression of weight"; but I could not say: "It, the body, is
  3818. heavy"; for this is tantamount to saying both these representations
  3819. are conjoined in the object, that is, without distinction as to the
  3820. condition of the subject, and do not merely stand together in my
  3821. perception, however frequently the perceptive act may be repeated.
  3822. SS 16. All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as
  3823. Conditions under which alone the manifold Content of them can be united
  3824. in one Consciousness.
  3825. The manifold content given in a sensuous intuition comes necessarily
  3826. under the original synthetical unity of apperception, because thereby
  3827. alone is the unity of intuition possible (SS 13). But that act of the
  3828. understanding, by which the manifold content of given representations
  3829. (whether intuitions or conceptions) is brought under one apperception,
  3830. is the logical function of judgements (SS 15). All the manifold,
  3831. therefore, in so far as it is given in one empirical intuition, is
  3832. determined in relation to one of the logical functions of judgement, by
  3833. means of which it is brought into union in one consciousness. Now the
  3834. categories are nothing else than these functions of judgement so far as
  3835. the manifold in a given intuition is determined in relation to them
  3836. (SS 9). Consequently, the manifold in a given intuition is necessarily
  3837. subject to the categories of the understanding.
  3838. SS 17. Observation.
  3839. The manifold in an intuition, which I call mine, is represented by means
  3840. of the synthesis of the understanding, as belonging to the necessary
  3841. unity of self-consciousness, and this takes place by means of the
  3842. category.* The category indicates accordingly that the empirical
  3843. consciousness of a given manifold in an intuition is subject to a
  3844. pure self-consciousness a priori, in the same manner as an empirical
  3845. intuition is subject to a pure sensuous intuition, which is also
  3846. a priori. In the above proposition, then, lies the beginning of a
  3847. deduction of the pure conceptions of the understanding. Now, as the
  3848. categories have their origin in the understanding alone, independently
  3849. of sensibility, I must in my deduction make abstraction of the mode in
  3850. which the manifold of an empirical intuition is given, in order to
  3851. fix my attention exclusively on the unity which is brought by the
  3852. understanding into the intuition by means of the category. In what
  3853. follows (SS 22), it will be shown, from the mode in which the empirical
  3854. intuition is given in the faculty of sensibility, that the unity which
  3855. belongs to it is no other than that which the category (according to SS
  3856. 16) imposes on the manifold in a given intuition, and thus, its a
  3857. priori validity in regard to all objects of sense being established, the
  3858. purpose of our deduction will be fully attained.
  3859. [*Footnote: The proof of this rests on the represented unity
  3860. of intuition, by means of which an object is given, and
  3861. which always includes in itself a synthesis of the manifold
  3862. to be intuited, and also the relation of this latter to
  3863. unity of apperception.]
  3864. But there is one thing in the above demonstration of which I could not
  3865. make abstraction, namely, that the manifold to be intuited must be given
  3866. previously to the synthesis of the understanding, and independently of
  3867. it. How this takes place remains here undetermined. For if I cogitate
  3868. an understanding which was itself intuitive (as, for example, a divine
  3869. understanding which should not represent given objects, but by whose
  3870. representation the objects themselves should be given or produced), the
  3871. categories would possess no significance in relation to such a faculty
  3872. of cognition. They are merely rules for an understanding, whose whole
  3873. power consists in thought, that is, in the act of submitting the
  3874. synthesis of the manifold which is presented to it in intuition from
  3875. a very different quarter, to the unity of apperception; a faculty,
  3876. therefore, which cognizes nothing per se, but only connects and
  3877. arranges the material of cognition, the intuition, namely, which must
  3878. be presented to it by means of the object. But to show reasons for this
  3879. peculiar character of our understandings, that it produces unity of
  3880. apperception a priori only by means of categories, and a certain kind
  3881. and number thereof, is as impossible as to explain why we are endowed
  3882. with precisely so many functions of judgement and no more, or why time
  3883. and space are the only forms of our intuition.
  3884. SS 18. In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is
  3885. the only legitimate use of the Category.
  3886. To think an object and to cognize an object are by no means the same
  3887. thing. In cognition there are two elements: firstly, the conception,
  3888. whereby an object is cogitated (the category); and, secondly, the
  3889. intuition, whereby the object is given. For supposing that to the
  3890. conception a corresponding intuition could not be given, it would
  3891. still be a thought as regards its form, but without any object, and no
  3892. cognition of anything would be possible by means of it, inasmuch as, so
  3893. far as I knew, there existed and could exist nothing to which my
  3894. thought could be applied. Now all intuition possible to us is sensuous;
  3895. consequently, our thought of an object by means of a pure conception of
  3896. the understanding, can become cognition for us only in so far as this
  3897. conception is applied to objects of the senses. Sensuous intuition is
  3898. either pure intuition (space and time) or empirical intuition--of that
  3899. which is immediately represented in space and time by means of sensation
  3900. as real. Through the determination of pure intuition we obtain a priori
  3901. cognitions of objects, as in mathematics, but only as regards their form
  3902. as phenomena; whether there can exist things which must be intuited
  3903. in this form is not thereby established. All mathematical conceptions,
  3904. therefore, are not per se cognition, except in so far as we presuppose
  3905. that there exist things which can only be represented conformably to the
  3906. form of our pure sensuous intuition. But things in space and time
  3907. are given only in so far as they are perceptions (representations
  3908. accompanied with sensation), therefore only by empirical representation.
  3909. Consequently the pure conceptions of the understanding, even when
  3910. they are applied to intuitions a priori (as in mathematics), produce
  3911. cognition only in so far as these (and therefore the conceptions of the
  3912. understanding by means of them) can be applied to empirical intuitions.
  3913. Consequently the categories do not, even by means of pure intuition
  3914. afford us any cognition of things; they can only do so in so far as they
  3915. can be applied to empirical intuition. That is to say, the categories
  3916. serve only to render empirical cognition possible. But this is what
  3917. we call experience. Consequently, in cognition, their application to
  3918. objects of experience is the only legitimate use of the categories.
  3919. SS 19.
  3920. The foregoing proposition is of the utmost importance, for it determines
  3921. the limits of the exercise of the pure conceptions of the understanding
  3922. in regard to objects, just as transcendental aesthetic determined the
  3923. limits of the exercise of the pure form of our sensuous intuition.
  3924. Space and time, as conditions of the possibility of the presentation
  3925. of objects to us, are valid no further than for objects of sense,
  3926. consequently, only for experience. Beyond these limits they represent
  3927. to us nothing, for they belong only to sense, and have no reality apart
  3928. from it. The pure conceptions of the understanding are free from this
  3929. limitation, and extend to objects of intuition in general, be the
  3930. intuition like or unlike to ours, provided only it be sensuous, and not
  3931. intellectual. But this extension of conceptions beyond the range of our
  3932. intuition is of no advantage; for they are then mere empty conceptions
  3933. of objects, as to the possibility or impossibility of the existence of
  3934. which they furnish us with no means of discovery. They are mere forms
  3935. of thought, without objective reality, because we have no intuition to
  3936. which the synthetical unity of apperception, which alone the categories
  3937. contain, could be applied, for the purpose of determining an object. Our
  3938. sensuous and empirical intuition can alone give them significance and
  3939. meaning.
  3940. If, then, we suppose an object of a non-sensuous intuition to be given
  3941. we can in that case represent it by all those predicates which are
  3942. implied in the presupposition that nothing appertaining to sensuous
  3943. intuition belongs to it; for example, that it is not extended, or in
  3944. space; that its duration is not time; that in it no change (the effect
  3945. of the determinations in time) is to be met with, and so on. But it
  3946. is no proper knowledge if I merely indicate what the intuition of the
  3947. object is not, without being able to say what is contained in it, for I
  3948. have not shown the possibility of an object to which my pure conception
  3949. of understanding could be applicable, because I have not been able to
  3950. furnish any intuition corresponding to it, but am only able to say that
  3951. our intuition is not valid for it. But the most important point is
  3952. this, that to a something of this kind not one category can be found
  3953. applicable. Take, for example, the conception of substance, that is,
  3954. something that can exist as subject, but never as mere predicate; in
  3955. regard to this conception I am quite ignorant whether there can really
  3956. be anything to correspond to such a determination of thought, if
  3957. empirical intuition did not afford me the occasion for its application.
  3958. But of this more in the sequel.
  3959. SS 20. Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the
  3960. Senses in general.
  3961. The pure conceptions of the understanding apply to objects of intuition
  3962. in general, through the understanding alone, whether the intuition be
  3963. our own or some other, provided only it be sensuous, but are, for
  3964. this very reason, mere forms of thought, by means of which alone no
  3965. determined object can be cognized. The synthesis or conjunction of the
  3966. manifold in these conceptions relates, we have said, only to the unity
  3967. of apperception, and is for this reason the ground of the possibility
  3968. of a priori cognition, in so far as this cognition is dependent on the
  3969. understanding. This synthesis is, therefore, not merely transcendental,
  3970. but also purely intellectual. But because a certain form of sensuous
  3971. intuition exists in the mind a priori which rests on the receptivity
  3972. of the representative faculty (sensibility), the understanding, as a
  3973. spontaneity, is able to determine the internal sense by means of the
  3974. diversity of given representations, conformably to the synthetical
  3975. unity of apperception, and thus to cogitate the synthetical unity of
  3976. the apperception of the manifold of sensuous intuition a priori, as the
  3977. condition to which must necessarily be submitted all objects of human
  3978. intuition. And in this manner the categories as mere forms of thought
  3979. receive objective reality, that is, application to objects which are
  3980. given to us in intuition, but that only as phenomena, for it is only of
  3981. phenomena that we are capable of a priori intuition.
  3982. This synthesis of the manifold of sensuous intuition, which is possible
  3983. and necessary a priori, may be called figurative (synthesis speciosa),
  3984. in contradistinction to that which is cogitated in the mere category
  3985. in regard to the manifold of an intuition in general, and is
  3986. called connection or conjunction of the understanding (synthesis
  3987. intellectualis). Both are transcendental, not merely because they
  3988. themselves precede a priori all experience, but also because they form
  3989. the basis for the possibility of other cognition a priori.
  3990. But the figurative synthesis, when it has relation only to the
  3991. originally synthetical unity of apperception, that is to the
  3992. transcendental unity cogitated in the categories, must, to be
  3993. distinguished from the purely intellectual conjunction, be entitled the
  3994. transcendental synthesis of imagination. Imagination is the faculty of
  3995. representing an object even without its presence in intuition. Now, as
  3996. all our intuition is sensuous, imagination, by reason of the subjective
  3997. condition under which alone it can give a corresponding intuition to the
  3998. conceptions of the understanding, belongs to sensibility. But in so far
  3999. as the synthesis of the imagination is an act of spontaneity, which is
  4000. determinative, and not, like sense, merely determinable, and which is
  4001. consequently able to determine sense a priori, according to its form,
  4002. conformably to the unity of apperception, in so far is the imagination
  4003. a faculty of determining sensibility a priori, and its synthesis of
  4004. intuitions according to the categories must be the transcendental
  4005. synthesis of the imagination. It is an operation of the understanding on
  4006. sensibility, and the first application of the understanding to objects
  4007. of possible intuition, and at the same time the basis for the
  4008. exercise of the other functions of that faculty. As figurative, it is
  4009. distinguished from the merely intellectual synthesis, which is produced
  4010. by the understanding alone, without the aid of imagination. Now, in
  4011. so far as imagination is spontaneity, I sometimes call it also the
  4012. productive imagination, and distinguish it from the reproductive, the
  4013. synthesis of which is subject entirely to empirical laws, those of
  4014. association, namely, and which, therefore, contributes nothing to the
  4015. explanation of the possibility of a priori cognition, and for this
  4016. reason belongs not to transcendental philosophy, but to psychology.
  4017. We have now arrived at the proper place for explaining the paradox which
  4018. must have struck every one in our exposition of the internal sense (SS
  4019. 6), namely--how this sense represents us to our own consciousness, only
  4020. as we appear to ourselves, not as we are in ourselves, because, to wit,
  4021. we intuite ourselves only as we are inwardly affected. Now this appears
  4022. to be contradictory, inasmuch as we thus stand in a passive relation
  4023. to ourselves; and therefore in the systems of psychology, the internal
  4024. sense is commonly held to be one with the faculty of apperception, while
  4025. we, on the contrary, carefully distinguish them.
  4026. That which determines the internal sense is the understanding, and its
  4027. original power of conjoining the manifold of intuition, that is, of
  4028. bringing this under an apperception (upon which rests the possibility
  4029. of the understanding itself). Now, as the human understanding is not in
  4030. itself a faculty of intuition, and is unable to exercise such a power,
  4031. in order to conjoin, as it were, the manifold of its own intuition, the
  4032. synthesis of understanding is, considered per se, nothing but the unity
  4033. of action, of which, as such, it is self-conscious, even apart from
  4034. sensibility, by which, moreover, it is able to determine our internal
  4035. sense in respect of the manifold which may be presented to it
  4036. according to the form of sensuous intuition. Thus, under the name of a
  4037. transcendental synthesis of imagination, the understanding exercises an
  4038. activity upon the passive subject, whose faculty it is; and so we
  4039. are right in saying that the internal sense is affected thereby.
  4040. Apperception and its synthetical unity are by no means one and the
  4041. same with the internal sense. The former, as the source of all our
  4042. synthetical conjunction, applies, under the name of the categories, to
  4043. the manifold of intuition in general, prior to all sensuous intuition of
  4044. objects. The internal sense, on the contrary, contains merely the form
  4045. of intuition, but without any synthetical conjunction of the manifold
  4046. therein, and consequently does not contain any determined intuition,
  4047. which is possible only through consciousness of the determination of
  4048. the manifold by the transcendental act of the imagination (synthetical
  4049. influence of the understanding on the internal sense), which I have
  4050. named figurative synthesis.
  4051. This we can indeed always perceive in ourselves. We cannot cogitate a
  4052. geometrical line without drawing it in thought, nor a circle without
  4053. describing it, nor represent the three dimensions of space without
  4054. drawing three lines from the same point perpendicular to one another. We
  4055. cannot even cogitate time, unless, in drawing a straight line (which is
  4056. to serve as the external figurative representation of time), we fix
  4057. our attention on the act of the synthesis of the manifold, whereby we
  4058. determine successively the internal sense, and thus attend also to the
  4059. succession of this determination. Motion as an act of the subject (not
  4060. as a determination of an object),* consequently the synthesis of the
  4061. manifold in space, if we make abstraction of space and attend merely to
  4062. the act by which we determine the internal sense according to its form,
  4063. is that which produces the conception of succession. The understanding,
  4064. therefore, does by no means find in the internal sense any such
  4065. synthesis of the manifold, but produces it, in that it affects this
  4066. sense. At the same time, how "I who think" is distinct from the "I"
  4067. which intuites itself (other modes of intuition being cogitable as at
  4068. least possible), and yet one and the same with this latter as the same
  4069. subject; how, therefore, I am able to say: "I, as an intelligence and
  4070. thinking subject, cognize myself as an object thought, so far as I am,
  4071. moreover, given to myself in intuition--only, like other phenomena, not
  4072. as I am in myself, and as considered by the understanding, but merely as
  4073. I appear"--is a question that has in it neither more nor less difficulty
  4074. than the question--"How can I be an object to myself?" or this--"How I
  4075. can be an object of my own intuition and internal perceptions?" But that
  4076. such must be the fact, if we admit that space is merely a pure form
  4077. of the phenomena of external sense, can be clearly proved by the
  4078. consideration that we cannot represent time, which is not an object of
  4079. external intuition, in any other way than under the image of a line,
  4080. which we draw in thought, a mode of representation without which we
  4081. could not cognize the unity of its dimension, and also that we are
  4082. necessitated to take our determination of periods of time, or of points
  4083. of time, for all our internal perceptions from the changes which
  4084. we perceive in outward things. It follows that we must arrange the
  4085. determinations of the internal sense, as phenomena in time, exactly in
  4086. the same manner as we arrange those of the external senses in space. And
  4087. consequently, if we grant, respecting this latter, that by means of them
  4088. we know objects only in so far as we are affected externally, we must
  4089. also confess, with regard to the internal sense, that by means of it we
  4090. intuite ourselves only as we are internally affected by ourselves; in
  4091. other words, as regards internal intuition, we cognize our own subject
  4092. only as phenomenon, and not as it is in itself.**
  4093. [*Footnote: Motion of an object in space does not belong to
  4094. a pure science, consequently not to geometry; because, that
  4095. a thing is movable cannot be known a priori, but only from
  4096. experience. But motion, considered as the description of a
  4097. space, is a pure act of the successive synthesis of the
  4098. manifold in external intuition by means of productive
  4099. imagination, and belongs not only to geometry, but even to
  4100. transcendental philosophy.]
  4101. [**Footnote: I do not see why so much difficulty should be
  4102. found in admitting that our internal sense is affected by
  4103. ourselves. Every act of attention exemplifies it. In such an
  4104. act the understanding determines the internal sense by the
  4105. synthetical conjunction which it cogitates, conformably to
  4106. the internal intuition which corresponds to the manifold in
  4107. the synthesis of the understanding. How much the mind is
  4108. usually affected thereby every one will be able to perceive
  4109. in himself.]
  4110. SS 21.
  4111. On the other hand, in the transcendental synthesis of the manifold
  4112. content of representations, consequently in the synthetical unity of
  4113. apperception, I am conscious of myself, not as I appear to myself,
  4114. nor as I am in myself, but only that "I am." This representation is a
  4115. thought, not an intuition. Now, as in order to cognize ourselves, in
  4116. addition to the act of thinking, which subjects the manifold of every
  4117. possible intuition to the unity of apperception, there is necessary a
  4118. determinate mode of intuition, whereby this manifold is given; although
  4119. my own existence is certainly not mere phenomenon (much less mere
  4120. illusion), the determination of my existence* Can only take place
  4121. conformably to the form of the internal sense, according to the
  4122. particular mode in which the manifold which I conjoin is given in
  4123. internal intuition, and I have therefore no knowledge of myself as I am,
  4124. but merely as I appear to myself. The consciousness of self is thus
  4125. very far from a knowledge of self, in which I do not use the categories,
  4126. whereby I cogitate an object, by means of the conjunction of the
  4127. manifold in one apperception. In the same way as I require, for the sake
  4128. of the cognition of an object distinct from myself, not only the thought
  4129. of an object in general (in the category), but also an intuition
  4130. by which to determine that general conception, in the same way do I
  4131. require, in order to the cognition of myself, not only the consciousness
  4132. of myself or the thought that I think myself, but in addition an
  4133. intuition of the manifold in myself, by which to determine this thought.
  4134. It is true that I exist as an intelligence which is conscious only of
  4135. its faculty of conjunction or synthesis, but subjected in relation to
  4136. the manifold which this intelligence has to conjoin to a limitative
  4137. conjunction called the internal sense. My intelligence (that is, I) can
  4138. render that conjunction or synthesis perceptible only according to
  4139. the relations of time, which are quite beyond the proper sphere of the
  4140. conceptions of the understanding and consequently cognize itself in
  4141. respect to an intuition (which cannot possibly be intellectual, nor
  4142. given by the understanding), only as it appears to itself, and not as it
  4143. would cognize itself, if its intuition were intellectual.
  4144. [*Footnote: The "I think" expresses the act of determining
  4145. my own existence. My existence is thus already given by the
  4146. act of consciousness; but the mode in which I must determine
  4147. my existence, that is, the mode in which I must place the
  4148. manifold belonging to my existence, is not thereby given.
  4149. For this purpose intuition of self is required, and this
  4150. intuition possesses a form given a priori, namely, time,
  4151. which is sensuous, and belongs to our receptivity of the
  4152. determinable. Now, as I do not possess another intuition of
  4153. self which gives the determining in me (of the spontaneity
  4154. of which I am conscious), prior to the act of determination,
  4155. in the same manner as time gives the determinable, it is
  4156. clear that I am unable to determine my own existence as that
  4157. of a spontaneous being, but I am only able to represent to
  4158. myself the spontaneity of my thought, that is, of my
  4159. determination, and my existence remains ever determinable in
  4160. a purely sensuous manner, that is to say, like the existence
  4161. of a phenomenon. But it is because of this spontaneity that
  4162. I call myself an intelligence.]
  4163. SS 22. Transcendental Deduction of the universally possible employment
  4164. in experience of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding.
  4165. In the metaphysical deduction, the a priori origin of categories was
  4166. proved by their complete accordance with the general logical of thought;
  4167. in the transcendental deduction was exhibited the possibility of the
  4168. categories as a priori cognitions of objects of an intuition in general
  4169. (SS 16 and 17).At present we are about to explain the possibility of
  4170. cognizing, a priori, by means of the categories, all objects which can
  4171. possibly be presented to our senses, not, indeed, according to the form
  4172. of their intuition, but according to the laws of their conjunction or
  4173. synthesis, and thus, as it were, of prescribing laws to nature and even
  4174. of rendering nature possible. For if the categories were inadequate
  4175. to this task, it would not be evident to us why everything that is
  4176. presented to our senses must be subject to those laws which have an a
  4177. priori origin in the understanding itself.
  4178. I premise that by the term synthesis of apprehension I understand
  4179. the combination of the manifold in an empirical intuition, whereby
  4180. perception, that is, empirical consciousness of the intuition (as
  4181. phenomenon), is possible.
  4182. We have a priori forms of the external and internal sensuous intuition
  4183. in the representations of space and time, and to these must the
  4184. synthesis of apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon be always
  4185. comformable, because the synthesis itself can only take place according
  4186. to these forms. But space and time are not merely forms of sensuous
  4187. intuition, but intuitions themselves (which contain a manifold), and
  4188. therefore contain a priori the determination of the unity of this
  4189. manifold.* (See the Transcendent Aesthetic.) Therefore is unity of the
  4190. synthesis of the manifold without or within us, consequently also a
  4191. conjunction to which all that is to be represented as determined in
  4192. space or time must correspond, given a priori along with (not in) these
  4193. intuitions, as the condition of the synthesis of all apprehension
  4194. of them. But this synthetical unity can be no other than that of the
  4195. conjunction of the manifold of a given intuition in general, in a
  4196. primitive act of consciousness, according to the categories, but applied
  4197. to our sensuous intuition. Consequently all synthesis, whereby alone
  4198. is even perception possible, is subject to the categories. And,
  4199. as experience is cognition by means of conjoined perceptions, the
  4200. categories are conditions of the possibility of experience and are
  4201. therefore valid a priori for all objects of experience.
  4202. [*Footnote: Space represented as an object (as geometry
  4203. really requires it to be) contains more than the mere form
  4204. of the intuition; namely, a combination of the manifold
  4205. given according to the form of sensibility into a
  4206. representation that can be intuited; so that the form of the
  4207. intuition gives us merely the manifold, but the formal
  4208. intuition gives unity of representation. In the aesthetic, I
  4209. regarded this unity as belonging entirely to sensibility,
  4210. for the purpose of indicating that it antecedes all
  4211. conceptions, although it presupposes a synthesis which does
  4212. not belong to sense, through which alone, however, all our
  4213. conceptions of space and time are possible. For as by means
  4214. of this unity alone (the understanding determining the
  4215. sensibility) space and time are given as intuitions, it
  4216. follows that the unity of this intuition a priori belongs to
  4217. space and time, and not to the conception of the
  4218. understanding (SS 20).]
  4219. When, then, for example, I make the empirical intuition of a house by
  4220. apprehension of the manifold contained therein into a perception, the
  4221. necessary unity of space and of my external sensuous intuition lies
  4222. at the foundation of this act, and I, as it were, draw the form of the
  4223. house conformably to this synthetical unity of the manifold in space.
  4224. But this very synthetical unity remains, even when I abstract the form
  4225. of space, and has its seat in the understanding, and is in fact the
  4226. category of the synthesis of the homogeneous in an intuition; that is
  4227. to say, the category of quantity, to which the aforesaid synthesis of
  4228. apprehension, that is, the perception, must be completely conformable.*
  4229. [*Footnote: In this manner it is proved, that the synthesis
  4230. of apprehension, which is empirical, must necessarily be
  4231. conformable to the synthesis of apperception, which is
  4232. intellectual, and contained a priori in the category. It is
  4233. one and the same spontaneity which at one time, under the
  4234. name of imagination, at another under that of understanding,
  4235. produces conjunction in the manifold of intuition.]
  4236. To take another example, when I perceive the freezing of water, I
  4237. apprehend two states (fluidity and solidity), which, as such, stand
  4238. toward each other mutually in a relation of time. But in the time, which
  4239. I place as an internal intuition, at the foundation of this phenomenon,
  4240. I represent to myself synthetical unity of the manifold, without which
  4241. the aforesaid relation could not be given in an intuition as determined
  4242. (in regard to the succession of time). Now this synthetical unity,
  4243. as the a priori condition under which I conjoin the manifold of an
  4244. intuition, is, if I make abstraction of the permanent form of my
  4245. internal intuition (that is to say, of time), the category of cause, by
  4246. means of which, when applied to my sensibility, I determine everything
  4247. that occurs according to relations of time. Consequently apprehension in
  4248. such an event, and the event itself, as far as regards the possibility
  4249. of its perception, stands under the conception of the relation of cause
  4250. and effect: and so in all other cases.
  4251. Categories are conceptions which prescribe laws a priori to phenomena,
  4252. consequently to nature as the complex of all phenomena (natura
  4253. materialiter spectata). And now the question arises--inasmuch as these
  4254. categories are not derived from nature, and do not regulate themselves
  4255. according to her as their model (for in that case they would be
  4256. empirical)--how it is conceivable that nature must regulate herself
  4257. according to them, in other words, how the categories can determine a
  4258. priori the synthesis of the manifold of nature, and yet not derive their
  4259. origin from her. The following is the solution of this enigma.
  4260. It is not in the least more difficult to conceive how the laws of the
  4261. phenomena of nature must harmonize with the understanding and with its a
  4262. priori form--that is, its faculty of conjoining the manifold--than it
  4263. is to understand how the phenomena themselves must correspond with the
  4264. a priori form of our sensuous intuition. For laws do not exist in the
  4265. phenomena any more than the phenomena exist as things in themselves.
  4266. Laws do not exist except by relation to the subject in which the
  4267. phenomena inhere, in so far as it possesses understanding, just as
  4268. phenomena have no existence except by relation to the same existing
  4269. subject in so far as it has senses. To things as things in themselves,
  4270. conformability to law must necessarily belong independently of an
  4271. understanding to cognize them. But phenomena are only representations
  4272. of things which are utterly unknown in respect to what they are in
  4273. themselves. But as mere representations, they stand under no law of
  4274. conjunction except that which the conjoining faculty prescribes. Now
  4275. that which conjoins the manifold of sensuous intuition is imagination,
  4276. a mental act to which understanding contributes unity of intellectual
  4277. synthesis, and sensibility, manifoldness of apprehension. Now as all
  4278. possible perception depends on the synthesis of apprehension, and this
  4279. empirical synthesis itself on the transcendental, consequently on the
  4280. categories, it is evident that all possible perceptions, and therefore
  4281. everything that can attain to empirical consciousness, that is, all
  4282. phenomena of nature, must, as regards their conjunction, be subject to
  4283. the categories. And nature (considered merely as nature in general)
  4284. is dependent on them, as the original ground of her necessary
  4285. conformability to law (as natura formaliter spectata). But the pure
  4286. faculty (of the understanding) of prescribing laws a priori to phenomena
  4287. by means of mere categories, is not competent to enounce other or more
  4288. laws than those on which a nature in general, as a conformability to law
  4289. of phenomena of space and time, depends. Particular laws, inasmuch
  4290. as they concern empirically determined phenomena, cannot be entirely
  4291. deduced from pure laws, although they all stand under them. Experience
  4292. must be superadded in order to know these particular laws; but in regard
  4293. to experience in general, and everything that can be cognized as an
  4294. object thereof, these a priori laws are our only rule and guide.
  4295. SS 23. Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the
  4296. Understanding.
  4297. We cannot think any object except by means of the categories; we cannot
  4298. cognize any thought except by means of intuitions corresponding to these
  4299. conceptions. Now all our intuitions are sensuous, and our cognition,
  4300. in so far as the object of it is given, is empirical. But empirical
  4301. cognition is experience; consequently no a priori cognition is possible
  4302. for us, except of objects of possible experience.*
  4303. [Footnote: Lest my readers should stumble at this assertion,
  4304. and the conclusions that may be too rashly drawn from it, I
  4305. must remind them that the categories in the act of thought
  4306. are by no means limited by the conditions of our sensuous
  4307. intuition, but have an unbounded sphere of action. It is
  4308. only the cognition of the object of thought, the determining
  4309. of the object, which requires intuition. In the absence of
  4310. intuition, our thought of an object may still have true and
  4311. useful consequences in regard to the exercise of reason by
  4312. the subject. But as this exercise of reason is not always
  4313. directed on the determination of the object, in other words,
  4314. on cognition thereof, but also on the determination of the
  4315. subject and its volition, I do not intend to treat of it in
  4316. this place.]
  4317. But this cognition, which is limited to objects of experience, is not
  4318. for that reason derived entirely, from, experience, but--and this
  4319. is asserted of the pure intuitions and the pure conceptions of the
  4320. understanding--there are, unquestionably, elements of cognition, which
  4321. exist in the mind a priori. Now there are only two ways in which a
  4322. necessary harmony of experience with the conceptions of its objects can
  4323. be cogitated. Either experience makes these conceptions possible, or
  4324. the conceptions make experience possible. The former of these statements
  4325. will not bold good with respect to the categories (nor in regard to pure
  4326. sensuous intuition), for they are a priori conceptions, and therefore
  4327. independent of experience. The assertion of an empirical origin would
  4328. attribute to them a sort of generatio aequivoca. Consequently, nothing
  4329. remains but to adopt the second alternative (which presents us with a
  4330. system, as it were, of the epigenesis of pure reason), namely, that on
  4331. the part of the understanding the categories do contain the grounds of
  4332. the possibility of all experience. But with respect to the questions
  4333. how they make experience possible, and what are the principles of the
  4334. possibility thereof with which they present us in their application to
  4335. phenomena, the following section on the transcendental exercise of the
  4336. faculty of judgement will inform the reader.
  4337. It is quite possible that someone may propose a species of
  4338. preformation-system of pure reason--a middle way between the two--to
  4339. wit, that the categories are neither innate and first a priori
  4340. principles of cognition, nor derived from experience, but are merely
  4341. subjective aptitudes for thought implanted in us contemporaneously with
  4342. our existence, which were so ordered and disposed by our Creator,
  4343. that their exercise perfectly harmonizes with the laws of nature which
  4344. regulate experience. Now, not to mention that with such an hypothesis
  4345. it is impossible to say at what point we must stop in the employment of
  4346. predetermined aptitudes, the fact that the categories would in this case
  4347. entirely lose that character of necessity which is essentially involved
  4348. in the very conception of them, is a conclusive objection to it. The
  4349. conception of cause, for example, which expresses the necessity of an
  4350. effect under a presupposed condition, would be false, if it rested only
  4351. upon such an arbitrary subjective necessity of uniting certain empirical
  4352. representations according to such a rule of relation. I could not then
  4353. say--"The effect is connected with its cause in the object (that is,
  4354. necessarily)," but only, "I am so constituted that I can think this
  4355. representation as so connected, and not otherwise." Now this is just
  4356. what the sceptic wants. For in this case, all our knowledge, depending
  4357. on the supposed objective validity of our judgement, is nothing but
  4358. mere illusion; nor would there be wanting people who would deny any such
  4359. subjective necessity in respect to themselves, though they must feel it.
  4360. At all events, we could not dispute with any one on that which merely
  4361. depends on the manner in which his subject is organized.
  4362. Short view of the above Deduction.
  4363. The foregoing deduction is an exposition of the pure conceptions of the
  4364. understanding (and with them of all theoretical a priori cognition), as
  4365. principles of the possibility of experience, but of experience as
  4366. the determination of all phenomena in space and time in general--of
  4367. experience, finally, from the principle of the original synthetical
  4368. unity of apperception, as the form of the understanding in relation to
  4369. time and space as original forms of sensibility.
  4370. I consider the division by paragraphs to be necessary only up to this
  4371. point, because we had to treat of the elementary conceptions. As we
  4372. now proceed to the exposition of the employment of these, I shall not
  4373. designate the chapters in this manner any further.
  4374. BOOK II.
  4375. Analytic of Principles.
  4376. General logic is constructed upon a plan which coincides exactly
  4377. with the division of the higher faculties of cognition. These are,
  4378. understanding, judgement, and reason. This science, accordingly, treats
  4379. in its analytic of conceptions, judgements, and conclusions in exact
  4380. correspondence with the functions and order of those mental powers which
  4381. we include generally under the generic denomination of understanding.
  4382. As this merely formal logic makes abstraction of all content of
  4383. cognition, whether pure or empirical, and occupies itself with the mere
  4384. form of thought (discursive cognition), it must contain in its analytic
  4385. a canon for reason. For the form of reason has its law, which, without
  4386. taking into consideration the particular nature of the cognition about
  4387. which it is employed, can be discovered a priori, by the simple analysis
  4388. of the action of reason into its momenta.
  4389. Transcendental logic, limited as it is to a determinate content, that of
  4390. pure a priori cognitions, to wit, cannot imitate general logic in this
  4391. division. For it is evident that the transcendental employment of reason
  4392. is not objectively valid, and therefore does not belong to the logic
  4393. of truth (that is, to analytic), but as a logic of illusion, occupies
  4394. a particular department in the scholastic system under the name of
  4395. transcendental dialectic.
  4396. Understanding and judgement accordingly possess in transcendental logic
  4397. a canon of objectively valid, and therefore true exercise, and are
  4398. comprehended in the analytical department of that logic. But reason,
  4399. in her endeavours to arrive by a priori means at some true statement
  4400. concerning objects and to extend cognition beyond the bounds of possible
  4401. experience, is altogether dialectic, and her illusory assertions cannot
  4402. be constructed into a canon such as an analytic ought to contain.
  4403. Accordingly, the analytic of principles will be merely a canon for
  4404. the faculty of judgement, for the instruction of this faculty in its
  4405. application to phenomena of the pure conceptions of the understanding,
  4406. which contain the necessary condition for the establishment of a priori
  4407. laws. On this account, although the subject of the following chapters is
  4408. the especial principles of understanding, I shall make use of the
  4409. term Doctrine of the faculty of judgement, in order to define more
  4410. particularly my present purpose.
  4411. INTRODUCTION. Of the Transcendental Faculty of judgement in General.
  4412. If understanding in general be defined as the faculty of laws or rules,
  4413. the faculty of judgement may be termed the faculty of subsumption under
  4414. these rules; that is, of distinguishing whether this or that does or
  4415. does not stand under a given rule (casus datae legis). General logic
  4416. contains no directions or precepts for the faculty of judgement, nor
  4417. can it contain any such. For as it makes abstraction of all content of
  4418. cognition, no duty is left for it, except that of exposing analytically
  4419. the mere form of cognition in conceptions, judgements, and conclusions,
  4420. and of thereby establishing formal rules for all exercise of the
  4421. understanding. Now if this logic wished to give some general direction
  4422. how we should subsume under these rules, that is, how we should
  4423. distinguish whether this or that did or did not stand under them, this
  4424. again could not be done otherwise than by means of a rule. But this
  4425. rule, precisely because it is a rule, requires for itself direction from
  4426. the faculty of judgement. Thus, it is evident that the understanding
  4427. is capable of being instructed by rules, but that the judgement is a
  4428. peculiar talent, which does not, and cannot require tuition, but
  4429. only exercise. This faculty is therefore the specific quality of the
  4430. so-called mother wit, the want of which no scholastic discipline can
  4431. compensate.
  4432. For although education may furnish, and, as it were, engraft upon a
  4433. limited understanding rules borrowed from other minds, yet the power of
  4434. employing these rules correctly must belong to the pupil himself; and no
  4435. rule which we can prescribe to him with this purpose is, in the absence
  4436. or deficiency of this gift of nature, secure from misuse.* A physician
  4437. therefore, a judge or a statesman, may have in his head many admirable
  4438. pathological, juridical, or political rules, in a degree that may enable
  4439. him to be a profound teacher in his particular science, and yet in the
  4440. application of these rules he may very possibly blunder--either because
  4441. he is wanting in natural judgement (though not in understanding) and,
  4442. whilst he can comprehend the general in abstracto, cannot distinguish
  4443. whether a particular case in concreto ought to rank under the former; or
  4444. because his faculty of judgement has not been sufficiently exercised by
  4445. examples and real practice. Indeed, the grand and only use of examples,
  4446. is to sharpen the judgement. For as regards the correctness and
  4447. precision of the insight of the understanding, examples are commonly
  4448. injurious rather than otherwise, because, as casus in terminis they
  4449. seldom adequately fulfil the conditions of the rule. Besides, they often
  4450. weaken the power of our understanding to apprehend rules or laws
  4451. in their universality, independently of particular circumstances of
  4452. experience; and hence, accustom us to employ them more as formulae than
  4453. as principles. Examples are thus the go-cart of the judgement, which
  4454. he who is naturally deficient in that faculty cannot afford to dispense
  4455. with.
  4456. [*Footnote: Deficiency in judgement is properly that which
  4457. is called stupidity; and for such a failing we know no
  4458. remedy. A dull or narrow-minded person, to whom nothing is
  4459. wanting but a proper degree of understanding, may be
  4460. improved by tuition, even so far as to deserve the epithet
  4461. of learned. But as such persons frequently labour under a
  4462. deficiency in the faculty of judgement, it is not uncommon
  4463. to find men extremely learned who in the application of
  4464. their science betray a lamentable degree this irremediable
  4465. want.]
  4466. But although general logic cannot give directions to the faculty of
  4467. judgement, the case is very different as regards transcendental logic,
  4468. insomuch that it appears to be the especial duty of the latter to secure
  4469. and direct, by means of determinate rules, the faculty of judgement in
  4470. the employment of the pure understanding. For, as a doctrine, that is,
  4471. as an endeavour to enlarge the sphere of the understanding in regard to
  4472. pure a priori cognitions, philosophy is worse than useless, since from
  4473. all the attempts hitherto made, little or no ground has been gained.
  4474. But, as a critique, in order to guard against the mistakes of the
  4475. faculty of judgement (lapsus judicii) in the employment of the few pure
  4476. conceptions of the understanding which we possess, although its use is
  4477. in this case purely negative, philosophy is called upon to apply all its
  4478. acuteness and penetration.
  4479. But transcendental philosophy has this peculiarity, that besides
  4480. indicating the rule, or rather the general condition for rules, which is
  4481. given in the pure conception of the understanding, it can, at the same
  4482. time, indicate a priori the case to which the rule must be applied.
  4483. The cause of the superiority which, in this respect, transcendental
  4484. philosophy possesses above all other sciences except mathematics, lies
  4485. in this: it treats of conceptions which must relate a priori to their
  4486. objects, whose objective validity consequently cannot be demonstrated a
  4487. posteriori, and is, at the same time, under the obligation of presenting
  4488. in general but sufficient tests, the conditions under which objects can
  4489. be given in harmony with those conceptions; otherwise they would be
  4490. mere logical forms, without content, and not pure conceptions of the
  4491. understanding.
  4492. Our transcendental doctrine of the faculty of judgement will contain
  4493. two chapters. The first will treat of the sensuous condition under which
  4494. alone pure conceptions of the understanding can be employed--that is, of
  4495. the schematism of the pure understanding. The second will treat of those
  4496. synthetical judgements which are derived a priori from pure conceptions
  4497. of the understanding under those conditions, and which lie a priori at
  4498. the foundation of all other cognitions, that is to say, it will treat of
  4499. the principles of the pure understanding.
  4500. TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF THE FACULTY OF JUDGEMENT OR, ANALYTIC OF
  4501. PRINCIPLES.
  4502. CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the
  4503. Understanding.
  4504. In all subsumptions of an object under a conception, the representation
  4505. of the object must be homogeneous with the conception; in other words,
  4506. the conception must contain that which is represented in the object to
  4507. be subsumed under it. For this is the meaning of the expression: "An
  4508. object is contained under a conception." Thus the empirical conception
  4509. of a plate is homogeneous with the pure geometrical conception of a
  4510. circle, inasmuch as the roundness which is cogitated in the former is
  4511. intuited in the latter.
  4512. But pure conceptions of the understanding, when compared with empirical
  4513. intuitions, or even with sensuous intuitions in general, are quite
  4514. heterogeneous, and never can be discovered in any intuition. How then
  4515. is the subsumption of the latter under the former, and consequently
  4516. the application of the categories to phenomena, possible?--For it is
  4517. impossible to say, for example: "Causality can be intuited through the
  4518. senses and is contained in the phenomenon."--This natural and important
  4519. question forms the real cause of the necessity of a transcendental
  4520. doctrine of the faculty of judgement, with the purpose, to wit, of
  4521. showing how pure conceptions of the understanding can be applied to
  4522. phenomena. In all other sciences, where the conceptions by which the
  4523. object is thought in the general are not so different and heterogeneous
  4524. from those which represent the object in concreto--as it is given, it
  4525. is quite unnecessary to institute any special inquiries concerning the
  4526. application of the former to the latter.
  4527. Now it is quite clear that there must be some third thing, which on the
  4528. one side is homogeneous with the category, and with the phenomenon on
  4529. the other, and so makes the application of the former to the latter
  4530. possible. This mediating representation must be pure (without any
  4531. empirical content), and yet must on the one side be intellectual, on the
  4532. other sensuous. Such a representation is the transcendental schema.
  4533. The conception of the understanding contains pure synthetical unity of
  4534. the manifold in general. Time, as the formal condition of the
  4535. manifold of the internal sense, consequently of the conjunction of all
  4536. representations, contains a priori a manifold in the pure intuition. Now
  4537. a transcendental determination of time is so far homogeneous with the
  4538. category, which constitutes the unity thereof, that it is universal and
  4539. rests upon a rule a priori. On the other hand, it is so far homogeneous
  4540. with the phenomenon, inasmuch as time is contained in every empirical
  4541. representation of the manifold. Thus an application of the category to
  4542. phenomena becomes possible, by means of the transcendental determination
  4543. of time, which, as the schema of the conceptions of the understanding,
  4544. mediates the subsumption of the latter under the former.
  4545. After what has been proved in our deduction of the categories, no
  4546. one, it is to be hoped, can hesitate as to the proper decision of
  4547. the question, whether the employment of these pure conceptions of the
  4548. understanding ought to be merely empirical or also transcendental;
  4549. in other words, whether the categories, as conditions of a possible
  4550. experience, relate a priori solely to phenomena, or whether, as
  4551. conditions of the possibility of things in general, their application
  4552. can be extended to objects as things in themselves. For we have
  4553. there seen that conceptions are quite impossible, and utterly without
  4554. signification, unless either to them, or at least to the elements of
  4555. which they consist, an object be given; and that, consequently, they
  4556. cannot possibly apply to objects as things in themselves without regard
  4557. to the question whether and how these may be given to us; and, further,
  4558. that the only manner in which objects can be given to us is by means of
  4559. the modification of our sensibility; and, finally, that pure a priori
  4560. conceptions, in addition to the function of the understanding in the
  4561. category, must contain a priori formal conditions of sensibility (of the
  4562. internal sense, namely), which again contain the general condition under
  4563. which alone the category can be applied to any object. This formal
  4564. and pure condition of sensibility, to which the conception of the
  4565. understanding is restricted in its employment, we shall name the
  4566. schema of the conception of the understanding, and the procedure of the
  4567. understanding with these schemata we shall call the schematism of the
  4568. pure understanding.
  4569. The schema is, in itself, always a mere product of the imagination. But,
  4570. as the synthesis of imagination has for its aim no single intuition, but
  4571. merely unity in the determination of sensibility, the schema is clearly
  4572. distinguishable from the image. Thus, if I place five points one after
  4573. another.... this is an image of the number five. On the other hand, if
  4574. I only think a number in general, which may be either five or a hundred,
  4575. this thought is rather the representation of a method of representing in
  4576. an image a sum (e.g., a thousand) in conformity with a conception, than
  4577. the image itself, an image which I should find some little difficulty in
  4578. reviewing, and comparing with the conception. Now this representation
  4579. of a general procedure of the imagination to present its image to a
  4580. conception, I call the schema of this conception.
  4581. In truth, it is not images of objects, but schemata, which lie at the
  4582. foundation of our pure sensuous conceptions. No image could ever be
  4583. adequate to our conception of a triangle in general. For the generalness
  4584. of the conception it never could attain to, as this includes under
  4585. itself all triangles, whether right-angled, acute-angled, etc., whilst
  4586. the image would always be limited to a single part of this sphere. The
  4587. schema of the triangle can exist nowhere else than in thought, and it
  4588. indicates a rule of the synthesis of the imagination in regard to pure
  4589. figures in space. Still less is an object of experience, or an image
  4590. of the object, ever to the empirical conception. On the contrary, the
  4591. conception always relates immediately to the schema of the imagination,
  4592. as a rule for the determination of our intuition, in conformity with a
  4593. certain general conception. The conception of a dog indicates a
  4594. rule, according to which my imagination can delineate the figure of a
  4595. four-footed animal in general, without being limited to any particular
  4596. individual form which experience presents to me, or indeed to any
  4597. possible image that I can represent to myself in concreto. This
  4598. schematism of our understanding in regard to phenomena and their mere
  4599. form, is an art, hidden in the depths of the human soul, whose true
  4600. modes of action we shall only with difficulty discover and unveil. Thus
  4601. much only can we say: "The image is a product of the empirical faculty
  4602. of the productive imagination--the schema of sensuous conceptions (of
  4603. figures in space, for example) is a product, and, as it were, a monogram
  4604. of the pure imagination a priori, whereby and according to which
  4605. images first become possible, which, however, can be connected with the
  4606. conception only mediately by means of the schema which they indicate,
  4607. and are in themselves never fully adequate to it." On the other hand,
  4608. the schema of a pure conception of the understanding is something that
  4609. cannot be reduced into any image--it is nothing else than the pure
  4610. synthesis expressed by the category, conformably, to a rule of unity
  4611. according to conceptions. It is a transcendental product of the
  4612. imagination, a product which concerns the determination of the internal
  4613. sense, according to conditions of its form (time) in respect to all
  4614. representations, in so far as these representations must be conjoined a
  4615. priori in one conception, conformably to the unity of apperception.
  4616. Without entering upon a dry and tedious analysis of the essential
  4617. requisites of transcendental schemata of the pure conceptions of the
  4618. understanding, we shall rather proceed at once to give an explanation
  4619. of them according to the order of the categories, and in connection
  4620. therewith.
  4621. For the external sense the pure image of all quantities (quantorum) is
  4622. space; the pure image of all objects of sense in general, is time.
  4623. But the pure schema of quantity (quantitatis) as a conception of
  4624. the understanding, is number, a representation which comprehends the
  4625. successive addition of one to one (homogeneous quantities). Thus, number
  4626. is nothing else than the unity of the synthesis of the manifold in
  4627. a homogeneous intuition, by means of my generating time itself in my
  4628. apprehension of the intuition.
  4629. Reality, in the pure conception of the understanding, is that which
  4630. corresponds to a sensation in general; that, consequently, the
  4631. conception of which indicates a being (in time). Negation is that the
  4632. conception of which represents a not-being (in time). The opposition of
  4633. these two consists therefore in the difference of one and the same
  4634. time, as a time filled or a time empty. Now as time is only the form of
  4635. intuition, consequently of objects as phenomena, that which in objects
  4636. corresponds to sensation is the transcendental matter of all objects
  4637. as things in themselves (Sachheit, reality). Now every sensation has
  4638. a degree or quantity by which it can fill time, that is to say, the
  4639. internal sense in respect of the representation of an object, more or
  4640. less, until it vanishes into nothing (= 0 = negatio). Thus there is
  4641. a relation and connection between reality and negation, or rather a
  4642. transition from the former to the latter, which makes every reality
  4643. representable to us as a quantum; and the schema of a reality as the
  4644. quantity of something in so far as it fills time, is exactly this
  4645. continuous and uniform generation of the reality in time, as we descend
  4646. in time from the sensation which has a certain degree, down to the
  4647. vanishing thereof, or gradually ascend from negation to the quantity
  4648. thereof.
  4649. The schema of substance is the permanence of the real in time; that is,
  4650. the representation of it as a substratum of the empirical determination
  4651. of time; a substratum which therefore remains, whilst all else changes.
  4652. (Time passes not, but in it passes the existence of the changeable. To
  4653. time, therefore, which is itself unchangeable and permanent, corresponds
  4654. that which in the phenomenon is unchangeable in existence, that is,
  4655. substance, and it is only by it that the succession and coexistence of
  4656. phenomena can be determined in regard to time.)
  4657. The schema of cause and of the causality of a thing is the real which,
  4658. when posited, is always followed by something else. It consists,
  4659. therefore, in the succession of the manifold, in so far as that
  4660. succession is subjected to a rule.
  4661. The schema of community (reciprocity of action and reaction), or the
  4662. reciprocal causality of substances in respect of their accidents, is the
  4663. coexistence of the determinations of the one with those of the other,
  4664. according to a general rule.
  4665. The schema of possibility is the accordance of the synthesis of
  4666. different representations with the conditions of time in general (as,
  4667. for example, opposites cannot exist together at the same time in
  4668. the same thing, but only after each other), and is therefore the
  4669. determination of the representation of a thing at any time.
  4670. The schema of reality is existence in a determined time.
  4671. The schema of necessity is the existence of an object in all time.
  4672. It is clear, from all this, that the schema of the category of quantity
  4673. contains and represents the generation (synthesis) of time itself, in
  4674. the successive apprehension of an object; the schema of quality the
  4675. synthesis of sensation with the representation of time, or the filling
  4676. up of time; the schema of relation the relation of perceptions to each
  4677. other in all time (that is, according to a rule of the determination
  4678. of time): and finally, the schema of modality and its categories, time
  4679. itself, as the correlative of the determination of an object--whether it
  4680. does belong to time, and how. The schemata, therefore, are nothing but
  4681. a priori determinations of time according to rules, and these, in regard
  4682. to all possible objects, following the arrangement of the categories,
  4683. relate to the series in time, the content in time, the order in time,
  4684. and finally, to the complex or totality in time.
  4685. Hence it is apparent that the schematism of the understanding, by means
  4686. of the transcendental synthesis of the imagination, amounts to nothing
  4687. else than the unity of the manifold of intuition in the internal
  4688. sense, and thus indirectly to the unity of apperception, as a function
  4689. corresponding to the internal sense (a receptivity). Thus, the schemata
  4690. of the pure conceptions of the understanding are the true and only
  4691. conditions whereby our understanding receives an application to objects,
  4692. and consequently significance. Finally, therefore, the categories are
  4693. only capable of empirical use, inasmuch as they serve merely to subject
  4694. phenomena to the universal rules of synthesis, by means of an a priori
  4695. necessary unity (on account of the necessary union of all consciousness
  4696. in one original apperception); and so to render them susceptible of a
  4697. complete connection in one experience. But within this whole of possible
  4698. experience lie all our cognitions, and in the universal relation to this
  4699. experience consists transcendental truth, which antecedes all empirical
  4700. truth, and renders the latter possible.
  4701. It is, however, evident at first sight, that although the schemata of
  4702. sensibility are the sole agents in realizing the categories, they do,
  4703. nevertheless, also restrict them, that is, they limit the categories
  4704. by conditions which lie beyond the sphere of understanding--namely, in
  4705. sensibility. Hence the schema is properly only the phenomenon, or the
  4706. sensuous conception of an object in harmony with the category. (Numerus
  4707. est quantitas phaenomenon--sensatio realitas phaenomenon; constans
  4708. et perdurabile rerum substantia phaenomenon--aeternitas, necessitas,
  4709. phaenomena, etc.) Now, if we remove a restrictive condition, we thereby
  4710. amplify, it appears, the formerly limited conception. In this way, the
  4711. categories in their pure signification, free from all conditions of
  4712. sensibility, ought to be valid of things as they are, and not, as the
  4713. schemata represent them, merely as they appear; and consequently the
  4714. categories must have a significance far more extended, and wholly
  4715. independent of all schemata. In truth, there does always remain to the
  4716. pure conceptions of the understanding, after abstracting every sensuous
  4717. condition, a value and significance, which is, however, merely logical.
  4718. But in this case, no object is given them, and therefore they have no
  4719. meaning sufficient to afford us a conception of an object. The notion
  4720. of substance, for example, if we leave out the sensuous determination
  4721. of permanence, would mean nothing more than a something which can be
  4722. cogitated as subject, without the possibility of becoming a predicate to
  4723. anything else. Of this representation I can make nothing, inasmuch as
  4724. it does not indicate to me what determinations the thing possesses which
  4725. must thus be valid as premier subject. Consequently, the categories,
  4726. without schemata are merely functions of the understanding for the
  4727. production of conceptions, but do not represent any object. This
  4728. significance they derive from sensibility, which at the same time
  4729. realizes the understanding and restricts it.
  4730. CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding.
  4731. In the foregoing chapter we have merely considered the general
  4732. conditions under which alone the transcendental faculty of judgement
  4733. is justified in using the pure conceptions of the understanding for
  4734. synthetical judgements. Our duty at present is to exhibit in systematic
  4735. connection those judgements which the understanding really produces a
  4736. priori. For this purpose, our table of the categories will certainly
  4737. afford us the natural and safe guidance. For it is precisely the
  4738. categories whose application to possible experience must constitute all
  4739. pure a priori cognition of the understanding; and the relation of which
  4740. to sensibility will, on that very account, present us with a complete
  4741. and systematic catalogue of all the transcendental principles of the use
  4742. of the understanding.
  4743. Principles a priori are so called, not merely because they contain
  4744. in themselves the grounds of other judgements, but also because they
  4745. themselves are not grounded in higher and more general cognitions. This
  4746. peculiarity, however, does not raise them altogether above the need of
  4747. a proof. For although there could be found no higher cognition, and
  4748. therefore no objective proof, and although such a principle rather
  4749. serves as the foundation for all cognition of the object, this by no
  4750. means hinders us from drawing a proof from the subjective sources of the
  4751. possibility of the cognition of an object. Such a proof is necessary,
  4752. moreover, because without it the principle might be liable to the
  4753. imputation of being a mere gratuitous assertion.
  4754. In the second place, we shall limit our investigations to those
  4755. principles which relate to the categories. For as to the principles
  4756. of transcendental aesthetic, according to which space and time are
  4757. the conditions of the possibility of things as phenomena, as also the
  4758. restriction of these principles, namely, that they cannot be applied to
  4759. objects as things in themselves--these, of course, do not fall within
  4760. the scope of our present inquiry. In like manner, the principles of
  4761. mathematical science form no part of this system, because they are
  4762. all drawn from intuition, and not from the pure conception of the
  4763. understanding. The possibility of these principles, however, will
  4764. necessarily be considered here, inasmuch as they are synthetical
  4765. judgements a priori, not indeed for the purpose of proving their
  4766. accuracy and apodeictic certainty, which is unnecessary, but merely to
  4767. render conceivable and deduce the possibility of such evident a priori
  4768. cognitions.
  4769. But we shall have also to speak of the principle of analytical
  4770. judgements, in opposition to synthetical judgements, which is the proper
  4771. subject of our inquiries, because this very opposition will free the
  4772. theory of the latter from all ambiguity, and place it clearly before our
  4773. eyes in its true nature.
  4774. SYSTEM OF THE PRINCIPLES OF THE PURE UNDERSTANDING.
  4775. SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements.
  4776. Whatever may be the content of our cognition, and in whatever manner
  4777. our cognition may be related to its object, the universal, although only
  4778. negative conditions of all our judgements is that they do not contradict
  4779. themselves; otherwise these judgements are in themselves (even without
  4780. respect to the object) nothing. But although there may exist no
  4781. contradiction in our judgement, it may nevertheless connect conceptions
  4782. in such a manner that they do not correspond to the object, or without
  4783. any grounds either a priori or a posteriori for arriving at such a
  4784. judgement, and thus, without being self-contradictory, a judgement may
  4785. nevertheless be either false or groundless.
  4786. Now, the proposition: "No subject can have a predicate that contradicts
  4787. it," is called the principle of contradiction, and is a universal but
  4788. purely negative criterion of all truth. But it belongs to logic alone,
  4789. because it is valid of cognitions, merely as cognitions and without
  4790. respect to their content, and declares that the contradiction entirely
  4791. nullifies them. We can also, however, make a positive use of this
  4792. principle, that is, not merely to banish falsehood and error (in so far
  4793. as it rests upon contradiction), but also for the cognition of truth.
  4794. For if the judgement is analytical, be it affirmative or negative,
  4795. its truth must always be recognizable by means of the principle of
  4796. contradiction. For the contrary of that which lies and is cogitated
  4797. as conception in the cognition of the object will be always properly
  4798. negatived, but the conception itself must always be affirmed of the
  4799. object, inasmuch as the contrary thereof would be in contradiction to
  4800. the object.
  4801. We must therefore hold the principle of contradiction to be the
  4802. universal and fully sufficient Principle of all analytical cognition.
  4803. But as a sufficient criterion of truth, it has no further utility or
  4804. authority. For the fact that no cognition can be at variance with this
  4805. principle without nullifying itself, constitutes this principle the sine
  4806. qua non, but not the determining ground of the truth of our cognition.
  4807. As our business at present is properly with the synthetical part of our
  4808. knowledge only, we shall always be on our guard not to transgress this
  4809. inviolable principle; but at the same time not to expect from it any
  4810. direct assistance in the establishment of the truth of any synthetical
  4811. proposition.
  4812. There exists, however, a formula of this celebrated principle--a
  4813. principle merely formal and entirely without content--which contains a
  4814. synthesis that has been inadvertently and quite unnecessarily mixed up
  4815. with it. It is this: "It is impossible for a thing to be and not to be
  4816. at the same time." Not to mention the superfluousness of the addition of
  4817. the word impossible to indicate the apodeictic certainty, which ought to
  4818. be self-evident from the proposition itself, the proposition is affected
  4819. by the condition of time, and as it were says: "A thing = A, which is
  4820. something = B, cannot at the same time be non-B." But both, B as well
  4821. as non-B, may quite well exist in succession. For example, a man who is
  4822. young cannot at the same time be old; but the same man can very well
  4823. be at one time young, and at another not young, that is, old. Now the
  4824. principle of contradiction as a merely logical proposition must not
  4825. by any means limit its application merely to relations of time, and
  4826. consequently a formula like the preceding is quite foreign to its
  4827. true purpose. The misunderstanding arises in this way. We first of all
  4828. separate a predicate of a thing from the conception of the thing, and
  4829. afterwards connect with this predicate its opposite, and hence do
  4830. not establish any contradiction with the subject, but only with its
  4831. predicate, which has been conjoined with the subject synthetically--a
  4832. contradiction, moreover, which obtains only when the first and second
  4833. predicate are affirmed in the same time. If I say: "A man who is
  4834. ignorant is not learned," the condition "at the same time" must be
  4835. added, for he who is at one time ignorant, may at another be learned.
  4836. But if I say: "No ignorant man is a learned man," the proposition is
  4837. analytical, because the characteristic ignorance is now a constituent
  4838. part of the conception of the subject; and in this case the
  4839. negative proposition is evident immediately from the proposition of
  4840. contradiction, without the necessity of adding the condition "the
  4841. same time." This is the reason why I have altered the formula of this
  4842. principle--an alteration which shows very clearly the nature of an
  4843. analytical proposition.
  4844. SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements.
  4845. The explanation of the possibility of synthetical judgements is a task
  4846. with which general logic has nothing to do; indeed she needs not even
  4847. be acquainted with its name. But in transcendental logic it is the most
  4848. important matter to be dealt with--indeed the only one, if the question
  4849. is of the possibility of synthetical judgements a priori, the conditions
  4850. and extent of their validity. For when this question is fully decided,
  4851. it can reach its aim with perfect ease, the determination, to wit, of
  4852. the extent and limits of the pure understanding.
  4853. In an analytical judgement I do not go beyond the given conception,
  4854. in order to arrive at some decision respecting it. If the judgement is
  4855. affirmative, I predicate of the conception only that which was already
  4856. cogitated in it; if negative, I merely exclude from the conception its
  4857. contrary. But in synthetical judgements, I must go beyond the given
  4858. conception, in order to cogitate, in relation with it, something quite
  4859. different from that which was cogitated in it, a relation which is
  4860. consequently never one either of identity or contradiction, and by means
  4861. of which the truth or error of the judgement cannot be discerned merely
  4862. from the judgement itself.
  4863. Granted, then, that we must go out beyond a given conception, in order
  4864. to compare it synthetically with another, a third thing is necessary, in
  4865. which alone the synthesis of two conceptions can originate. Now what
  4866. is this tertium quid that is to be the medium of all synthetical
  4867. judgements? It is only a complex in which all our representations are
  4868. contained, the internal sense to wit, and its form a priori, time.
  4869. The synthesis of our representations rests upon the imagination; their
  4870. synthetical unity (which is requisite to a judgement), upon the unity
  4871. of apperception. In this, therefore, is to be sought the possibility of
  4872. synthetical judgements, and as all three contain the sources of a priori
  4873. representations, the possibility of pure synthetical judgements also;
  4874. nay, they are necessary upon these grounds, if we are to possess
  4875. a knowledge of objects, which rests solely upon the synthesis of
  4876. representations.
  4877. If a cognition is to have objective reality, that is, to relate to an
  4878. object, and possess sense and meaning in respect to it, it is necessary
  4879. that the object be given in some way or another. Without this, our
  4880. conceptions are empty, and we may indeed have thought by means of them,
  4881. but by such thinking we have not, in fact, cognized anything, we have
  4882. merely played with representation. To give an object, if this expression
  4883. be understood in the sense of "to present" the object, not mediately
  4884. but immediately in intuition, means nothing else than to apply the
  4885. representation of it to experience, be that experience real or only
  4886. possible. Space and time themselves, pure as these conceptions are from
  4887. all that is empirical, and certain as it is that they are represented
  4888. fully a priori in the mind, would be completely without objective
  4889. validity, and without sense and significance, if their necessary use
  4890. in the objects of experience were not shown. Nay, the representation
  4891. of them is a mere schema, that always relates to the reproductive
  4892. imagination, which calls up the objects of experience, without which
  4893. they have no meaning. And so it is with all conceptions without
  4894. distinction.
  4895. The possibility of experience is, then, that which gives objective
  4896. reality to all our a priori cognitions. Now experience depends upon the
  4897. synthetical unity of phenomena, that is, upon a synthesis according to
  4898. conceptions of the object of phenomena in general, a synthesis without
  4899. which experience never could become knowledge, but would be merely a
  4900. rhapsody of perceptions, never fitting together into any connected text,
  4901. according to rules of a thoroughly united (possible) consciousness, and
  4902. therefore never subjected to the transcendental and necessary unity
  4903. of apperception. Experience has therefore for a foundation, a priori
  4904. principles of its form, that is to say, general rules of unity in
  4905. the synthesis of phenomena, the objective reality of which rules, as
  4906. necessary conditions even of the possibility of experience can
  4907. which rules, as necessary conditions--even of the possibility of
  4908. experience--can always be shown in experience. But apart from this
  4909. relation, a priori synthetical propositions are absolutely impossible,
  4910. because they have no third term, that is, no pure object, in which the
  4911. synthetical unity can exhibit the objective reality of its conceptions.
  4912. Although, then, respecting space, or the forms which productive
  4913. imagination describes therein, we do cognize much a priori in
  4914. synthetical judgements, and are really in no need of experience for this
  4915. purpose, such knowledge would nevertheless amount to nothing but a busy
  4916. trifling with a mere chimera, were not space to be considered as the
  4917. condition of the phenomena which constitute the material of external
  4918. experience. Hence those pure synthetical judgements do relate, though
  4919. but mediately, to possible experience, or rather to the possibility of
  4920. experience, and upon that alone is founded the objective validity of
  4921. their synthesis.
  4922. While then, on the one hand, experience, as empirical synthesis, is
  4923. the only possible mode of cognition which gives reality to all other
  4924. synthesis; on the other hand, this latter synthesis, as cognition a
  4925. priori, possesses truth, that is, accordance with its object, only in
  4926. so far as it contains nothing more than what is necessary to the
  4927. synthetical unity of experience.
  4928. Accordingly, the supreme principle of all synthetical judgements is:
  4929. "Every object is subject to the necessary conditions of the synthetical
  4930. unity of the manifold of intuition in a possible experience."
  4931. A priori synthetical judgements are possible when we apply the formal
  4932. conditions of the a priori intuition, the synthesis of the imagination,
  4933. and the necessary unity of that synthesis in a transcendental
  4934. apperception, to a possible cognition of experience, and say: "The
  4935. conditions of the possibility of experience in general are at the same
  4936. time conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience, and
  4937. have, for that reason, objective validity in an a priori synthetical
  4938. judgement."
  4939. SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of
  4940. the Pure Understanding.
  4941. That principles exist at all is to be ascribed solely to the pure
  4942. understanding, which is not only the faculty of rules in regard to that
  4943. which happens, but is even the source of principles according to which
  4944. everything that can be presented to us as an object is necessarily
  4945. subject to rules, because without such rules we never could attain
  4946. to cognition of an object. Even the laws of nature, if they are
  4947. contemplated as principles of the empirical use of the understanding,
  4948. possess also a characteristic of necessity, and we may therefore at
  4949. least expect them to be determined upon grounds which are valid a
  4950. priori and antecedent to all experience. But all laws of nature, without
  4951. distinction, are subject to higher principles of the understanding,
  4952. inasmuch as the former are merely applications of the latter to
  4953. particular cases of experience. These higher principles alone therefore
  4954. give the conception, which contains the necessary condition, and, as it
  4955. were, the exponent of a rule; experience, on the other hand, gives the
  4956. case which comes under the rule.
  4957. There is no danger of our mistaking merely empirical principles for
  4958. principles of the pure understanding, or conversely; for the character
  4959. of necessity, according to conceptions which distinguish the latter,
  4960. and the absence of this in every empirical proposition, how extensively
  4961. valid soever it may be, is a perfect safeguard against confounding
  4962. them. There are, however, pure principles a priori, which nevertheless I
  4963. should not ascribe to the pure understanding--for this reason, that they
  4964. are not derived from pure conceptions, but (although by the mediation
  4965. of the understanding) from pure intuitions. But understanding is the
  4966. faculty of conceptions. Such principles mathematical science possesses,
  4967. but their application to experience, consequently their objective
  4968. validity, nay the possibility of such a priori synthetical cognitions
  4969. (the deduction thereof) rests entirely upon the pure understanding.
  4970. On this account, I shall not reckon among my principles those of
  4971. mathematics; though I shall include those upon the possibility and
  4972. objective validity a priori, of principles of the mathematical science,
  4973. which, consequently, are to be looked upon as the principle of these,
  4974. and which proceed from conceptions to intuition, and not from intuition
  4975. to conceptions.
  4976. In the application of the pure conceptions of the understanding to
  4977. possible experience, the employment of their synthesis is either
  4978. mathematical or dynamical, for it is directed partly on the intuition
  4979. alone, partly on the existence of a phenomenon. But the a priori
  4980. conditions of intuition are in relation to a possible experience
  4981. absolutely necessary, those of the existence of objects of a possible
  4982. empirical intuition are in themselves contingent. Hence the principles
  4983. of the mathematical use of the categories will possess a character of
  4984. absolute necessity, that is, will be apodeictic; those, on the other
  4985. hand, of the dynamical use, the character of an a priori necessity
  4986. indeed, but only under the condition of empirical thought in an
  4987. experience, therefore only mediately and indirectly. Consequently
  4988. they will not possess that immediate evidence which is peculiar to the
  4989. former, although their application to experience does not, for that
  4990. reason, lose its truth and certitude. But of this point we shall be
  4991. better able to judge at the conclusion of this system of principles.
  4992. The table of the categories is naturally our guide to the table of
  4993. principles, because these are nothing else than rules for the objective
  4994. employment of the former. Accordingly, all principles of the pure
  4995. understanding are:
  4996. 1
  4997. Axioms
  4998. of Intuition
  4999. 2 3
  5000. Anticipations Analogies
  5001. of Perception of Experience
  5002. 4
  5003. Postulates of
  5004. Empirical Thought
  5005. in general
  5006. These appellations I have chosen advisedly, in order that we might
  5007. not lose sight of the distinctions in respect of the evidence and the
  5008. employment of these principles. It will, however, soon appear that--a
  5009. fact which concerns both the evidence of these principles, and the
  5010. a priori determination of phenomena--according to the categories of
  5011. quantity and quality (if we attend merely to the form of these), the
  5012. principles of these categories are distinguishable from those of the two
  5013. others, in as much as the former are possessed of an intuitive, but
  5014. the latter of a merely discursive, though in both instances a complete,
  5015. certitude. I shall therefore call the former mathematical, and the
  5016. latter dynamical principles.* It must be observed, however, that by
  5017. these terms I mean just as little in the one case the principles of
  5018. mathematics as those of general (physical) dynamics in the other. I have
  5019. here in view merely the principles of the pure understanding, in
  5020. their application to the internal sense (without distinction of the
  5021. representations given therein), by means of which the sciences of
  5022. mathematics and dynamics become possible. Accordingly, I have named
  5023. these principles rather with reference to their application than their
  5024. content; and I shall now proceed to consider them in the order in which
  5025. they stand in the table.
  5026. [*Footnote: All combination (conjunctio) is either
  5027. composition (compositio) or connection (nexus). The former
  5028. is the synthesis of a manifold, the parts of which do not
  5029. necessarily belong to each other. For example, the two
  5030. triangles into which a square is divided by a diagonal, do
  5031. not necessarily belong to each other, and of this kind is
  5032. the synthesis of the homogeneous in everything that can be
  5033. mathematically considered. This synthesis can be divided
  5034. into those of aggregation and coalition, the former of which
  5035. is applied to extensive, the latter to intensive quantities.
  5036. The second sort of combination (nexus) is the synthesis of a
  5037. manifold, in so far as its parts do belong necessarily to
  5038. each other; for example, the accident to a substance, or the
  5039. effect to the cause. Consequently it is a synthesis of that
  5040. which though heterogeneous, is represented as connected a
  5041. priori. This combination--not an arbitrary one--I entitle
  5042. dynamical because it concerns the connection of the
  5043. existence of the manifold. This, again, may be divided into
  5044. the physical synthesis, of the phenomena divided among each
  5045. other, and the metaphysical synthesis, or the connection of
  5046. phenomena a priori in the faculty of cognition.]
  5047. 1. AXIOMS OF INTUITION.
  5048. The principle of these is: All Intuitions are Extensive Quantities.
  5049. PROOF.
  5050. All phenomena contain, as regards their form, an intuition in space and
  5051. time, which lies a priori at the foundation of all without exception.
  5052. Phenomena, therefore, cannot be apprehended, that is, received into
  5053. empirical consciousness otherwise than through the synthesis of a
  5054. manifold, through which the representations of a determinate space
  5055. or time are generated; that is to say, through the composition of the
  5056. homogeneous and the consciousness of the synthetical unity of this
  5057. manifold (homogeneous). Now the consciousness of a homogeneous manifold
  5058. in intuition, in so far as thereby the representation of an object
  5059. is rendered possible, is the conception of a quantity (quanti).
  5060. Consequently, even the perception of an object as phenomenon is possible
  5061. only through the same synthetical unity of the manifold of the given
  5062. sensuous intuition, through which the unity of the composition of the
  5063. homogeneous manifold in the conception of a quantity is cogitated;
  5064. that is to say, all phenomena are quantities, and extensive quantities,
  5065. because as intuitions in space or time they must be represented by
  5066. means of the same synthesis through which space and time themselves are
  5067. determined.
  5068. An extensive quantity I call that wherein the representation of the
  5069. parts renders possible (and therefore necessarily antecedes) the
  5070. representation of the whole. I cannot represent to myself any line,
  5071. however small, without drawing it in thought, that is, without
  5072. generating from a point all its parts one after another, and in this
  5073. way alone producing this intuition. Precisely the same is the case with
  5074. every, even the smallest, portion of time. I cogitate therein only the
  5075. successive progress from one moment to another, and hence, by means of
  5076. the different portions of time and the addition of them, a determinate
  5077. quantity of time is produced. As the pure intuition in all phenomena
  5078. is either time or space, so is every phenomenon in its character of
  5079. intuition an extensive quantity, inasmuch as it can only be cognized
  5080. in our apprehension by successive synthesis (from part to part). All
  5081. phenomena are, accordingly, to be considered as aggregates, that is, as
  5082. a collection of previously given parts; which is not the case with
  5083. every sort of quantities, but only with those which are represented and
  5084. apprehended by us as extensive.
  5085. On this successive synthesis of the productive imagination, in the
  5086. generation of figures, is founded the mathematics of extension, or
  5087. geometry, with its axioms, which express the conditions of sensuous
  5088. intuition a priori, under which alone the schema of a pure conception of
  5089. external intuition can exist; for example, "be tween two points only one
  5090. straight line is possible," "two straight lines cannot enclose a space,"
  5091. etc. These are the axioms which properly relate only to quantities
  5092. (quanta) as such.
  5093. But, as regards the quantity of a thing (quantitas), that is to say, the
  5094. answer to the question: "How large is this or that object?" although, in
  5095. respect to this question, we have various propositions synthetical and
  5096. immediately certain (indemonstrabilia); we have, in the proper sense of
  5097. the term, no axioms. For example, the propositions: "If equals be added
  5098. to equals, the wholes are equal"; "If equals be taken from equals,
  5099. the remainders are equal"; are analytical, because I am immediately
  5100. conscious of the identity of the production of the one quantity with
  5101. the production of the other; whereas axioms must be a priori synthetical
  5102. propositions. On the other hand, the self-evident propositions as to the
  5103. relation of numbers, are certainly synthetical but not universal, like
  5104. those of geometry, and for this reason cannot be called axioms, but
  5105. numerical formulae. That 7 + 5 = 12 is not an analytical proposition.
  5106. For neither in the representation of seven, nor of five, nor of the
  5107. composition of the two numbers, do I cogitate the number twelve.
  5108. (Whether I cogitate the number in the addition of both, is not at
  5109. present the question; for in the case of an analytical proposition,
  5110. the only point is whether I really cogitate the predicate in the
  5111. representation of the subject.) But although the proposition is
  5112. synthetical, it is nevertheless only a singular proposition. In so far
  5113. as regard is here had merely to the synthesis of the homogeneous (the
  5114. units), it cannot take place except in one manner, although our use
  5115. of these numbers is afterwards general. If I say: "A triangle can
  5116. be constructed with three lines, any two of which taken together are
  5117. greater than the third," I exercise merely the pure function of the
  5118. productive imagination, which may draw the lines longer or shorter and
  5119. construct the angles at its pleasure. On the contrary, the number seven
  5120. is possible only in one manner, and so is likewise the number twelve,
  5121. which results from the synthesis of seven and five. Such propositions,
  5122. then, cannot be termed axioms (for in that case we should have an
  5123. infinity of these), but numerical formulae.
  5124. This transcendental principle of the mathematics of phenomena greatly
  5125. enlarges our a priori cognition. For it is by this principle alone that
  5126. pure mathematics is rendered applicable in all its precision to objects
  5127. of experience, and without it the validity of this application would not
  5128. be so self-evident; on the contrary, contradictions and confusions have
  5129. often arisen on this very point. Phenomena are not things in themselves.
  5130. Empirical intuition is possible only through pure intuition (of space
  5131. and time); consequently, what geometry affirms of the latter, is
  5132. indisputably valid of the former. All evasions, such as the statement
  5133. that objects of sense do not conform to the rules of construction in
  5134. space (for example, to the rule of the infinite divisibility of lines or
  5135. angles), must fall to the ground. For, if these objections hold good, we
  5136. deny to space, and with it to all mathematics, objective validity, and
  5137. no longer know wherefore, and how far, mathematics can be applied to
  5138. phenomena. The synthesis of spaces and times as the essential form of
  5139. all intuition, is that which renders possible the apprehension of a
  5140. phenomenon, and therefore every external experience, consequently all
  5141. cognition of the objects of experience; and whatever mathematics in its
  5142. pure use proves of the former, must necessarily hold good of the latter.
  5143. All objections are but the chicaneries of an ill-instructed reason,
  5144. which erroneously thinks to liberate the objects of sense from the
  5145. formal conditions of our sensibility, and represents these, although
  5146. mere phenomena, as things in themselves, presented as such to our
  5147. understanding. But in this case, no a priori synthetical cognition of
  5148. them could be possible, consequently not through pure conceptions of
  5149. space and the science which determines these conceptions, that is to
  5150. say, geometry, would itself be impossible.
  5151. 2. ANTICIPATIONS OF PERCEPTION.
  5152. The principle of these is: In all phenomena the Real, that which is an
  5153. object of sensation, has Intensive Quantity, that is, has a Degree.
  5154. PROOF.
  5155. Perception is empirical consciousness, that is to say, a consciousness
  5156. which contains an element of sensation. Phenomena as objects of
  5157. perception are not pure, that is, merely formal intuitions, like space
  5158. and time, for they cannot be perceived in themselves.
  5159. [Footnote: They can be perceived only as phenomena, and some
  5160. part of them must always belong to the non-ego; whereas pure
  5161. intuitions are entirely the products of the mind itself, and
  5162. as such are coguized IN THEMSELVES.--Tr]
  5163. They contain, then, over and above the intuition, the materials for an
  5164. object (through which is represented something existing in space or
  5165. time), that is to say, they contain the real of sensation, as a
  5166. representation merely subjective, which gives us merely the
  5167. consciousness that the subject is affected, and which we refer to some
  5168. external object. Now, a gradual transition from empirical consciousness
  5169. to pure consciousness is possible, inasmuch as the real in this
  5170. consciousness entirely vanishes, and there remains a merely formal
  5171. consciousness (a priori) of the manifold in time and space; consequently
  5172. there is possible a synthesis also of the production of the quantity of
  5173. a sensation from its commencement, that is, from the pure intuition = 0
  5174. onwards up to a certain quantity of the sensation. Now as sensation in
  5175. itself is not an objective representation, and in it is to be found
  5176. neither the intuition of space nor of time, it cannot possess any
  5177. extensive quantity, and yet there does belong to it a quantity (and that
  5178. by means of its apprehension, in which empirical consciousness can
  5179. within a certain time rise from nothing = 0 up to its given amount),
  5180. consequently an intensive quantity. And thus we must ascribe intensive
  5181. quantity, that is, a degree of influence on sense to all objects of
  5182. perception, in so far as this perception contains sensation.
  5183. All cognition, by means of which I am enabled to cognize and determine
  5184. a priori what belongs to empirical cognition, may be called an
  5185. anticipation; and without doubt this is the sense in which Epicurus
  5186. employed his expression prholepsis. But as there is in phenomena
  5187. something which is never cognized a priori, which on this account
  5188. constitutes the proper difference between pure and empirical cognition,
  5189. that is to say, sensation (as the matter of perception), it follows,
  5190. that sensation is just that element in cognition which cannot be at
  5191. all anticipated. On the other hand, we might very well term the pure
  5192. determinations in space and time, as well in regard to figure as to
  5193. quantity, anticipations of phenomena, because they represent a priori
  5194. that which may always be given a posteriori in experience. But suppose
  5195. that in every sensation, as sensation in general, without any particular
  5196. sensation being thought of, there existed something which could be
  5197. cognized a priori, this would deserve to be called anticipation in a
  5198. special sense--special, because it may seem surprising to forestall
  5199. experience, in that which concerns the matter of experience, and which
  5200. we can only derive from itself. Yet such really is the case here.
  5201. Apprehension*, by means of sensation alone, fills only one moment, that
  5202. is, if I do not take into consideration a succession of many sensations.
  5203. As that in the phenomenon, the apprehension of which is not a successive
  5204. synthesis advancing from parts to an entire representation, sensation
  5205. has therefore no extensive quantity; the want of sensation in a moment
  5206. of time would represent it as empty, consequently = 0. That which in
  5207. the empirical intuition corresponds to sensation is reality (realitas
  5208. phaenomenon); that which corresponds to the absence of it, negation = 0.
  5209. Now every sensation is capable of a diminution, so that it can decrease,
  5210. and thus gradually disappear. Therefore, between reality in a phenomenon
  5211. and negation, there exists a continuous concatenation of many possible
  5212. intermediate sensations, the difference of which from each other is
  5213. always smaller than that between the given sensation and zero, or
  5214. complete negation. That is to say, the real in a phenomenon has always a
  5215. quantity, which however is not discoverable in apprehension, inasmuch as
  5216. apprehension take place by means of mere sensation in one instant, and
  5217. not by the successive synthesis of many sensations, and therefore does
  5218. not progress from parts to the whole. Consequently, it has a quantity,
  5219. but not an extensive quantity.
  5220. [*Footnote: Apprehension is the Kantian word for preception, in the
  5221. largest sense in which we employ that term. It is the genus which
  5222. includes under i, as species, perception proper and sensation
  5223. proper--Tr]
  5224. Now that quantity which is apprehended only as unity, and in which
  5225. plurality can be represented only by approximation to negation = O,
  5226. I term intensive quantity. Consequently, reality in a phenomenon has
  5227. intensive quantity, that is, a degree. If we consider this reality as
  5228. cause (be it of sensation or of another reality in the phenomenon, for
  5229. example, a change), we call the degree of reality in its character of
  5230. cause a momentum, for example, the momentum of weight; and for this
  5231. reason, that the degree only indicates that quantity the apprehension of
  5232. which is not successive, but instantaneous. This, however, I touch upon
  5233. only in passing, for with causality I have at present nothing to do.
  5234. Accordingly, every sensation, consequently every reality in phenomena,
  5235. however small it may be, has a degree, that is, an intensive quantity,
  5236. which may always be lessened, and between reality and negation there
  5237. exists a continuous connection of possible realities, and possible
  5238. smaller perceptions. Every colour--for example, red--has a degree,
  5239. which, be it ever so small, is never the smallest, and so is it always
  5240. with heat, the momentum of weight, etc.
  5241. This property of quantities, according to which no part of them is the
  5242. smallest possible (no part simple), is called their continuity. Space
  5243. and time are quanta continua, because no part of them can be
  5244. given, without enclosing it within boundaries (points and moments),
  5245. consequently, this given part is itself a space or a time. Space,
  5246. therefore, consists only of spaces, and time of times. Points and
  5247. moments are only boundaries, that is, the mere places or positions of
  5248. their limitation. But places always presuppose intuitions which are to
  5249. limit or determine them; and we cannot conceive either space or time
  5250. composed of constituent parts which are given before space or time.
  5251. Such quantities may also be called flowing, because synthesis (of the
  5252. productive imagination) in the production of these quantities is a
  5253. progression in time, the continuity of which we are accustomed to
  5254. indicate by the expression flowing.
  5255. All phenomena, then, are continuous quantities, in respect both to
  5256. intuition and mere perception (sensation, and with it reality). In the
  5257. former case they are extensive quantities; in the latter, intensive.
  5258. When the synthesis of the manifold of a phenomenon is interrupted, there
  5259. results merely an aggregate of several phenomena, and not properly a
  5260. phenomenon as a quantity, which is not produced by the mere continuation
  5261. of the productive synthesis of a certain kind, but by the repetition of
  5262. a synthesis always ceasing. For example, if I call thirteen dollars a
  5263. sum or quantity of money, I employ the term quite correctly, inasmuch as
  5264. I understand by thirteen dollars the value of a mark in standard silver,
  5265. which is, to be sure, a continuous quantity, in which no part is the
  5266. smallest, but every part might constitute a piece of money, which would
  5267. contain material for still smaller pieces. If, however, by the words
  5268. thirteen dollars I understand so many coins (be their value in silver
  5269. what it may), it would be quite erroneous to use the expression a
  5270. quantity of dollars; on the contrary, I must call them aggregate, that
  5271. is, a number of coins. And as in every number we must have unity as the
  5272. foundation, so a phenomenon taken as unity is a quantity, and as such
  5273. always a continuous quantity (quantum continuum).
  5274. Now, seeing all phenomena, whether considered as extensive or intensive,
  5275. are continuous quantities, the proposition: "All change (transition of a
  5276. thing from one state into another) is continuous," might be proved here
  5277. easily, and with mathematical evidence, were it not that the causality
  5278. of a change lies, entirely beyond the bounds of a transcendental
  5279. philosophy, and presupposes empirical principles. For of the possibility
  5280. of a cause which changes the condition of things, that is, which
  5281. determines them to the contrary to a certain given state, the
  5282. understanding gives us a priori no knowledge; not merely because it has
  5283. no insight into the possibility of it (for such insight is absent in
  5284. several a priori cognitions), but because the notion of change concerns
  5285. only certain determinations of phenomena, which experience alone can
  5286. acquaint us with, while their cause lies in the unchangeable. But seeing
  5287. that we have nothing which we could here employ but the pure fundamental
  5288. conceptions of all possible experience, among which of course nothing
  5289. empirical can be admitted, we dare not, without injuring the unity of
  5290. our system, anticipate general physical science, which is built upon
  5291. certain fundamental experiences.
  5292. Nevertheless, we are in no want of proofs of the great influence
  5293. which the principle above developed exercises in the anticipation of
  5294. perceptions, and even in supplying the want of them, so far as to shield
  5295. us against the false conclusions which otherwise we might rashly draw.
  5296. If all reality in perception has a degree, between which and negation
  5297. there is an endless sequence of ever smaller degrees, and if,
  5298. nevertheless, every sense must have a determinate degree of receptivity
  5299. for sensations; no perception, and consequently no experience is
  5300. possible, which can prove, either immediately or mediately, an entire
  5301. absence of all reality in a phenomenon; in other words, it is impossible
  5302. ever to draw from experience a proof of the existence of empty space or
  5303. of empty time. For in the first place, an entire absence of reality in
  5304. a sensuous intuition cannot of course be an object of perception;
  5305. secondly, such absence cannot be deduced from the contemplation of any
  5306. single phenomenon, and the difference of the degrees in its reality; nor
  5307. ought it ever to be admitted in explanation of any phenomenon. For if
  5308. even the complete intuition of a determinate space or time is thoroughly
  5309. real, that is, if no part thereof is empty, yet because every reality
  5310. has its degree, which, with the extensive quantity of the phenomenon
  5311. unchanged, can diminish through endless gradations down to nothing (the
  5312. void), there must be infinitely graduated degrees, with which space or
  5313. time is filled, and the intensive quantity in different phenomena may
  5314. be smaller or greater, although the extensive quantity of the intuition
  5315. remains equal and unaltered.
  5316. We shall give an example of this. Almost all natural philosophers,
  5317. remarking a great difference in the quantity of the matter of different
  5318. kinds in bodies with the same volume (partly on account of the momentum
  5319. of gravity or weight, partly on account of the momentum of resistance
  5320. to other bodies in motion), conclude unanimously that this volume
  5321. (extensive quantity of the phenomenon) must be void in all bodies,
  5322. although in different proportion. But who would suspect that these for
  5323. the most part mathematical and mechanical inquirers into nature should
  5324. ground this conclusion solely on a metaphysical hypothesis--a sort of
  5325. hypothesis which they profess to disparage and avoid? Yet this they
  5326. do, in assuming that the real in space (I must not here call it
  5327. impenetrability or weight, because these are empirical conceptions)
  5328. is always identical, and can only be distinguished according to its
  5329. extensive quantity, that is, multiplicity. Now to this presupposition,
  5330. for which they can have no ground in experience, and which consequently
  5331. is merely metaphysical, I oppose a transcendental demonstration, which
  5332. it is true will not explain the difference in the filling up of spaces,
  5333. but which nevertheless completely does away with the supposed necessity
  5334. of the above-mentioned presupposition that we cannot explain the said
  5335. difference otherwise than by the hypothesis of empty spaces. This
  5336. demonstration, moreover, has the merit of setting the understanding
  5337. at liberty to conceive this distinction in a different manner, if the
  5338. explanation of the fact requires any such hypothesis. For we perceive
  5339. that although two equal spaces may be completely filled by matters
  5340. altogether different, so that in neither of them is there left a single
  5341. point wherein matter is not present, nevertheless, every reality has its
  5342. degree (of resistance or of weight), which, without diminution of the
  5343. extensive quantity, can become less and less ad infinitum, before it
  5344. passes into nothingness and disappears. Thus an expansion which fills
  5345. a space--for example, caloric, or any other reality in the phenomenal
  5346. world--can decrease in its degrees to infinity, yet without leaving the
  5347. smallest part of the space empty; on the contrary, filling it with those
  5348. lesser degrees as completely as another phenomenon could with greater.
  5349. My intention here is by no means to maintain that this is really
  5350. the case with the difference of matters, in regard to their
  5351. specific gravity; I wish only to prove, from a principle of the pure
  5352. understanding, that the nature of our perceptions makes such a mode of
  5353. explanation possible, and that it is erroneous to regard the real in
  5354. a phenomenon as equal quoad its degree, and different only quoad its
  5355. aggregation and extensive quantity, and this, too, on the pretended
  5356. authority of an a priori principle of the understanding.
  5357. Nevertheless, this principle of the anticipation of perception must
  5358. somewhat startle an inquirer whom initiation into transcendental
  5359. philosophy has rendered cautious. We must naturally entertain some
  5360. doubt whether or not the understanding can enounce any such synthetical
  5361. proposition as that respecting the degree of all reality in phenomena,
  5362. and consequently the possibility of the internal difference of sensation
  5363. itself--abstraction being made of its empirical quality. Thus it is a
  5364. question not unworthy of solution: "How the understanding can pronounce
  5365. synthetically and a priori respecting phenomena, and thus anticipate
  5366. these, even in that which is peculiarly and merely empirical, that,
  5367. namely, which concerns sensation itself?"
  5368. The quality of sensation is in all cases merely empirical, and cannot
  5369. be represented a priori (for example, colours, taste, etc.). But the
  5370. real--that which corresponds to sensation--in opposition to negation =
  5371. 0, only represents something the conception of which in itself contains
  5372. a being (ein seyn), and signifies nothing but the synthesis in an
  5373. empirical consciousness. That is to say, the empirical consciousness in
  5374. the internal sense can be raised from 0 to every higher degree, so that
  5375. the very same extensive quantity of intuition, an illuminated surface,
  5376. for example, excites as great a sensation as an aggregate of many other
  5377. surfaces less illuminated. We can therefore make complete abstraction
  5378. of the extensive quantity of a phenomenon, and represent to ourselves
  5379. in the mere sensation in a certain momentum, a synthesis of homogeneous
  5380. ascension from 0 up to the given empirical consciousness, All sensations
  5381. therefore as such are given only a posteriori, but this property
  5382. thereof, namely, that they have a degree, can be known a priori. It
  5383. is worthy of remark, that in respect to quantities in general, we can
  5384. cognize a priori only a single quality, namely, continuity; but in
  5385. respect to all quality (the real in phenomena), we cannot cognize a
  5386. priori anything more than the intensive quantity thereof, namely, that
  5387. they have a degree. All else is left to experience.
  5388. 3. ANALOGIES OF EXPERIENCE.
  5389. The principle of these is: Experience is possible only through the
  5390. representation of a necessary connection of Perceptions.
  5391. PROOF.
  5392. Experience is an empirical cognition; that is to say, a cognition
  5393. which determines an object by means of perceptions. It is therefore a
  5394. synthesis of perceptions, a synthesis which is not itself contained in
  5395. perception, but which contains the synthetical unity of the manifold of
  5396. perception in a consciousness; and this unity constitutes the essential
  5397. of our cognition of objects of the senses, that is, of experience (not
  5398. merely of intuition or sensation). Now in experience our perceptions
  5399. come together contingently, so that no character of necessity in their
  5400. connection appears, or can appear from the perceptions themselves,
  5401. because apprehension is only a placing together of the manifold of
  5402. empirical intuition, and no representation of a necessity in the
  5403. connected existence of the phenomena which apprehension brings together,
  5404. is to be discovered therein. But as experience is a cognition of objects
  5405. by means of perceptions, it follows that the relation of the existence
  5406. of the existence of the manifold must be represented in experience not
  5407. as it is put together in time, but as it is objectively in time. And as
  5408. time itself cannot be perceived, the determination of the existence of
  5409. objects in time can only take place by means of their connection in
  5410. time in general, consequently only by means of a priori connecting
  5411. conceptions. Now as these conceptions always possess the character of
  5412. necessity, experience is possible only by means of a representation of
  5413. the necessary connection of perception.
  5414. The three modi of time are permanence, succession, and coexistence.
  5415. Accordingly, there are three rules of all relations of time in
  5416. phenomena, according to which the existence of every phenomenon is
  5417. determined in respect of the unity of all time, and these antecede all
  5418. experience and render it possible.
  5419. The general principle of all three analogies rests on the necessary
  5420. unity of apperception in relation to all possible empirical
  5421. consciousness (perception) at every time, consequently, as this unity
  5422. lies a priori at the foundation of all mental operations, the principle
  5423. rests on the synthetical unity of all phenomena according to their
  5424. relation in time. For the original apperception relates to our internal
  5425. sense (the complex of all representations), and indeed relates a priori
  5426. to its form, that is to say, the relation of the manifold empirical
  5427. consciousness in time. Now this manifold must be combined in original
  5428. apperception according to relations of time--a necessity imposed by the
  5429. a priori transcendental unity of apperception, to which is subjected all
  5430. that can belong to my (i.e., my own) cognition, and therefore all that
  5431. can become an object for me. This synthetical and a priori determined
  5432. unity in relation of perceptions in time is therefore the rule: "All
  5433. empirical determinations of time must be subject to rules of the general
  5434. determination of time"; and the analogies of experience, of which we are
  5435. now about to treat, must be rules of this nature.
  5436. These principles have this peculiarity, that they do not concern
  5437. phenomena, and the synthesis of the empirical intuition thereof, but
  5438. merely the existence of phenomena and their relation to each other in
  5439. regard to this existence. Now the mode in which we apprehend a thing in
  5440. a phenomenon can be determined a priori in such a manner that the rule
  5441. of its synthesis can give, that is to say, can produce this a priori
  5442. intuition in every empirical example. But the existence of phenomena
  5443. cannot be known a priori, and although we could arrive by this path at
  5444. a conclusion of the fact of some existence, we could not cognize that
  5445. existence determinately, that is to say, we should be incapable of
  5446. anticipating in what respect the empirical intuition of it would be
  5447. distinguishable from that of others.
  5448. The two principles above mentioned, which I called mathematical, in
  5449. consideration of the fact of their authorizing the application of
  5450. mathematic phenomena, relate to these phenomena only in regard to their
  5451. possibility, and instruct us how phenomena, as far as regards their
  5452. intuition or the real in their perception, can be generated according
  5453. to the rules of a mathematical synthesis. Consequently, numerical
  5454. quantities, and with them the determination of a phenomenon as a
  5455. quantity, can be employed in the one case as well as in the other. Thus,
  5456. for example, out of 200,000 illuminations by the moon, I might compose
  5457. and give a priori, that is construct, the degree of our sensations
  5458. of the sun-light.* We may therefore entitle these two principles
  5459. constitutive.
  5460. [*Footnote: Kant's meaning is: The two principles enunciated under
  5461. the heads of "Axioms of Intuition," and "Anticipations of Perception,"
  5462. authorize the application to phenomena of determinations of size and
  5463. number, that is of mathematic. For example, I may compute the light of
  5464. the sun, and say that its quantity is a certain number of times
  5465. greater than that of the moon. In the same way, heat is measured by the
  5466. comparison of its different effects on water, &c., and on mercury in a
  5467. thermometer.--Tr]
  5468. The case is very different with those principles whose province it is to
  5469. subject the existence of phenomena to rules a priori. For as existence
  5470. does not admit of being constructed, it is clear that they must only
  5471. concern the relations of existence and be merely regulative principles.
  5472. In this case, therefore, neither axioms nor anticipations are to be
  5473. thought of. Thus, if a perception is given us, in a certain relation of
  5474. time to other (although undetermined) perceptions, we cannot then say
  5475. a priori, what and how great (in quantity) the other perception
  5476. necessarily connected with the former is, but only how it is connected,
  5477. quoad its existence, in this given modus of time. Analogies in
  5478. philosophy mean something very different from that which they represent
  5479. in mathematics. In the latter they are formulae, which enounce the
  5480. equality of two relations of quantity, and are always constitutive, so
  5481. that if two terms of the proportion are given, the third is also
  5482. given, that is, can be constructed by the aid of these formulae. But in
  5483. philosophy, analogy is not the equality of two quantitative but of two
  5484. qualitative relations. In this case, from three given terms, I can
  5485. give a priori and cognize the relation to a fourth member, but not this
  5486. fourth term itself, although I certainly possess a rule to guide me in
  5487. the search for this fourth term in experience, and a mark to assist me
  5488. in discovering it. An analogy of experience is therefore only a rule
  5489. according to which unity of experience must arise out of perceptions in
  5490. respect to objects (phenomena) not as a constitutive, but merely as
  5491. a regulative principle. The same holds good also of the postulates of
  5492. empirical thought in general, which relate to the synthesis of mere
  5493. intuition (which concerns the form of phenomena), the synthesis of
  5494. perception (which concerns the matter of phenomena), and the synthesis
  5495. of experience (which concerns the relation of these perceptions). For
  5496. they are only regulative principles, and clearly distinguishable from
  5497. the mathematical, which are constitutive, not indeed in regard to the
  5498. certainty which both possess a priori, but in the mode of evidence
  5499. thereof, consequently also in the manner of demonstration.
  5500. But what has been observed of all synthetical propositions, and must
  5501. be particularly remarked in this place, is this, that these
  5502. analogies possess significance and validity, not as principles of the
  5503. transcendental, but only as principles of the empirical use of the
  5504. understanding, and their truth can therefore be proved only as such, and
  5505. that consequently the phenomena must not be subjoined directly under the
  5506. categories, but only under their schemata. For if the objects to which
  5507. those principles must be applied were things in themselves, it would
  5508. be quite impossible to cognize aught concerning them synthetically a
  5509. priori. But they are nothing but phenomena; a complete knowledge
  5510. of which--a knowledge to which all principles a priori must at
  5511. last relate--is the only possible experience. It follows that these
  5512. principles can have nothing else for their aim than the conditions of
  5513. the empirical cognition in the unity of synthesis of phenomena. But this
  5514. synthesis is cogitated only in the schema of the pure conception of the
  5515. understanding, of whose unity, as that of a synthesis in general, the
  5516. category contains the function unrestricted by any sensuous condition.
  5517. These principles will therefore authorize us to connect phenomena
  5518. according to an analogy, with the logical and universal unity of
  5519. conceptions, and consequently to employ the categories in the principles
  5520. themselves; but in the application of them to experience, we shall use
  5521. only their schemata, as the key to their proper application, instead of
  5522. the categories, or rather the latter as restricting conditions, under
  5523. the title of "formulae" of the former.
  5524. A. FIRST ANALOGY.
  5525. Principle of the Permanence of Substance.
  5526. In all changes of phenomena, substance is permanent, and the quantum
  5527. thereof in nature is neither increased nor diminished.
  5528. PROOF.
  5529. All phenomena exist in time, wherein alone as substratum, that is, as
  5530. the permanent form of the internal intuition, coexistence and succession
  5531. can be represented. Consequently time, in which all changes of phenomena
  5532. must be cogitated, remains and changes not, because it is that in which
  5533. succession and coexistence can be represented only as determinations
  5534. thereof. Now, time in itself cannot be an object of perception. It
  5535. follows that in objects of perception, that is, in phenomena, there must
  5536. be found a substratum which represents time in general, and in which
  5537. all change or coexistence can be perceived by means of the relation of
  5538. phenomena to it. But the substratum of all reality, that is, of all that
  5539. pertains to the existence of things, is substance; all that pertains
  5540. to existence can be cogitated only as a determination of substance.
  5541. Consequently, the permanent, in relation to which alone can all
  5542. relations of time in phenomena be determined, is substance in the
  5543. world of phenomena, that is, the real in phenomena, that which, as the
  5544. substratum of all change, remains ever the same. Accordingly, as this
  5545. cannot change in existence, its quantity in nature can neither be
  5546. increased nor diminished.
  5547. Our apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon is always successive,
  5548. is Consequently always changing. By it alone we could, therefore,
  5549. never determine whether this manifold, as an object of experience, is
  5550. coexistent or successive, unless it had for a foundation something fixed
  5551. and permanent, of the existence of which all succession and coexistence
  5552. are nothing but so many modes (modi of time). Only in the permanent,
  5553. then, are relations of time possible (for simultaneity and succession
  5554. are the only relations in time); that is to say, the permanent is the
  5555. substratum of our empirical representation of time itself, in which
  5556. alone all determination of time is possible. Permanence is, in fact,
  5557. just another expression for time, as the abiding correlate of all
  5558. existence of phenomena, and of all change, and of all coexistence. For
  5559. change does not affect time itself, but only the phenomena in time (just
  5560. as coexistence cannot be regarded as a modus of time itself, seeing
  5561. that in time no parts are coexistent, but all successive). If we were
  5562. to attribute succession to time itself, we should be obliged to cogitate
  5563. another time, in which this succession would be possible. It is only
  5564. by means of the permanent that existence in different parts of the
  5565. successive series of time receives a quantity, which we entitle
  5566. duration. For in mere succession, existence is perpetually vanishing and
  5567. recommencing, and therefore never has even the least quantity. Without
  5568. the permanent, then, no relation in time is possible. Now, time in
  5569. itself is not an object of perception; consequently the permanent in
  5570. phenomena must be regarded as the substratum of all determination of
  5571. time, and consequently also as the condition of the possibility of
  5572. all synthetical unity of perceptions, that is, of experience; and all
  5573. existence and all change in time can only be regarded as a mode in
  5574. the existence of that which abides unchangeably. Therefore, in all
  5575. phenomena, the permanent is the object in itself, that is, the substance
  5576. (phenomenon); but all that changes or can change belongs only to the
  5577. mode of the existence of this substance or substances, consequently to
  5578. its determinations.
  5579. I find that in all ages not only the philosopher, but even the common
  5580. understanding, has preposited this permanence as a substratum of all
  5581. change in phenomena; indeed, I am compelled to believe that they
  5582. will always accept this as an indubitable fact. Only the philosopher
  5583. expresses himself in a more precise and definite manner, when he says:
  5584. "In all changes in the world, the substance remains, and the accidents
  5585. alone are changeable." But of this decidedly synthetical proposition, I
  5586. nowhere meet with even an attempt at proof; nay, it very rarely has the
  5587. good fortune to stand, as it deserves to do, at the head of the pure and
  5588. entirely a priori laws of nature. In truth, the statement that substance
  5589. is permanent, is tautological. For this very permanence is the ground
  5590. on which we apply the category of substance to the phenomenon; and
  5591. we should have been obliged to prove that in all phenomena there is
  5592. something permanent, of the existence of which the changeable is nothing
  5593. but a determination. But because a proof of this nature cannot be
  5594. dogmatical, that is, cannot be drawn from conceptions, inasmuch as it
  5595. concerns a synthetical proposition a priori, and as philosophers never
  5596. reflected that such propositions are valid only in relation to possible
  5597. experience, and therefore cannot be proved except by means of a
  5598. deduction of the possibility of experience, it is no wonder that while
  5599. it has served as the foundation of all experience (for we feel the need
  5600. of it in empirical cognition), it has never been supported by proof.
  5601. A philosopher was asked: "What is the weight of smoke?" He answered:
  5602. "Subtract from the weight of the burnt wood the weight of the remaining
  5603. ashes, and you will have the weight of the smoke." Thus he presumed it
  5604. to be incontrovertible that even in fire the matter (substance) does not
  5605. perish, but that only the form of it undergoes a change. In like manner
  5606. was the saying: "From nothing comes nothing," only another inference
  5607. from the principle or permanence, or rather of the ever-abiding
  5608. existence of the true subject in phenomena. For if that in the
  5609. phenomenon which we call substance is to be the proper substratum of all
  5610. determination of time, it follows that all existence in past as well as
  5611. in future time, must be determinable by means of it alone. Hence we are
  5612. entitled to apply the term substance to a phenomenon, only because we
  5613. suppose its existence in all time, a notion which the word permanence
  5614. does not fully express, as it seems rather to be referable to future
  5615. time. However, the internal necessity perpetually to be, is inseparably
  5616. connected with the necessity always to have been, and so the expression
  5617. may stand as it is. "Gigni de nihilo nihil; in nihilum nil posse
  5618. reverti,"* are two propositions which the ancients never parted, and
  5619. which people nowadays sometimes mistakenly disjoin, because they imagine
  5620. that the propositions apply to objects as things in themselves, and that
  5621. the former might be inimical to the dependence (even in respect of its
  5622. substance also) of the world upon a supreme cause. But this apprehension
  5623. is entirely needless, for the question in this case is only of phenomena
  5624. in the sphere of experience, the unity of which never could be possible,
  5625. if we admitted the possibility that new things (in respect of their
  5626. substance) should arise. For in that case, we should lose altogether
  5627. that which alone can represent the unity of time, to wit, the identity
  5628. of the substratum, as that through which alone all change possesses
  5629. complete and thorough unity. This permanence is, however, nothing but
  5630. the manner in which we represent to ourselves the existence of things in
  5631. the phenomenal world.
  5632. [*Footnote: Persius, Satirae, iii.83-84.]
  5633. The determinations of a substance, which are only particular modes of
  5634. its existence, are called accidents. They are always real, because they
  5635. concern the existence of substance (negations are only determinations,
  5636. which express the non-existence of something in the substance). Now,
  5637. if to this real in the substance we ascribe a particular existence (for
  5638. example, to motion as an accident of matter), this existence is called
  5639. inherence, in contradistinction to the existence of substance, which we
  5640. call subsistence. But hence arise many misconceptions, and it would be a
  5641. more accurate and just mode of expression to designate the accident
  5642. only as the mode in which the existence of a substance is positively
  5643. determined. Meanwhile, by reason of the conditions of the logical
  5644. exercise of our understanding, it is impossible to avoid separating,
  5645. as it were, that which in the existence of a substance is subject to
  5646. change, whilst the substance remains, and regarding it in relation to
  5647. that which is properly permanent and radical. On this account, this
  5648. category of substance stands under the title of relation, rather because
  5649. it is the condition thereof than because it contains in itself any
  5650. relation.
  5651. Now, upon this notion of permanence rests the proper notion of the
  5652. conception change. Origin and extinction are not changes of that which
  5653. originates or becomes extinct. Change is but a mode of existence, which
  5654. follows on another mode of existence of the same object; hence all that
  5655. changes is permanent, and only the condition thereof changes. Now since
  5656. this mutation affects only determinations, which can have a beginning
  5657. or an end, we may say, employing an expression which seems somewhat
  5658. paradoxical: "Only the permanent (substance) is subject to change; the
  5659. mutable suffers no change, but rather alternation, that is, when certain
  5660. determinations cease, others begin."
  5661. Change, when, cannot be perceived by us except in substances, and origin
  5662. or extinction in an absolute sense, that does not concern merely a
  5663. determination of the permanent, cannot be a possible perception, for
  5664. it is this very notion of the permanent which renders possible the
  5665. representation of a transition from one state into another, and from
  5666. non-being to being, which, consequently, can be empirically cognized
  5667. only as alternating determinations of that which is permanent. Grant
  5668. that a thing absolutely begins to be; we must then have a point of time
  5669. in which it was not. But how and by what can we fix and determine
  5670. this point of time, unless by that which already exists? For a void
  5671. time--preceding--is not an object of perception; but if we connect this
  5672. beginning with objects which existed previously, and which continue to
  5673. exist till the object in question in question begins to be, then the
  5674. latter can only be a determination of the former as the permanent. The
  5675. same holds good of the notion of extinction, for this presupposes the
  5676. empirical representation of a time, in which a phenomenon no longer
  5677. exists.
  5678. Substances (in the world of phenomena) are the substratum of all
  5679. determinations of time. The beginning of some, and the ceasing to be of
  5680. other substances, would utterly do away with the only condition of the
  5681. empirical unity of time; and in that case phenomena would relate to two
  5682. different times, in which, side by side, existence would pass; which is
  5683. absurd. For there is only one time in which all different times must be
  5684. placed, not as coexistent, but as successive.
  5685. Accordingly, permanence is a necessary condition under which alone
  5686. phenomena, as things or objects, are determinable in a possible
  5687. experience. But as regards the empirical criterion of this necessary
  5688. permanence, and with it of the substantiality of phenomena, we shall
  5689. find sufficient opportunity to speak in the sequel.
  5690. B. SECOND ANALOGY.
  5691. Principle of the Succession of Time According to the Law of Causality.
  5692. All changes take place according to the law of the connection of Cause
  5693. and Effect.
  5694. PROOF.
  5695. (That all phenomena in the succession of time are only changes, that
  5696. is, a successive being and non-being of the determinations of substance,
  5697. which is permanent; consequently that a being of substance itself which
  5698. follows on the non-being thereof, or a non-being of substance which
  5699. follows on the being thereof, in other words, that the origin or
  5700. extinction of substance itself, is impossible--all this has been fully
  5701. established in treating of the foregoing principle. This principle
  5702. might have been expressed as follows: "All alteration (succession) of
  5703. phenomena is merely change"; for the changes of substance are not origin
  5704. or extinction, because the conception of change presupposes the same
  5705. subject as existing with two opposite determinations, and consequently
  5706. as permanent. After this premonition, we shall proceed to the proof.)
  5707. I perceive that phenomena succeed one another, that is to say, a state
  5708. of things exists at one time, the opposite of which existed in a former
  5709. state. In this case, then, I really connect together two perceptions in
  5710. time. Now connection is not an operation of mere sense and intuition,
  5711. but is the product of a synthetical faculty of imagination, which
  5712. determines the internal sense in respect of a relation of time. But
  5713. imagination can connect these two states in two ways, so that either the
  5714. one or the other may antecede in time; for time in itself cannot be an
  5715. object of perception, and what in an object precedes and what follows
  5716. cannot be empirically determined in relation to it. I am only conscious,
  5717. then, that my imagination places one state before and the other after;
  5718. not that the one state antecedes the other in the object. In other
  5719. words, the objective relation of the successive phenomena remains
  5720. quite undetermined by means of mere perception. Now in order that this
  5721. relation may be cognized as determined, the relation between the two
  5722. states must be so cogitated that it is thereby determined as necessary,
  5723. which of them must be placed before and which after, and not conversely.
  5724. But the conception which carries with it a necessity of synthetical
  5725. unity, can be none other than a pure conception of the understanding
  5726. which does not lie in mere perception; and in this case it is the
  5727. conception of "the relation of cause and effect," the former of which
  5728. determines the latter in time, as its necessary consequence, and not as
  5729. something which might possibly antecede (or which might in some cases
  5730. not be perceived to follow). It follows that it is only because we
  5731. subject the sequence of phenomena, and consequently all change, to the
  5732. law of causality, that experience itself, that is, empirical cognition
  5733. of phenomena, becomes possible; and consequently, that phenomena
  5734. themselves, as objects of experience, are possible only by virtue of
  5735. this law.
  5736. Our apprehension of the manifold of phenomena is always successive. The
  5737. representations of parts succeed one another. Whether they succeed one
  5738. another in the object also, is a second point for reflection, which
  5739. was not contained in the former. Now we may certainly give the name of
  5740. object to everything, even to every representation, so far as we are
  5741. conscious thereof; but what this word may mean in the case of phenomena,
  5742. not merely in so far as they (as representations) are objects, but only
  5743. in so far as they indicate an object, is a question requiring deeper
  5744. consideration. In so far as they, regarded merely as representations,
  5745. are at the same time objects of consciousness, they are not to be
  5746. distinguished from apprehension, that is, reception into the synthesis
  5747. of imagination, and we must therefore say: "The manifold of phenomena is
  5748. always produced successively in the mind." If phenomena were things in
  5749. themselves, no man would be able to conjecture from the succession of
  5750. our representations how this manifold is connected in the object; for
  5751. we have to do only with our representations. How things may be in
  5752. themselves, without regard to the representations through which they
  5753. affect us, is utterly beyond the sphere of our cognition. Now although
  5754. phenomena are not things in themselves, and are nevertheless the only
  5755. thing given to us to be cognized, it is my duty to show what sort of
  5756. connection in time belongs to the manifold in phenomena themselves,
  5757. while the representation of this manifold in apprehension is always
  5758. successive. For example, the apprehension of the manifold in the
  5759. phenomenon of a house which stands before me, is successive. Now
  5760. comes the question whether the manifold of this house is in itself
  5761. successive--which no one will be at all willing to grant. But, so
  5762. soon as I raise my conception of an object to the transcendental
  5763. signification thereof, I find that the house is not a thing in itself,
  5764. but only a phenomenon, that is, a representation, the transcendental
  5765. object of which remains utterly unknown. What then am I to understand
  5766. by the question: "How can the manifold be connected in the phenomenon
  5767. itself--not considered as a thing in itself, but merely as a
  5768. phenomenon?" Here that which lies in my successive apprehension is
  5769. regarded as representation, whilst the phenomenon which is given
  5770. me, notwithstanding that it is nothing more than a complex of these
  5771. representations, is regarded as the object thereof, with which my
  5772. conception, drawn from the representations of apprehension, must
  5773. harmonize. It is very soon seen that, as accordance of the cognition
  5774. with its object constitutes truth, the question now before us can
  5775. only relate to the formal conditions of empirical truth; and that the
  5776. phenomenon, in opposition to the representations of apprehension, can
  5777. only be distinguished therefrom as the object of them, if it is subject
  5778. to a rule which distinguishes it from every other apprehension, and
  5779. which renders necessary a mode of connection of the manifold. That in
  5780. the phenomenon which contains the condition of this necessary rule of
  5781. apprehension, is the object.
  5782. Let us now proceed to our task. That something happens, that is to say,
  5783. that something or some state exists which before was not, cannot be
  5784. empirically perceived, unless a phenomenon precedes, which does not
  5785. contain in itself this state. For a reality which should follow upon
  5786. a void time, in other words, a beginning, which no state of things
  5787. precedes, can just as little be apprehended as the void time itself.
  5788. Every apprehension of an event is therefore a perception which follows
  5789. upon another perception. But as this is the case with all synthesis
  5790. of apprehension, as I have shown above in the example of a house, my
  5791. apprehension of an event is not yet sufficiently distinguished from
  5792. other apprehensions. But I remark also that if in a phenomenon which
  5793. contains an occurrence, I call the antecedent state of my perception,
  5794. A, and the following state, B, the perception B can only follow A in
  5795. apprehension, and the perception A cannot follow B, but only precede
  5796. it. For example, I see a ship float down the stream of a river. My
  5797. perception of its place lower down follows upon my perception of its
  5798. place higher up the course of the river, and it is impossible that,
  5799. in the apprehension of this phenomenon, the vessel should be perceived
  5800. first below and afterwards higher up the stream. Here, therefore, the
  5801. order in the sequence of perceptions in apprehension is determined;
  5802. and by this order apprehension is regulated. In the former example, my
  5803. perceptions in the apprehension of a house might begin at the roof and
  5804. end at the foundation, or vice versa; or I might apprehend the manifold
  5805. in this empirical intuition, by going from left to right, and from right
  5806. to left. Accordingly, in the series of these perceptions, there was no
  5807. determined order, which necessitated my beginning at a certain point, in
  5808. order empirically to connect the manifold. But this rule is always to be
  5809. met with in the perception of that which happens, and it makes the order
  5810. of the successive perceptions in the apprehension of such a phenomenon
  5811. necessary.
  5812. I must, therefore, in the present case, deduce the subjective sequence
  5813. of apprehension from the objective sequence of phenomena, for
  5814. otherwise the former is quite undetermined, and one phenomenon is not
  5815. distinguishable from another. The former alone proves nothing as to the
  5816. connection of the manifold in an object, for it is quite arbitrary.
  5817. The latter must consist in the order of the manifold in a phenomenon,
  5818. according to which order the apprehension of one thing (that which
  5819. happens) follows that of another thing (which precedes), in conformity
  5820. with a rule. In this way alone can I be authorized to say of the
  5821. phenomenon itself, and not merely of my own apprehension, that a certain
  5822. order or sequence is to be found therein. That is, in other words, I
  5823. cannot arrange my apprehension otherwise than in this order.
  5824. In conformity with this rule, then, it is necessary that in that which
  5825. antecedes an event there be found the condition of a rule, according to
  5826. which in this event follows always and necessarily; but I cannot reverse
  5827. this and go back from the event, and determine (by apprehension) that
  5828. which antecedes it. For no phenomenon goes back from the succeeding
  5829. point of time to the preceding point, although it does certainly relate
  5830. to a preceding point of time; from a given time, on the other hand,
  5831. there is always a necessary progression to the determined succeeding
  5832. time. Therefore, because there certainly is something that follows, I
  5833. must of necessity connect it with something else, which antecedes, and
  5834. upon which it follows, in conformity with a rule, that is necessarily,
  5835. so that the event, as conditioned, affords certain indication of a
  5836. condition, and this condition determines the event.
  5837. Let us suppose that nothing precedes an event, upon which this event
  5838. must follow in conformity with a rule. All sequence of perception
  5839. would then exist only in apprehension, that is to say, would be merely
  5840. subjective, and it could not thereby be objectively determined what
  5841. thing ought to precede, and what ought to follow in perception. In such
  5842. a case, we should have nothing but a play of representations, which
  5843. would possess no application to any object. That is to say, it would
  5844. not be possible through perception to distinguish one phenomenon from
  5845. another, as regards relations of time; because the succession in the act
  5846. of apprehension would always be of the same sort, and therefore there
  5847. would be nothing in the phenomenon to determine the succession, and to
  5848. render a certain sequence objectively necessary. And, in this case, I
  5849. cannot say that two states in a phenomenon follow one upon the other,
  5850. but only that one apprehension follows upon another. But this is merely
  5851. subjective, and does not determine an object, and consequently cannot be
  5852. held to be cognition of an object--not even in the phenomenal world.
  5853. Accordingly, when we know in experience that something happens, we
  5854. always presuppose that something precedes, whereupon it follows in
  5855. conformity with a rule. For otherwise I could not say of the object that
  5856. it follows; because the mere succession in my apprehension, if it be
  5857. not determined by a rule in relation to something preceding, does not
  5858. authorize succession in the object. Only, therefore, in reference to
  5859. a rule, according to which phenomena are determined in their sequence,
  5860. that is, as they happen, by the preceding state, can I make my
  5861. subjective synthesis (of apprehension) objective, and it is only under
  5862. this presupposition that even the experience of an event is possible.
  5863. No doubt it appears as if this were in thorough contradiction to all
  5864. the notions which people have hitherto entertained in regard to the
  5865. procedure of the human understanding. According to these opinions, it
  5866. is by means of the perception and comparison of similar consequences
  5867. following upon certain antecedent phenomena that the understanding is
  5868. led to the discovery of a rule, according to which certain events always
  5869. follow certain phenomena, and it is only by this process that we attain
  5870. to the conception of cause. Upon such a basis, it is clear that this
  5871. conception must be merely empirical, and the rule which it furnishes
  5872. us with--"Everything that happens must have a cause"--would be just as
  5873. contingent as experience itself. The universality and necessity of the
  5874. rule or law would be perfectly spurious attributes of it. Indeed, it
  5875. could not possess universal validity, inasmuch as it would not in this
  5876. case be a priori, but founded on deduction. But the same is the case
  5877. with this law as with other pure a priori representations (e.g., space
  5878. and time), which we can draw in perfect clearness and completeness from
  5879. experience, only because we had already placed them therein, and by that
  5880. means, and by that alone, had rendered experience possible. Indeed,
  5881. the logical clearness of this representation of a rule, determining
  5882. the series of events, is possible only when we have made use thereof in
  5883. experience. Nevertheless, the recognition of this rule, as a condition
  5884. of the synthetical unity of phenomena in time, was the ground of
  5885. experience itself and consequently preceded it a priori.
  5886. It is now our duty to show by an example that we never, even in
  5887. experience, attribute to an object the notion of succession or effect
  5888. (of an event--that is, the happening of something that did not
  5889. exist before), and distinguish it from the subjective succession of
  5890. apprehension, unless when a rule lies at the foundation, which compels
  5891. us to observe this order of perception in preference to any other, and
  5892. that, indeed, it is this necessity which first renders possible the
  5893. representation of a succession in the object.
  5894. We have representations within us, of which also we can be conscious.
  5895. But, however widely extended, however accurate and thoroughgoing this
  5896. consciousness may be, these representations are still nothing more than
  5897. representations, that is, internal determinations of the mind in this or
  5898. that relation of time. Now how happens it that to these representations
  5899. we should set an object, or that, in addition to their subjective
  5900. reality, as modifications, we should still further attribute to them
  5901. a certain unknown objective reality? It is clear that objective
  5902. significancy cannot consist in a relation to another representation
  5903. (of that which we desire to term object), for in that case the question
  5904. again arises: "How does this other representation go out of itself, and
  5905. obtain objective significancy over and above the subjective, which
  5906. is proper to it, as a determination of a state of mind?" If we try to
  5907. discover what sort of new property the relation to an object gives to
  5908. our subjective representations, and what new importance they thereby
  5909. receive, we shall find that this relation has no other effect than
  5910. that of rendering necessary the connection of our representations in a
  5911. certain manner, and of subjecting them to a rule; and that conversely,
  5912. it is only because a certain order is necessary in the relations of time
  5913. of our representations, that objective significancy is ascribed to them.
  5914. In the synthesis of phenomena, the manifold of our representations is
  5915. always successive. Now hereby is not represented an object, for by means
  5916. of this succession, which is common to all apprehension, no one thing is
  5917. distinguished from another. But so soon as I perceive or assume that in
  5918. this succession there is a relation to a state antecedent, from which
  5919. the representation follows in accordance with a rule, so soon do I
  5920. represent something as an event, or as a thing that happens; in other
  5921. words, I cognize an object to which I must assign a certain determinate
  5922. position in time, which cannot be altered, because of the preceding
  5923. state in the object. When, therefore, I perceive that something happens,
  5924. there is contained in this representation, in the first place, the fact,
  5925. that something antecedes; because, it is only in relation to this that
  5926. the phenomenon obtains its proper relation of time, in other words,
  5927. exists after an antecedent time, in which it did not exist. But it can
  5928. receive its determined place in time only by the presupposition
  5929. that something existed in the foregoing state, upon which it follows
  5930. inevitably and always, that is, in conformity with a rule. From all this
  5931. it is evident that, in the first place, I cannot reverse the order
  5932. of succession, and make that which happens precede that upon which
  5933. it follows; and that, in the second place, if the antecedent state be
  5934. posited, a certain determinate event inevitably and necessarily
  5935. follows. Hence it follows that there exists a certain order in our
  5936. representations, whereby the present gives a sure indication of some
  5937. previously existing state, as a correlate, though still undetermined, of
  5938. the existing event which is given--a correlate which itself relates to
  5939. the event as its consequence, conditions it, and connects it necessarily
  5940. with itself in the series of time.
  5941. If then it be admitted as a necessary law of sensibility, and
  5942. consequently a formal condition of all perception, that the preceding
  5943. necessarily determines the succeeding time (inasmuch as I cannot arrive
  5944. at the succeeding except through the preceding), it must likewise be an
  5945. indispensable law of empirical representation of the series of time
  5946. that the phenomena of the past determine all phenomena in the succeeding
  5947. time, and that the latter, as events, cannot take place, except in so
  5948. far as the former determine their existence in time, that is to say,
  5949. establish it according to a rule. For it is of course only in phenomena
  5950. that we can empirically cognize this continuity in the connection of
  5951. times.
  5952. For all experience and for the possibility of experience, understanding
  5953. is indispensable, and the first step which it takes in this sphere is
  5954. not to render the representation of objects clear, but to render the
  5955. representation of an object in general, possible. It does this by
  5956. applying the order of time to phenomena, and their existence. In other
  5957. words, it assigns to each phenomenon, as a consequence, a place in
  5958. relation to preceding phenomena, determined a priori in time, without
  5959. which it could not harmonize with time itself, which determines a place
  5960. a priori to all its parts. This determination of place cannot be derived
  5961. from the relation of phenomena to absolute time (for it is not an
  5962. object of perception); but, on the contrary, phenomena must reciprocally
  5963. determine the places in time of one another, and render these necessary
  5964. in the order of time. In other words, whatever follows or happens, must
  5965. follow in conformity with a universal rule upon that which was contained
  5966. in the foregoing state. Hence arises a series of phenomena, which, by
  5967. means of the understanding, produces and renders necessary exactly
  5968. the same order and continuous connection in the series of our possible
  5969. perceptions, as is found a priori in the form of internal intuition
  5970. (time), in which all our perceptions must have place.
  5971. That something happens, then, is a perception which belongs to a
  5972. possible experience, which becomes real only because I look upon the
  5973. phenomenon as determined in regard to its place in time, consequently as
  5974. an object, which can always be found by means of a rule in the connected
  5975. series of my perceptions. But this rule of the determination of a thing
  5976. according to succession in time is as follows: "In what precedes may be
  5977. found the condition, under which an event always (that is, necessarily)
  5978. follows." From all this it is obvious that the principle of cause and
  5979. effect is the principle of possible experience, that is, of objective
  5980. cognition of phenomena, in regard to their relations in the succession
  5981. of time.
  5982. The proof of this fundamental proposition rests entirely on the
  5983. following momenta of argument. To all empirical cognition belongs the
  5984. synthesis of the manifold by the imagination, a synthesis which is
  5985. always successive, that is, in which the representations therein always
  5986. follow one another. But the order of succession in imagination is not
  5987. determined, and the series of successive representations may be taken
  5988. retrogressively as well as progressively. But if this synthesis is a
  5989. synthesis of apprehension (of the manifold of a given phenomenon), then
  5990. the order is determined in the object, or to speak more accurately,
  5991. there is therein an order of successive synthesis which determines an
  5992. object, and according to which something necessarily precedes, and
  5993. when this is posited, something else necessarily follows. If, then,
  5994. my perception is to contain the cognition of an event, that is, of
  5995. something which really happens, it must be an empirical judgement,
  5996. wherein we think that the succession is determined; that is, it
  5997. presupposes another phenomenon, upon which this event follows
  5998. necessarily, or in conformity with a rule. If, on the contrary, when I
  5999. posited the antecedent, the event did not necessarily follow, I should
  6000. be obliged to consider it merely as a subjective play of my imagination,
  6001. and if in this I represented to myself anything as objective, I must
  6002. look upon it as a mere dream. Thus, the relation of phenomena (as
  6003. possible perceptions), according to which that which happens is, as
  6004. to its existence, necessarily determined in time by something which
  6005. antecedes, in conformity with a rule--in other words, the relation of
  6006. cause and effect--is the condition of the objective validity of
  6007. our empirical judgements in regard to the sequence of perceptions,
  6008. consequently of their empirical truth, and therefore of experience. The
  6009. principle of the relation of causality in the succession of phenomena is
  6010. therefore valid for all objects of experience, because it is itself the
  6011. ground of the possibility of experience.
  6012. Here, however, a difficulty arises, which must be resolved. The
  6013. principle of the connection of causality among phenomena is limited in
  6014. our formula to the succession thereof, although in practice we find that
  6015. the principle applies also when the phenomena exist together in the same
  6016. time, and that cause and effect may be simultaneous. For example, there
  6017. is heat in a room, which does not exist in the open air. I look about
  6018. for the cause, and find it to be the fire, Now the fire as the cause is
  6019. simultaneous with its effect, the heat of the room. In this case, then,
  6020. there is no succession as regards time, between cause and effect, but
  6021. they are simultaneous; and still the law holds good. The greater part of
  6022. operating causes in nature are simultaneous with their effects, and
  6023. the succession in time of the latter is produced only because the cause
  6024. cannot achieve the total of its effect in one moment. But at the
  6025. moment when the effect first arises, it is always simultaneous with the
  6026. causality of its cause, because, if the cause had but a moment before
  6027. ceased to be, the effect could not have arisen. Here it must be
  6028. specially remembered that we must consider the order of time and not the
  6029. lapse thereof. The relation remains, even though no time has elapsed.
  6030. The time between the causality of the cause and its immediate effect may
  6031. entirely vanish, and the cause and effect be thus simultaneous, but the
  6032. relation of the one to the other remains always determinable according
  6033. to time. If, for example, I consider a leaden ball, which lies upon a
  6034. cushion and makes a hollow in it, as a cause, then it is simultaneous
  6035. with the effect. But I distinguish the two through the relation of time
  6036. of the dynamical connection of both. For if I lay the ball upon the
  6037. cushion, then the hollow follows upon the before smooth surface; but
  6038. supposing the cushion has, from some cause or another, a hollow, there
  6039. does not thereupon follow a leaden ball.
  6040. Thus, the law of succession of time is in all instances the only
  6041. empirical criterion of effect in relation to the causality of the
  6042. antecedent cause. The glass is the cause of the rising of the
  6043. water above its horizontal surface, although the two phenomena are
  6044. contemporaneous. For, as soon as I draw some water with the glass from
  6045. a larger vessel, an effect follows thereupon, namely, the change of the
  6046. horizontal state which the water had in the large vessel into a concave,
  6047. which it assumes in the glass.
  6048. This conception of causality leads us to the conception of action; that
  6049. of action, to the conception of force; and through it, to the conception
  6050. of substance. As I do not wish this critical essay, the sole purpose of
  6051. which is to treat of the sources of our synthetical cognition a priori,
  6052. to be crowded with analyses which merely explain, but do not enlarge
  6053. the sphere of our conceptions, I reserve the detailed explanation of the
  6054. above conceptions for a future system of pure reason. Such an analysis,
  6055. indeed, executed with great particularity, may already be found in
  6056. well-known works on this subject. But I cannot at present refrain from
  6057. making a few remarks on the empirical criterion of a substance, in so
  6058. far as it seems to be more evident and more easily recognized through
  6059. the conception of action than through that of the permanence of a
  6060. phenomenon.
  6061. Where action (consequently activity and force) exists, substance also
  6062. must exist, and in it alone must be sought the seat of that fruitful
  6063. source of phenomena. Very well. But if we are called upon to explain
  6064. what we mean by substance, and wish to avoid the vice of reasoning in
  6065. a circle, the answer is by no means so easy. How shall we conclude
  6066. immediately from the action to the permanence of that which acts, this
  6067. being nevertheless an essential and peculiar criterion of substance
  6068. (phenomenon)? But after what has been said above, the solution of
  6069. this question becomes easy enough, although by the common mode
  6070. of procedure--merely analysing our conceptions--it would be quite
  6071. impossible. The conception of action indicates the relation of the
  6072. subject of causality to the effect. Now because all effect consists
  6073. in that which happens, therefore in the changeable, the last subject
  6074. thereof is the permanent, as the substratum of all that changes, that
  6075. is, substance. For according to the principle of causality, actions are
  6076. always the first ground of all change in phenomena and, consequently,
  6077. cannot be a property of a subject which itself changes, because if this
  6078. were the case, other actions and another subject would be necessary to
  6079. determine this change. From all this it results that action alone, as
  6080. an empirical criterion, is a sufficient proof of the presence of
  6081. substantiality, without any necessity on my part of endeavouring to
  6082. discover the permanence of substance by a comparison. Besides, by this
  6083. mode of induction we could not attain to the completeness which the
  6084. magnitude and strict universality of the conception requires. For that
  6085. the primary subject of the causality of all arising and passing away,
  6086. all origin and extinction, cannot itself (in the sphere of phenomena)
  6087. arise and pass away, is a sound and safe conclusion, a conclusion which
  6088. leads us to the conception of empirical necessity and permanence
  6089. in existence, and consequently to the conception of a substance as
  6090. phenomenon.
  6091. When something happens, the mere fact of the occurrence, without
  6092. regard to that which occurs, is an object requiring investigation.
  6093. The transition from the non-being of a state into the existence of it,
  6094. supposing that this state contains no quality which previously existed
  6095. in the phenomenon, is a fact of itself demanding inquiry. Such an event,
  6096. as has been shown in No. A, does not concern substance (for substance
  6097. does not thus originate), but its condition or state. It is therefore
  6098. only change, and not origin from nothing. If this origin be regarded as
  6099. the effect of a foreign cause, it is termed creation, which cannot be
  6100. admitted as an event among phenomena, because the very possibility of
  6101. it would annihilate the unity of experience. If, however, I regard all
  6102. things not as phenomena, but as things in themselves and objects of
  6103. understanding alone, they, although substances, may be considered as
  6104. dependent, in respect of their existence, on a foreign cause. But this
  6105. would require a very different meaning in the words, a meaning which
  6106. could not apply to phenomena as objects of possible experience.
  6107. How a thing can be changed, how it is possible that upon one state
  6108. existing in one point of time, an opposite state should follow in
  6109. another point of time--of this we have not the smallest conception a
  6110. priori. There is requisite for this the knowledge of real powers, which
  6111. can only be given empirically; for example, knowledge of moving forces,
  6112. or, in other words, of certain successive phenomena (as movements) which
  6113. indicate the presence of such forces. But the form of every change,
  6114. the condition under which alone it can take place as the coming into
  6115. existence of another state (be the content of the change, that is, the
  6116. state which is changed, what it may), and consequently the succession of
  6117. the states themselves can very well be considered a priori, in relation
  6118. to the law of causality and the conditions of time.*
  6119. [*Footnote: It must be remarked that I do not speak of the change of
  6120. certain relations, but of the change of the state. Thus, when a body
  6121. moves in a uniform manner, it does not change its state (of motion); but
  6122. only when all motion increases or decreases.]
  6123. When a substance passes from one state, a, into another state, b,
  6124. the point of time in which the latter exists is different from, and
  6125. subsequent to that in which the former existed. In like manner, the
  6126. second state, as reality (in the phenomenon), differs from the first, in
  6127. which the reality of the second did not exist, as b from zero. That is
  6128. to say, if the state, b, differs from the state, a, only in respect to
  6129. quantity, the change is a coming into existence of b -a, which in the
  6130. former state did not exist, and in relation to which that state is = O.
  6131. Now the question arises how a thing passes from one state = a, into
  6132. another state = b. Between two moments there is always a certain time,
  6133. and between two states existing in these moments there is always a
  6134. difference having a certain quantity (for all parts of phenomena are in
  6135. their turn quantities). Consequently, every transition from one state
  6136. into another is always effected in a time contained between two moments,
  6137. of which the first determines the state which leaves, and the second
  6138. determines the state into the thing passes. The thing leaves, and the
  6139. second determines the state into which the thing Both moments, then, are
  6140. limitations of the time of a change, consequently of the intermediate
  6141. state between both, and as such they belong to the total of the change.
  6142. Now every change has a cause, which evidences its causality in the whole
  6143. time during which the charge takes place. The cause, therefore, does not
  6144. produce the change all at once or in one moment, but in a time, so that,
  6145. as the time gradually increases from the commencing instant, a, to its
  6146. completion at b, in like manner also, the quantity of the reality (b -
  6147. a) is generated through the lesser degrees which are contained between
  6148. the first and last. All change is therefore possible only through a
  6149. continuous action of the causality, which, in so far as it is uniform,
  6150. we call a momentum. The change does not consist of these momenta, but is
  6151. generated or produced by them as their effect.
  6152. Such is the law of the continuity of all change, the ground of which is
  6153. that neither time itself nor any phenomenon in time consists of parts
  6154. which are the smallest possible, but that, notwithstanding, the state
  6155. of a thing passes in the process of a change through all these parts, as
  6156. elements, to its second state. There is no smallest degree of reality
  6157. in a phenomenon, just as there is no smallest degree in the quantity of
  6158. time; and so the new state of reality grows up out of the former state,
  6159. through all the infinite degrees thereof, the differences of which one
  6160. from another, taken all together, are less than the difference between o
  6161. and a.
  6162. It is not our business to inquire here into the utility of this
  6163. principle in the investigation of nature. But how such a proposition,
  6164. which appears so greatly to extend our knowledge of nature, is possible
  6165. completely a priori, is indeed a question which deserves investigation,
  6166. although the first view seems to demonstrate the truth and reality of
  6167. the principle, and the question, how it is possible, may be considered
  6168. superfluous. For there are so many groundless pretensions to the
  6169. enlargement of our knowledge by pure reason that we must take it as a
  6170. general rule to be mistrustful of all such, and without a thoroughgoing
  6171. and radical deduction, to believe nothing of the sort even on the
  6172. clearest dogmatical evidence.
  6173. Every addition to our empirical knowledge, and every advance made in
  6174. the exercise of our perception, is nothing more than an extension of the
  6175. determination of the internal sense, that is to say, a progression
  6176. in time, be objects themselves what they may, phenomena, or pure
  6177. intuitions. This progression in time determines everything, and is
  6178. itself determined by nothing else. That is to say, the parts of the
  6179. progression exist only in time, and by means of the synthesis thereof,
  6180. and are not given antecedently to it. For this reason, every transition
  6181. in perception to anything which follows upon another in time, is a
  6182. determination of time by means of the production of this perception.
  6183. And as this determination of time is, always and in all its parts, a
  6184. quantity, the perception produced is to be considered as a quantity
  6185. which proceeds through all its degrees--no one of which is the smallest
  6186. possible--from zero up to its determined degree. From this we perceive
  6187. the possibility of cognizing a priori a law of changes--a law,
  6188. however, which concerns their form merely. We merely anticipate our own
  6189. apprehension, the formal condition of which, inasmuch as it is itself to
  6190. be found in the mind antecedently to all given phenomena, must certainly
  6191. be capable of being cognized a priori.
  6192. Thus, as time contains the sensuous condition a priori of the
  6193. possibility of a continuous progression of that which exists to
  6194. that which follows it, the understanding, by virtue of the unity of
  6195. apperception, contains the condition a priori of the possibility of a
  6196. continuous determination of the position in time of all phenomena, and
  6197. this by means of the series of causes and effects, the former of which
  6198. necessitate the sequence of the latter, and thereby render universally
  6199. and for all time, and by consequence, objectively, valid the empirical
  6200. cognition of the relations of time.
  6201. C. THIRD ANALOGY.
  6202. Principle of Coexistence, According to the Law of Reciprocity or
  6203. Community.
  6204. All substances, in so far as they can be perceived in space at the same
  6205. time, exist in a state of complete reciprocity of action.
  6206. PROOF.
  6207. Things are coexistent, when in empirical intuition the perception of the
  6208. one can follow upon the perception of the other, and vice versa--which
  6209. cannot occur in the succession of phenomena, as we have shown in the
  6210. explanation of the second principle. Thus I can perceive the moon and
  6211. then the earth, or conversely, first the earth and then the moon; and
  6212. for the reason that my perceptions of these objects can reciprocally
  6213. follow each other, I say, they exist contemporaneously. Now coexistence
  6214. is the existence of the manifold in the same time. But time itself is
  6215. not an object of perception; and therefore we cannot conclude from the
  6216. fact that things are placed in the same time, the other fact, that
  6217. the perception of these things can follow each other reciprocally. The
  6218. synthesis of the imagination in apprehension would only present to us
  6219. each of these perceptions as present in the subject when the other is
  6220. not present, and contrariwise; but would not show that the objects are
  6221. coexistent, that is to say, that, if the one exists, the other also
  6222. exists in the same time, and that this is necessarily so, in order that
  6223. the perceptions may be capable of following each other reciprocally.
  6224. It follows that a conception of the understanding or category of the
  6225. reciprocal sequence of the determinations of phenomena (existing, as
  6226. they do, apart from each other, and yet contemporaneously), is requisite
  6227. to justify us in saying that the reciprocal succession of perceptions
  6228. has its foundation in the object, and to enable us to represent
  6229. coexistence as objective. But that relation of substances in which
  6230. the one contains determinations the ground of which is in the other
  6231. substance, is the relation of influence. And, when this influence is
  6232. reciprocal, it is the relation of community or reciprocity. Consequently
  6233. the coexistence of substances in space cannot be cognized in experience
  6234. otherwise than under the precondition of their reciprocal action. This
  6235. is therefore the condition of the possibility of things themselves as
  6236. objects of experience.
  6237. Things are coexistent, in so far as they exist in one and the same time.
  6238. But how can we know that they exist in one and the same time? Only
  6239. by observing that the order in the synthesis of apprehension of the
  6240. manifold is arbitrary and a matter of indifference, that is to say, that
  6241. it can proceed from A, through B, C, D, to E, or contrariwise from E
  6242. to A. For if they were successive in time (and in the order, let
  6243. us suppose, which begins with A), it is quite impossible for the
  6244. apprehension in perception to begin with E and go backwards to A,
  6245. inasmuch as A belongs to past time and, therefore, cannot be an object
  6246. of apprehension.
  6247. Let us assume that in a number of substances considered as phenomena
  6248. each is completely isolated, that is, that no one acts upon another.
  6249. Then I say that the coexistence of these cannot be an object of
  6250. possible perception and that the existence of one cannot, by any mode of
  6251. empirical synthesis, lead us to the existence of another. For we imagine
  6252. them in this case to be separated by a completely void space, and thus
  6253. perception, which proceeds from the one to the other in time, would
  6254. indeed determine their existence by means of a following perception, but
  6255. would be quite unable to distinguish whether the one phenomenon follows
  6256. objectively upon the first, or is coexistent with it.
  6257. Besides the mere fact of existence, then, there must be something by
  6258. means of which A determines the position of B in time and, conversely,
  6259. B the position of A; because only under this condition can substances
  6260. be empirically represented as existing contemporaneously. Now that alone
  6261. determines the position of another thing in time which is the cause of
  6262. it or of its determinations. Consequently every substance (inasmuch
  6263. as it can have succession predicated of it only in respect of its
  6264. determinations) must contain the causality of certain determinations in
  6265. another substance, and at the same time the effects of the causality of
  6266. the other in itself. That is to say, substances must stand (mediately or
  6267. immediately) in dynamical community with each other, if coexistence is
  6268. to be cognized in any possible experience. But, in regard to objects of
  6269. experience, that is absolutely necessary without which the experience of
  6270. these objects would itself be impossible. Consequently it is absolutely
  6271. necessary that all substances in the world of phenomena, in so far
  6272. as they are coexistent, stand in a relation of complete community of
  6273. reciprocal action to each other.
  6274. The word community has in our language [Footnote: German] two meanings,
  6275. and contains the two notions conveyed in the Latin communio and
  6276. commercium. We employ it in this place in the latter sense--that of a
  6277. dynamical community, without which even the community of place (communio
  6278. spatii) could not be empirically cognized. In our experiences it is easy
  6279. to observe that it is only the continuous influences in all parts of
  6280. space that can conduct our senses from one object to another; that the
  6281. light which plays between our eyes and the heavenly bodies produces a
  6282. mediating community between them and us, and thereby evidences their
  6283. coexistence with us; that we cannot empirically change our position
  6284. (perceive this change), unless the existence of matter throughout the
  6285. whole of space rendered possible the perception of the positions we
  6286. occupy; and that this perception can prove the contemporaneous existence
  6287. of these places only through their reciprocal influence, and thereby
  6288. also the coexistence of even the most remote objects--although in this
  6289. case the proof is only mediate. Without community, every perception (of
  6290. a phenomenon in space) is separated from every other and isolated, and
  6291. the chain of empirical representations, that is, of experience, must,
  6292. with the appearance of a new object, begin entirely de novo, without the
  6293. least connection with preceding representations, and without standing
  6294. towards these even in the relation of time. My intention here is by no
  6295. means to combat the notion of empty space; for it may exist where our
  6296. perceptions cannot exist, inasmuch as they cannot reach thereto, and
  6297. where, therefore, no empirical perception of coexistence takes place.
  6298. But in this case it is not an object of possible experience.
  6299. The following remarks may be useful in the way of explanation. In the
  6300. mind, all phenomena, as contents of a possible experience, must exist in
  6301. community (communio) of apperception or consciousness, and in so far as
  6302. it is requisite that objects be represented as coexistent and connected,
  6303. in so far must they reciprocally determine the position in time of each
  6304. other and thereby constitute a whole. If this subjective community is
  6305. to rest upon an objective basis, or to be applied to substances as
  6306. phenomena, the perception of one substance must render possible the
  6307. perception of another, and conversely. For otherwise succession, which
  6308. is always found in perceptions as apprehensions, would be predicated of
  6309. external objects, and their representation of their coexistence be thus
  6310. impossible. But this is a reciprocal influence, that is to say, a
  6311. real community (commercium) of substances, without which therefore the
  6312. empirical relation of coexistence would be a notion beyond the reach of
  6313. our minds. By virtue of this commercium, phenomena, in so far as
  6314. they are apart from, and nevertheless in connection with each other,
  6315. constitute a compositum reale. Such composita are possible in many
  6316. different ways. The three dynamical relations then, from which all
  6317. others spring, are those of inherence, consequence, and composition.
  6318. These, then, are the three analogies of experience. They are nothing
  6319. more than principles of the determination of the existence of phenomena
  6320. in time, according to the three modi of this determination; to wit, the
  6321. relation to time itself as a quantity (the quantity of existence, that
  6322. is, duration), the relation in time as a series or succession, finally,
  6323. the relation in time as the complex of all existence (simultaneity).
  6324. This unity of determination in regard to time is thoroughly dynamical;
  6325. that is to say, time is not considered as that in which experience
  6326. determines immediately to every existence its position; for this is
  6327. impossible, inasmuch as absolute time is not an object of perception,
  6328. by means of which phenomena can be connected with each other. On
  6329. the contrary, the rule of the understanding, through which alone
  6330. the existence of phenomena can receive synthetical unity as regards
  6331. relations of time, determines for every phenomenon its position in time,
  6332. and consequently a priori, and with validity for all and every time.
  6333. By nature, in the empirical sense of the word, we understand the
  6334. totality of phenomena connected, in respect of their existence,
  6335. according to necessary rules, that is, laws. There are therefore certain
  6336. laws (which are moreover a priori) which make nature possible; and all
  6337. empirical laws can exist only by means of experience, and by virtue of
  6338. those primitive laws through which experience itself becomes possible.
  6339. The purpose of the analogies is therefore to represent to us the unity
  6340. of nature in the connection of all phenomena under certain exponents,
  6341. the only business of which is to express the relation of time (in so far
  6342. as it contains all existence in itself) to the unity of apperception,
  6343. which can exist in synthesis only according to rules. The combined
  6344. expression of all is this: "All phenomena exist in one nature, and
  6345. must so exist, inasmuch as without this a priori unity, no unity of
  6346. experience, and consequently no determination of objects in experience,
  6347. is possible."
  6348. As regards the mode of proof which we have employed in treating of these
  6349. transcendental laws of nature, and the peculiar character of we must
  6350. make one remark, which will at the same time be important as a guide
  6351. in every other attempt to demonstrate the truth of intellectual and
  6352. likewise synthetical propositions a priori. Had we endeavoured to prove
  6353. these analogies dogmatically, that is, from conceptions; that is to say,
  6354. had we employed this method in attempting to show that everything which
  6355. exists, exists only in that which is permanent--that every thing or
  6356. event presupposes the existence of something in a preceding state,
  6357. upon which it follows in conformity with a rule--lastly, that in the
  6358. manifold, which is coexistent, the states coexist in connection with
  6359. each other according to a rule, all our labour would have been utterly
  6360. in vain. For more conceptions of things, analyse them as we may, cannot
  6361. enable us to conclude from the existence of one object to the existence
  6362. of another. What other course was left for us to pursue? This only, to
  6363. demonstrate the possibility of experience as a cognition in which
  6364. at last all objects must be capable of being presented to us, if the
  6365. representation of them is to possess any objective reality. Now in this
  6366. third, this mediating term, the essential form of which consists in
  6367. the synthetical unity of the apperception of all phenomena, we found
  6368. a priori conditions of the universal and necessary determination as
  6369. to time of all existences in the world of phenomena, without which the
  6370. empirical determination thereof as to time would itself be impossible,
  6371. and we also discovered rules of synthetical unity a priori, by means of
  6372. which we could anticipate experience. For want of this method, and from
  6373. the fancy that it was possible to discover a dogmatical proof of the
  6374. synthetical propositions which are requisite in the empirical employment
  6375. of the understanding, has it happened that a proof of the principle of
  6376. sufficient reason has been so often attempted, and always in vain.
  6377. The other two analogies nobody has ever thought of, although they have
  6378. always been silently employed by the mind,* because the guiding thread
  6379. furnished by the categories was wanting, the guide which alone can
  6380. enable us to discover every hiatus, both in the system of conceptions
  6381. and of principles.
  6382. [*Footnote: The unity of the universe, in which all phenomena to be
  6383. connected, is evidently a mere consequence of the admitted principle
  6384. of the community of all substances which are coexistent. For were
  6385. substances isolated, they could not as parts constitute a whole, and
  6386. were their connection (reciprocal action of the manifold) not necessary
  6387. from the very fact of coexistence, we could not conclude from the fact
  6388. of the latter as a merely ideal relation to the former as a real one. We
  6389. have, however, shown in its place that community is the proper ground
  6390. of the possibility of an empirical cognition of coexistence, and that
  6391. we may therefore properly reason from the latter to the former as its
  6392. condition.]
  6393. 4. THE POSTULATES OF EMPIRICAL THOUGHT.
  6394. 1. That which agrees with the formal conditions (intuition and
  6395. conception) of experience, is possible.
  6396. 2. That which coheres with the material conditions of experience
  6397. (sensation), is real.
  6398. 3. That whose coherence with the real is determined according to
  6399. universal conditions of experience is (exists) necessary.
  6400. Explanation.
  6401. The categories of modality possess this peculiarity, that they do not in
  6402. the least determine the object, or enlarge the conception to which they
  6403. are annexed as predicates, but only express its relation to the faculty
  6404. of cognition. Though my conception of a thing is in itself complete, I
  6405. am still entitled to ask whether the object of it is merely possible,
  6406. or whether it is also real, or, if the latter, whether it is also
  6407. necessary. But hereby the object itself is not more definitely
  6408. determined in thought, but the question is only in what relation it,
  6409. including all its determinations, stands to the understanding and its
  6410. employment in experience, to the empirical faculty of judgement, and to
  6411. the reason of its application to experience.
  6412. For this very reason, too, the categories of modality are nothing
  6413. more than explanations of the conceptions of possibility, reality, and
  6414. necessity, as employed in experience, and at the same time, restrictions
  6415. of all the categories to empirical use alone, not authorizing the
  6416. transcendental employment of them. For if they are to have something
  6417. more than a merely logical significance, and to be something more than
  6418. a mere analytical expression of the form of thought, and to have a
  6419. relation to things and their possibility, reality, or necessity, they
  6420. must concern possible experience and its synthetical unity, in which
  6421. alone objects of cognition can be given.
  6422. The postulate of the possibility of things requires also, that the
  6423. conception of the things agree with the formal conditions of our
  6424. experience in general. But this, that is to say, the objective form of
  6425. experience, contains all the kinds of synthesis which are requisite for
  6426. the cognition of objects. A conception which contains a synthesis
  6427. must be regarded as empty and, without reference to an object, if its
  6428. synthesis does not belong to experience--either as borrowed from it,
  6429. and in this case it is called an empirical conception, or such as is the
  6430. ground and a priori condition of experience (its form), and in this
  6431. case it is a pure conception, a conception which nevertheless belongs to
  6432. experience, inasmuch as its object can be found in this alone. For where
  6433. shall we find the criterion or character of the possibility of an object
  6434. which is cogitated by means of an a priori synthetical conception, if
  6435. not in the synthesis which constitutes the form of empirical cognition
  6436. of objects? That in such a conception no contradiction exists is indeed
  6437. a necessary logical condition, but very far from being sufficient
  6438. to establish the objective reality of the conception, that is, the
  6439. possibility of such an object as is thought in the conception. Thus, in
  6440. the conception of a figure which is contained within two straight lines,
  6441. there is no contradiction, for the conceptions of two straight lines and
  6442. of their junction contain no negation of a figure. The impossibility in
  6443. such a case does not rest upon the conception in itself, but upon the
  6444. construction of it in space, that is to say, upon the conditions of
  6445. space and its determinations. But these have themselves objective
  6446. reality, that is, they apply to possible things, because they contain a
  6447. priori the form of experience in general.
  6448. And now we shall proceed to point out the extensive utility and
  6449. influence of this postulate of possibility. When I represent to myself a
  6450. thing that is permanent, so that everything in it which changes belongs
  6451. merely to its state or condition, from such a conception alone I never
  6452. can cognize that such a thing is possible. Or, if I represent to myself
  6453. something which is so constituted that, when it is posited,
  6454. something else follows always and infallibly, my thought contains no
  6455. self-contradiction; but whether such a property as causality is to
  6456. be found in any possible thing, my thought alone affords no means
  6457. of judging. Finally, I can represent to myself different things
  6458. (substances) which are so constituted that the state or condition of one
  6459. causes a change in the state of the other, and reciprocally; but whether
  6460. such a relation is a property of things cannot be perceived from these
  6461. conceptions, which contain a merely arbitrary synthesis. Only from the
  6462. fact, therefore, that these conceptions express a priori the relations
  6463. of perceptions in every experience, do we know that they possess
  6464. objective reality, that is, transcendental truth; and that independent
  6465. of experience, though not independent of all relation to form of an
  6466. experience in general and its synthetical unity, in which alone objects
  6467. can be empirically cognized.
  6468. But when we fashion to ourselves new conceptions of substances, forces,
  6469. action, and reaction, from the material presented to us by perception,
  6470. without following the example of experience in their connection, we
  6471. create mere chimeras, of the possibility of which we cannot discover any
  6472. criterion, because we have not taken experience for our instructress,
  6473. though we have borrowed the conceptions from her. Such fictitious
  6474. conceptions derive their character of possibility not, like the
  6475. categories, a priori, as conceptions on which all experience depends,
  6476. but only, a posteriori, as conceptions given by means of experience
  6477. itself, and their possibility must either be cognized a posteriori
  6478. and empirically, or it cannot be cognized at all. A substance which is
  6479. permanently present in space, yet without filling it (like that tertium
  6480. quid between matter and the thinking subject which some have tried to
  6481. introduce into metaphysics), or a peculiar fundamental power of the mind
  6482. of intuiting the future by anticipation (instead of merely inferring
  6483. from past and present events), or, finally, a power of the mind to place
  6484. itself in community of thought with other men, however distant they may
  6485. be--these are conceptions the possibility of which has no ground to rest
  6486. upon. For they are not based upon experience and its known laws; and,
  6487. without experience, they are a merely arbitrary conjunction of thoughts,
  6488. which, though containing no internal contradiction, has no claim to
  6489. objective reality, neither, consequently, to the possibility of such an
  6490. object as is thought in these conceptions. As far as concerns reality,
  6491. it is self-evident that we cannot cogitate such a possibility in
  6492. concreto without the aid of experience; because reality is concerned
  6493. only with sensation, as the matter of experience, and not with the form
  6494. of thought, with which we can no doubt indulge in shaping fancies.
  6495. But I pass by everything which derives its possibility from reality in
  6496. experience, and I purpose treating here merely of the possibility of
  6497. things by means of a priori conceptions. I maintain, then, that the
  6498. possibility of things is not derived from such conceptions per se, but
  6499. only when considered as formal and objective conditions of an experience
  6500. in general.
  6501. It seems, indeed, as if the possibility of a triangle could be cognized
  6502. from the conception of it alone (which is certainly independent of
  6503. experience); for we can certainly give to the conception a corresponding
  6504. object completely a priori, that is to say, we can construct it. But as
  6505. a triangle is only the form of an object, it must remain a mere product
  6506. of the imagination, and the possibility of the existence of an object
  6507. corresponding to it must remain doubtful, unless we can discover some
  6508. other ground, unless we know that the figure can be cogitated under the
  6509. conditions upon which all objects of experience rest. Now, the facts
  6510. that space is a formal condition a priori of external experience,
  6511. that the formative synthesis, by which we construct a triangle in
  6512. imagination, is the very same as that we employ in the apprehension of a
  6513. phenomenon for the purpose of making an empirical conception of it, are
  6514. what alone connect the notion of the possibility of such a thing, with
  6515. the conception of it. In the same manner, the possibility of continuous
  6516. quantities, indeed of quantities in general, for the conceptions of them
  6517. are without exception synthetical, is never evident from the conceptions
  6518. in themselves, but only when they are considered as the formal
  6519. conditions of the determination of objects in experience. And where,
  6520. indeed, should we look for objects to correspond to our conceptions, if
  6521. not in experience, by which alone objects are presented to us? It is,
  6522. however, true that without antecedent experience we can cognize and
  6523. characterize the possibility of things, relatively to the formal
  6524. conditions, under which something is determined in experience as an
  6525. object, consequently, completely a priori. But still this is possible
  6526. only in relation to experience and within its limits.
  6527. The postulate concerning the cognition of the reality of things requires
  6528. perception, consequently conscious sensation, not indeed immediately,
  6529. that is, of the object itself, whose existence is to be cognized, but
  6530. still that the object have some connection with a real perception, in
  6531. accordance with the analogies of experience, which exhibit all kinds of
  6532. real connection in experience.
  6533. From the mere conception of a thing it is impossible to conclude its
  6534. existence. For, let the conception be ever so complete, and containing
  6535. a statement of all the determinations of the thing, the existence of
  6536. it has nothing to do with all this, but only with thew question whether
  6537. such a thing is given, so that the perception of it can in every case
  6538. precede the conception. For the fact that the conception of it precedes
  6539. the perception, merely indicates the possibility of its existence; it
  6540. is perception which presents matter to the conception, that is the sole
  6541. criterion of reality. Prior to the perception of the thing, however, and
  6542. therefore comparatively a priori, we are able to cognize its existence,
  6543. provided it stands in connection with some perceptions according to the
  6544. principles of the empirical conjunction of these, that is, in conformity
  6545. with the analogies of perception. For, in this case, the existence
  6546. of the supposed thing is connected with our perception in a possible
  6547. experience, and we are able, with the guidance of these analogies, to
  6548. reason in the series of possible perceptions from a thing which we do
  6549. really perceive to the thing we do not perceive. Thus, we cognize
  6550. the existence of a magnetic matter penetrating all bodies from the
  6551. perception of the attraction of the steel-filings by the magnet,
  6552. although the constitution of our organs renders an immediate perception
  6553. of this matter impossible for us. For, according to the laws of
  6554. sensibility and the connected context of our perceptions, we should
  6555. in an experience come also on an immediate empirical intuition of
  6556. this matter, if our senses were more acute--but this obtuseness has
  6557. no influence upon and cannot alter the form of possible experience in
  6558. general. Our knowledge of the existence of things reaches as far as our
  6559. perceptions, and what may be inferred from them according to empirical
  6560. laws, extend. If we do not set out from experience, or do not proceed
  6561. according to the laws of the empirical connection of phenomena, our
  6562. pretensions to discover the existence of a thing which we do not
  6563. immediately perceive are vain. Idealism, however, brings forward
  6564. powerful objections to these rules for proving existence mediately. This
  6565. is, therefore, the proper place for its refutation.
  6566. REFUTATION OF IDEALISM.
  6567. Idealism--I mean material idealism--is the theory which declares the
  6568. existence of objects in space without us to be either () doubtful
  6569. and indemonstrable, or (2) false and impossible. The first is the
  6570. problematical idealism of Descartes, who admits the undoubted certainty
  6571. of only one empirical assertion (assertio), to wit, "I am." The second
  6572. is the dogmatical idealism of Berkeley, who maintains that space,
  6573. together with all the objects of which it is the inseparable condition,
  6574. is a thing which is in itself impossible, and that consequently the
  6575. objects in space are mere products of the imagination. The dogmatical
  6576. theory of idealism is unavoidable, if we regard space as a property
  6577. of things in themselves; for in that case it is, with all to which it
  6578. serves as condition, a nonentity. But the foundation for this kind of
  6579. idealism we have already destroyed in the transcendental aesthetic.
  6580. Problematical idealism, which makes no such assertion, but only alleges
  6581. our incapacity to prove the existence of anything besides ourselves by
  6582. means of immediate experience, is a theory rational and evidencing a
  6583. thorough and philosophical mode of thinking, for it observes the rule
  6584. not to form a decisive judgement before sufficient proof be shown. The
  6585. desired proof must therefore demonstrate that we have experience of
  6586. external things, and not mere fancies. For this purpose, we must prove,
  6587. that our internal and, to Descartes, indubitable experience is itself
  6588. possible only under the previous assumption of external experience.
  6589. THEOREM.
  6590. The simple but empirically determined consciousness of my own existence
  6591. proves the existence of external objects in space.
  6592. PROOF
  6593. I am conscious of my own existence as determined in time. All
  6594. determination in regard to time presupposes the existence of something
  6595. permanent in perception. But this permanent something cannot be
  6596. something in me, for the very reason that my existence in time is itself
  6597. determined by this permanent something. It follows that the perception
  6598. of this permanent existence is possible only through a thing without
  6599. me and not through the mere representation of a thing without me.
  6600. Consequently, the determination of my existence in time is possible only
  6601. through the existence of real things external to me. Now, consciousness
  6602. in time is necessarily connected with the consciousness of the
  6603. possibility of this determination in time. Hence it follows that
  6604. consciousness in time is necessarily connected also with the existence
  6605. of things without me, inasmuch as the existence of these things is the
  6606. condition of determination in time. That is to say, the consciousness of
  6607. my own existence is at the same time an immediate consciousness of the
  6608. existence of other things without me.
  6609. Remark I. The reader will observe, that in the foregoing proof the game
  6610. which idealism plays is retorted upon itself, and with more justice.
  6611. It assumed that the only immediate experience is internal and that from
  6612. this we can only infer the existence of external things. But, as
  6613. always happens, when we reason from given effects to determined causes,
  6614. idealism has reasoned with too much haste and uncertainty, for it
  6615. is quite possible that the cause of our representations may lie in
  6616. ourselves, and that we ascribe it falsely to external things. But our
  6617. proof shows that external experience is properly immediate,* that only
  6618. by virtue of it--not, indeed, the consciousness of our own existence,
  6619. but certainly the determination of our existence in time, that is,
  6620. internal experience--is possible. It is true, that the representation
  6621. "I am," which is the expression of the consciousness which can accompany
  6622. all my thoughts, is that which immediately includes the existence of a
  6623. subject. But in this representation we cannot find any knowledge of the
  6624. subject, and therefore also no empirical knowledge, that is, experience.
  6625. For experience contains, in addition to the thought of something
  6626. existing, intuition, and in this case it must be internal intuition,
  6627. that is, time, in relation to which the subject must be determined.
  6628. But the existence of external things is absolutely requisite for this
  6629. purpose, so that it follows that internal experience is itself possible
  6630. only mediately and through external experience.
  6631. [*Footnote: The immediate consciousness of the existence of external
  6632. things is, in the preceding theorem, not presupposed, but proved, by the
  6633. possibility of this consciousness understood by us or not. The question
  6634. as to the possibility of it would stand thus: "Have we an internal
  6635. sense, but no external sense, and is our belief in external perception
  6636. a mere delusion?" But it is evident that, in order merely to fancy to
  6637. ourselves anything as external, that is, to present it to the sense in
  6638. intuition we must already possess an external sense, and must thereby
  6639. distinguish immediately the mere receptivity of an external intuition
  6640. from the spontaneity which characterizes every act of imagination. For
  6641. merely to imagine also an external sense, would annihilate the faculty
  6642. of intuition itself which is to be determined by the imagination.]
  6643. Remark II. Now with this view all empirical use of our faculty of
  6644. cognition in the determination of time is in perfect accordance.
  6645. Its truth is supported by the fact that it is possible to perceive a
  6646. determination of time only by means of a change in external relations
  6647. (motion) to the permanent in space (for example, we become aware of the
  6648. sun's motion by observing the changes of his relation to the objects
  6649. of this earth). But this is not all. We find that we possess nothing
  6650. permanent that can correspond and be submitted to the conception of a
  6651. substance as intuition, except matter. This idea of permanence is not
  6652. itself derived from external experience, but is an a priori necessary
  6653. condition of all determination of time, consequently also of the
  6654. internal sense in reference to our own existence, and that through
  6655. the existence of external things. In the representation "I," the
  6656. consciousness of myself is not an intuition, but a merely intellectual
  6657. representation produced by the spontaneous activity of a thinking
  6658. subject. It follows, that this "I" has not any predicate of intuition,
  6659. which, in its character of permanence, could serve as correlate to
  6660. the determination of time in the internal sense--in the same way as
  6661. impenetrability is the correlate of matter as an empirical intuition.
  6662. Remark III. From the fact that the existence of external things is a
  6663. necessary condition of the possibility of a determined consciousness
  6664. of ourselves, it does not follow that every intuitive representation
  6665. of external things involves the existence of these things, for their
  6666. representations may very well be the mere products of the imagination
  6667. (in dreams as well as in madness); though, indeed, these are themselves
  6668. created by the reproduction of previous external perceptions, which,
  6669. as has been shown, are possible only through the reality of external
  6670. objects. The sole aim of our remarks has, however, been to prove
  6671. that internal experience in general is possible only through external
  6672. experience in general. Whether this or that supposed experience be
  6673. purely imaginary must be discovered from its particular determinations
  6674. and by comparing these with the criteria of all real experience.
  6675. Finally, as regards the third postulate, it applies to material
  6676. necessity in existence, and not to merely formal and logical necessity
  6677. in the connection of conceptions. Now as we cannot cognize completely
  6678. a priori the existence of any object of sense, though we can do so
  6679. comparatively a priori, that is, relatively to some other previously
  6680. given existence--a cognition, however, which can only be of such an
  6681. existence as must be contained in the complex of experience, of which
  6682. the previously given perception is a part--the necessity of existence
  6683. can never be cognized from conceptions, but always, on the contrary,
  6684. from its connection with that which is an object of perception. But the
  6685. only existence cognized, under the condition of other given phenomena,
  6686. as necessary, is the existence of effects from given causes in
  6687. conformity with the laws of causality. It is consequently not the
  6688. necessity of the existence of things (as substances), but the necessity
  6689. of the state of things that we cognize, and that not immediately, but by
  6690. means of the existence of other states given in perception, according
  6691. to empirical laws of causality. Hence it follows that the criterion of
  6692. necessity is to be found only in the law of possible experience--that
  6693. everything which happens is determined a priori in the phenomenon by
  6694. its cause. Thus we cognize only the necessity of effects in nature, the
  6695. causes of which are given us. Moreover, the criterion of necessity
  6696. in existence possesses no application beyond the field of possible
  6697. experience, and even in this it is not valid of the existence of things
  6698. as substances, because these can never be considered as empirical
  6699. effects, or as something that happens and has a beginning. Necessity,
  6700. therefore, regards only the relations of phenomena according to the
  6701. dynamical law of causality, and the possibility grounded thereon, of
  6702. reasoning from some given existence (of a cause) a priori to another
  6703. existence (of an effect). "Everything that happens is hypothetically
  6704. necessary," is a principle which subjects the changes that take place in
  6705. the world to a law, that is, to a rule of necessary existence, without
  6706. which nature herself could not possibly exist. Hence the proposition,
  6707. "Nothing happens by blind chance (in mundo non datur casus)," is an
  6708. a priori law of nature. The case is the same with the proposition,
  6709. "Necessity in nature is not blind," that is, it is conditioned,
  6710. consequently intelligible necessity (non datur fatum). Both laws subject
  6711. the play of change to "a nature of things (as phenomena)," or, which
  6712. is the same thing, to the unity of the understanding, and through
  6713. the understanding alone can changes belong to an experience, as the
  6714. synthetical unity of phenomena. Both belong to the class of dynamical
  6715. principles. The former is properly a consequence of the principle of
  6716. causality--one of the analogies of experience. The latter belongs to the
  6717. principles of modality, which to the determination of causality adds the
  6718. conception of necessity, which is itself, however, subject to a rule of
  6719. the understanding. The principle of continuity forbids any leap in the
  6720. series of phenomena regarded as changes (in mundo non datur saltus); and
  6721. likewise, in the complex of all empirical intuitions in space, any
  6722. break or hiatus between two phenomena (non datur hiatus)--for we can so
  6723. express the principle, that experience can admit nothing which proves
  6724. the existence of a vacuum, or which even admits it as a part of an
  6725. empirical synthesis. For, as regards a vacuum or void, which we may
  6726. cogitate as out and beyond the field of possible experience (the world),
  6727. such a question cannot come before the tribunal of mere understanding,
  6728. which decides only upon questions that concern the employment of given
  6729. phenomena for the construction of empirical cognition. It is rather a
  6730. problem for ideal reason, which passes beyond the sphere of a possible
  6731. experience and aims at forming a judgement of that which surrounds and
  6732. circumscribes it, and the proper place for the consideration of it is
  6733. the transcendental dialectic. These four propositions, "In mundo non
  6734. datur hiatus, non datur saltus, non datur casus, non datur fatum," as
  6735. well as all principles of transcendental origin, we could very easily
  6736. exhibit in their proper order, that is, in conformity with the order
  6737. of the categories, and assign to each its proper place. But the already
  6738. practised reader will do this for himself, or discover the clue to such
  6739. an arrangement. But the combined result of all is simply this, to admit
  6740. into the empirical synthesis nothing which might cause a break in or
  6741. be foreign to the understanding and the continuous connection of all
  6742. phenomena, that is, the unity of the conceptions of the understanding.
  6743. For in the understanding alone is the unity of experience, in which all
  6744. perceptions must have their assigned place, possible.
  6745. Whether the field of possibility be greater than that of reality,
  6746. and whether the field of the latter be itself greater than that of
  6747. necessity, are interesting enough questions, and quite capable
  6748. of synthetic solution, questions, however, which come under the
  6749. jurisdiction of reason alone. For they are tantamount to asking whether
  6750. all things as phenomena do without exception belong to the complex and
  6751. connected whole of a single experience, of which every given
  6752. perception is a part which therefore cannot be conjoined with any
  6753. other phenomena--or, whether my perceptions can belong to more than one
  6754. possible experience? The understanding gives to experience, according
  6755. to the subjective and formal conditions, of sensibility as well as of
  6756. apperception, the rules which alone make this experience possible.
  6757. Other forms of intuition besides those of space and time, other forms of
  6758. understanding besides the discursive forms of thought, or of cognition
  6759. by means of conceptions, we can neither imagine nor make intelligible
  6760. to ourselves; and even if we could, they would still not belong to
  6761. experience, which is the only mode of cognition by which objects are
  6762. presented to us. Whether other perceptions besides those which belong
  6763. to the total of our possible experience, and consequently whether some
  6764. other sphere of matter exists, the understanding has no power to decide,
  6765. its proper occupation being with the synthesis of that which is given.
  6766. Moreover, the poverty of the usual arguments which go to prove the
  6767. existence of a vast sphere of possibility, of which all that is real
  6768. (every object of experience) is but a small part, is very remarkable.
  6769. "All real is possible"; from this follows naturally, according to the
  6770. logical laws of conversion, the particular proposition: "Some possible
  6771. is real." Now this seems to be equivalent to: "Much is possible that is
  6772. not real." No doubt it does seem as if we ought to consider the sum of
  6773. the possible to be greater than that of the real, from the fact that
  6774. something must be added to the former to constitute the latter. But this
  6775. notion of adding to the possible is absurd. For that which is not in
  6776. the sum of the possible, and consequently requires to be added to it,
  6777. is manifestly impossible. In addition to accordance with the formal
  6778. conditions of experience, the understanding requires a connection with
  6779. some perception; but that which is connected with this perception is
  6780. real, even although it is not immediately perceived. But that another
  6781. series of phenomena, in complete coherence with that which is given
  6782. in perception, consequently more than one all-embracing experience is
  6783. possible, is an inference which cannot be concluded from the data given
  6784. us by experience, and still less without any data at all. That which is
  6785. possible only under conditions which are themselves merely possible, is
  6786. not possible in any respect. And yet we can find no more certain ground
  6787. on which to base the discussion of the question whether the sphere of
  6788. possibility is wider than that of experience.
  6789. I have merely mentioned these questions, that in treating of the
  6790. conception of the understanding, there might be no omission of anything
  6791. that, in the common opinion, belongs to them. In reality, however, the
  6792. notion of absolute possibility (possibility which is valid in every
  6793. respect) is not a mere conception of the understanding, which can be
  6794. employed empirically, but belongs to reason alone, which passes the
  6795. bounds of all empirical use of the understanding. We have, therefore,
  6796. contented ourselves with a merely critical remark, leaving the subject
  6797. to be explained in the sequel.
  6798. Before concluding this fourth section, and at the same time the system
  6799. of all principles of the pure understanding, it seems proper to
  6800. mention the reasons which induced me to term the principles of modality
  6801. postulates. This expression I do not here use in the sense which some
  6802. more recent philosophers, contrary to its meaning with mathematicians,
  6803. to whom the word properly belongs, attach to it--that of a proposition,
  6804. namely, immediately certain, requiring neither deduction nor proof. For
  6805. if, in the case of synthetical propositions, however evident they may
  6806. be, we accord to them without deduction, and merely on the strength
  6807. of their own pretensions, unqualified belief, all critique of the
  6808. understanding is entirely lost; and, as there is no want of bold
  6809. pretensions, which the common belief (though for the philosopher this is
  6810. no credential) does not reject, the understanding lies exposed to every
  6811. delusion and conceit, without the power of refusing its assent to those
  6812. assertions, which, though illegitimate, demand acceptance as veritable
  6813. axioms. When, therefore, to the conception of a thing an a priori
  6814. determination is synthetically added, such a proposition must obtain, if
  6815. not a proof, at least a deduction of the legitimacy of its assertion.
  6816. The principles of modality are, however, not objectively synthetical,
  6817. for the predicates of possibility, reality, and necessity do not in
  6818. the least augment the conception of that of which they are affirmed,
  6819. inasmuch as they contribute nothing to the representation of the object.
  6820. But as they are, nevertheless, always synthetical, they are so merely
  6821. subjectively. That is to say, they have a reflective power, and apply
  6822. to the conception of a thing, of which, in other respects, they affirm
  6823. nothing, the faculty of cognition in which the conception originates
  6824. and has its seat. So that if the conception merely agree with the formal
  6825. conditions of experience, its object is called possible; if it is in
  6826. connection with perception, and determined thereby, the object is real;
  6827. if it is determined according to conceptions by means of the connection
  6828. of perceptions, the object is called necessary. The principles of
  6829. modality therefore predicate of a conception nothing more than the
  6830. procedure of the faculty of cognition which generated it. Now a
  6831. postulate in mathematics is a practical proposition which contains
  6832. nothing but the synthesis by which we present an object to ourselves,
  6833. and produce the conception of it, for example--"With a given line,
  6834. to describe a circle upon a plane, from a given point"; and such a
  6835. proposition does not admit of proof, because the procedure, which it
  6836. requires, is exactly that by which alone it is possible to generate the
  6837. conception of such a figure. With the same right, accordingly, can we
  6838. postulate the principles of modality, because they do not augment* the
  6839. conception of a thing but merely indicate the manner in which it is
  6840. connected with the faculty of cognition.
  6841. [*Footnote: When I think the reality of a thing, I do really think more
  6842. than the possibility, but not in the thing; for that can never contain
  6843. more in reality than was contained in its complete possibility. But
  6844. while the notion of possibility is merely the notion of a position of
  6845. thing in relation to the understanding (its empirical use), reality is
  6846. the conjunction of the thing with perception.]
  6847. GENERAL REMARK ON THE SYSTEM OF PRINCIPLES.
  6848. It is very remarkable that we cannot perceive the possibility of a thing
  6849. from the category alone, but must always have an intuition, by which
  6850. to make evident the objective reality of the pure conception of the
  6851. understanding. Take, for example, the categories of relation. How (1)
  6852. a thing can exist only as a subject, and not as a mere determination of
  6853. other things, that is, can be substance; or how (2), because something
  6854. exists, some other thing must exist, consequently how a thing can be a
  6855. cause; or how (3), when several things exist, from the fact that one
  6856. of these things exists, some consequence to the others follows,
  6857. and reciprocally, and in this way a community of substances can be
  6858. possible--are questions whose solution cannot be obtained from mere
  6859. conceptions. The very same is the case with the other categories; for
  6860. example, how a thing can be of the same sort with many others, that is,
  6861. can be a quantity, and so on. So long as we have not intuition we cannot
  6862. know whether we do really think an object by the categories, and where
  6863. an object can anywhere be found to cohere with them, and thus the truth
  6864. is established, that the categories are not in themselves cognitions,
  6865. but mere forms of thought for the construction of cognitions from given
  6866. intuitions. For the same reason is it true that from categories alone
  6867. no synthetical proposition can be made. For example: "In every existence
  6868. there is substance," that is, something that can exist only as a subject
  6869. and not as mere predicate; or, "Everything is a quantity"--to construct
  6870. propositions such as these, we require something to enable us to go out
  6871. beyond the given conception and connect another with it. For the same
  6872. reason the attempt to prove a synthetical proposition by means of mere
  6873. conceptions, for example: "Everything that exists contingently has a
  6874. cause," has never succeeded. We could never get further than proving
  6875. that, without this relation to conceptions, we could not conceive the
  6876. existence of the contingent, that is, could not a priori through the
  6877. understanding cognize the existence of such a thing; but it does not
  6878. hence follow that this is also the condition of the possibility of the
  6879. thing itself that is said to be contingent. If, accordingly; we look
  6880. back to our proof of the principle of causality, we shall find that we
  6881. were able to prove it as valid only of objects of possible experience,
  6882. and, indeed, only as itself the principle of the possibility of
  6883. experience, Consequently of the cognition of an object given in
  6884. empirical intuition, and not from mere conceptions. That, however,
  6885. the proposition: "Everything that is contingent must have a cause," is
  6886. evident to every one merely from conceptions, is not to be denied. But
  6887. in this case the conception of the contingent is cogitated as involving
  6888. not the category of modality (as that the non-existence of which can
  6889. be conceived) but that of relation (as that which can exist only as
  6890. the consequence of something else), and so it is really an identical
  6891. proposition: "That which can exist only as a consequence, has a cause."
  6892. In fact, when we have to give examples of contingent existence, we
  6893. always refer to changes, and not merely to the possibility of conceiving
  6894. the opposite.* But change is an event, which, as such, is possible only
  6895. through a cause, and considered per se its non-existence is therefore
  6896. possible, and we become cognizant of its contingency from the fact that
  6897. it can exist only as the effect of a cause. Hence, if a thing is assumed
  6898. to be contingent, it is an analytical proposition to say, it has a
  6899. cause.
  6900. [*Footnote: We can easily conceive the non-existence of matter; but the
  6901. ancients did not thence infer its contingency. But even the alternation
  6902. of the existence and non-existence of a given state in a thing, in
  6903. which all change consists, by no means proves the contingency of that
  6904. state--the ground of proof being the reality of its opposite. For
  6905. example, a body is in a state of rest after motion, but we cannot infer
  6906. the contingency of the motion from the fact that the former is the
  6907. opposite of the latter. For this opposite is merely a logical and not a
  6908. real opposite to the other. If we wish to demonstrate the contingency of
  6909. the motion, what we ought to prove is that, instead of the motion which
  6910. took place in the preceding point of time, it was possible for the body
  6911. to have been then in rest, not, that it is afterwards in rest; for in
  6912. this case, both opposites are perfectly consistent with each other.]
  6913. But it is still more remarkable that, to understand the possibility of
  6914. things according to the categories and thus to demonstrate the objective
  6915. reality of the latter, we require not merely intuitions, but external
  6916. intuitions. If, for example, we take the pure conceptions of relation,
  6917. we find that (1) for the purpose of presenting to the conception of
  6918. substance something permanent in intuition corresponding thereto and
  6919. thus of demonstrating the objective reality of this conception, we
  6920. require an intuition (of matter) in space, because space alone is
  6921. permanent and determines things as such, while time, and with it all
  6922. that is in the internal sense, is in a state of continual flow; (2)
  6923. in order to represent change as the intuition corresponding to the
  6924. conception of causality, we require the representation of motion as
  6925. change in space; in fact, it is through it alone that changes, the
  6926. possibility of which no pure understanding can perceive, are capable
  6927. of being intuited. Change is the connection of determinations
  6928. contradictorily opposed to each other in the existence of one and the
  6929. same thing. Now, how it is possible that out of a given state one
  6930. quite opposite to it in the same thing should follow, reason without
  6931. an example can not only not conceive, but cannot even make intelligible
  6932. without intuition; and this intuition is the motion of a point in space;
  6933. the existence of which in different spaces (as a consequence of opposite
  6934. determinations) alone makes the intuition of change possible. For, in
  6935. order to make even internal change cognitable, we require to represent
  6936. time, as the form of the internal sense, figuratively by a line, and the
  6937. internal change by the drawing of that line (motion), and consequently
  6938. are obliged to employ external intuition to be able to represent the
  6939. successive existence of ourselves in different states. The proper ground
  6940. of this fact is that all change to be perceived as change presupposes
  6941. something permanent in intuition, while in the internal sense no
  6942. permanent intuition is to be found. Lastly, the objective possibility
  6943. of the category of community cannot be conceived by mere reason, and
  6944. consequently its objective reality cannot be demonstrated without an
  6945. intuition, and that external in space. For how can we conceive the
  6946. possibility of community, that is, when several substances exist, that
  6947. some effect on the existence of the one follows from the existence
  6948. of the other, and reciprocally, and therefore that, because something
  6949. exists in the latter, something else must exist in the former, which
  6950. could not be understood from its own existence alone? For this is the
  6951. very essence of community--which is inconceivable as a property of
  6952. things which are perfectly isolated. Hence, Leibnitz, in attributing to
  6953. the substances of the world--as cogitated by the understanding alone--a
  6954. community, required the mediating aid of a divinity; for, from their
  6955. existence, such a property seemed to him with justice inconceivable. But
  6956. we can very easily conceive the possibility of community (of
  6957. substances as phenomena) if we represent them to ourselves as in space,
  6958. consequently in external intuition. For external intuition contains
  6959. in itself a priori formal external relations, as the conditions of the
  6960. possibility of the real relations of action and reaction, and
  6961. therefore of the possibility of community. With the same ease can it
  6962. be demonstrated, that the possibility of things as quantities, and
  6963. consequently the objective reality of the category of quantity, can be
  6964. grounded only in external intuition, and that by its means alone is the
  6965. notion of quantity appropriated by the internal sense. But I must avoid
  6966. prolixity, and leave the task of illustrating this by examples to the
  6967. reader's own reflection.
  6968. The above remarks are of the greatest importance, not only for the
  6969. confirmation of our previous confutation of idealism, but still more
  6970. when the subject of self-cognition by mere internal consciousness
  6971. and the determination of our own nature without the aid of external
  6972. empirical intuitions is under discussion, for the indication of the
  6973. grounds of the possibility of such a cognition.
  6974. The result of the whole of this part of the analytic of principles is,
  6975. therefore: "All principles of the pure understanding are nothing more
  6976. than a priori principles of the possibility of experience, and to
  6977. experience alone do all a priori synthetical propositions apply and
  6978. relate"; indeed, their possibility itself rests entirely on this
  6979. relation.
  6980. CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena
  6981. and Noumena.
  6982. We have now not only traversed the region of the pure understanding and
  6983. carefully surveyed every part of it, but we have also measured it, and
  6984. assigned to everything therein its proper place. But this land is an
  6985. island, and enclosed by nature herself within unchangeable limits. It is
  6986. the land of truth (an attractive word), surrounded by a wide and stormy
  6987. ocean, the region of illusion, where many a fog-bank, many an iceberg,
  6988. seems to the mariner, on his voyage of discovery, a new country, and,
  6989. while constantly deluding him with vain hopes, engages him in dangerous
  6990. adventures, from which he never can desist, and which yet he never can
  6991. bring to a termination. But before venturing upon this sea, in order
  6992. to explore it in its whole extent, and to arrive at a certainty whether
  6993. anything is to be discovered there, it will not be without advantage if
  6994. we cast our eyes upon the chart of the land that we are about to
  6995. leave, and to ask ourselves, firstly, whether we cannot rest perfectly
  6996. contented with what it contains, or whether we must not of necessity
  6997. be contented with it, if we can find nowhere else a solid foundation to
  6998. build upon; and, secondly, by what title we possess this land itself,
  6999. and how we hold it secure against all hostile claims? Although, in the
  7000. course of our analytic, we have already given sufficient answers to
  7001. these questions, yet a summary recapitulation of these solutions may
  7002. be useful in strengthening our conviction, by uniting in one point the
  7003. momenta of the arguments.
  7004. We have seen that everything which the understanding draws from itself,
  7005. without borrowing from experience, it nevertheless possesses only
  7006. for the behoof and use of experience. The principles of the pure
  7007. understanding, whether constitutive a priori (as the mathematical
  7008. principles), or merely regulative (as the dynamical), contain nothing
  7009. but the pure schema, as it were, of possible experience. For experience
  7010. possesses its unity from the synthetical unity which the understanding,
  7011. originally and from itself, imparts to the synthesis of the imagination
  7012. in relation to apperception, and in a priori relation to and agreement
  7013. with which phenomena, as data for a possible cognition, must stand. But
  7014. although these rules of the understanding are not only a priori true,
  7015. but the very source of all truth, that is, of the accordance of our
  7016. cognition with objects, and on this ground, that they contain the basis
  7017. of the possibility of experience, as the ensemble of all cognition, it
  7018. seems to us not enough to propound what is true--we desire also to
  7019. be told what we want to know. If, then, we learn nothing more by this
  7020. critical examination than what we should have practised in the merely
  7021. empirical use of the understanding, without any such subtle inquiry,
  7022. the presumption is that the advantage we reap from it is not worth
  7023. the labour bestowed upon it. It may certainly be answered that no rash
  7024. curiosity is more prejudicial to the enlargement of our knowledge than
  7025. that which must know beforehand the utility of this or that piece
  7026. of information which we seek, before we have entered on the needful
  7027. investigations, and before one could form the least conception of its
  7028. utility, even though it were placed before our eyes. But there is
  7029. one advantage in such transcendental inquiries which can be made
  7030. comprehensible to the dullest and most reluctant learner--this, namely,
  7031. that the understanding which is occupied merely with empirical exercise,
  7032. and does not reflect on the sources of its own cognition, may exercise
  7033. its functions very well and very successfully, but is quite unable to do
  7034. one thing, and that of very great importance, to determine, namely,
  7035. the bounds that limit its employment, and to know what lies within
  7036. or without its own sphere. This purpose can be obtained only by
  7037. such profound investigations as we have instituted. But if it cannot
  7038. distinguish whether certain questions lie within its horizon or not, it
  7039. can never be sure either as to its claims or possessions, but must lay
  7040. its account with many humiliating corrections, when it transgresses, as
  7041. it unavoidably will, the limits of its own territory, and loses itself
  7042. in fanciful opinions and blinding illusions.
  7043. That the understanding, therefore, cannot make of its a priori
  7044. principles, or even of its conceptions, other than an empirical use,
  7045. is a proposition which leads to the most important results. A
  7046. transcendental use is made of a conception in a fundamental proposition
  7047. or principle, when it is referred to things in general and considered
  7048. as things in themselves; an empirical use, when it is referred merely to
  7049. phenomena, that is, to objects of a possible experience. That the latter
  7050. use of a conception is the only admissible one is evident from the
  7051. reasons following. For every conception are requisite, firstly, the
  7052. logical form of a conception (of thought) general; and, secondly, the
  7053. possibility of presenting to this an object to which it may apply.
  7054. Failing this latter, it has no sense, and utterly void of content,
  7055. although it may contain the logical function for constructing a
  7056. conception from certain data. Now, object cannot be given to a
  7057. conception otherwise than by intuition, and, even if a pure intuition
  7058. antecedent to the object is a priori possible, this pure intuition can
  7059. itself obtain objective validity only from empirical intuition, of which
  7060. it is itself but the form. All conceptions, therefore, and with them
  7061. all principles, however high the degree of their a priori possibility,
  7062. relate to empirical intuitions, that is, to data towards a possible
  7063. experience. Without this they possess no objective validity, but are
  7064. mere play of imagination or of understanding with images or notions. Let
  7065. us take, for example, the conceptions of mathematics, and first in its
  7066. pure intuitions. "Space has three dimensions"--"Between two points there
  7067. can be only one straight line," etc. Although all these principles,
  7068. and the representation of the object with which this science occupies
  7069. itself, are generated in the mind entirely a priori, they would
  7070. nevertheless have no significance if we were not always able to exhibit
  7071. their significance in and by means of phenomena (empirical objects).
  7072. Hence it is requisite that an abstract conception be made sensuous,
  7073. that is, that an object corresponding to it in intuition be forthcoming,
  7074. otherwise the conception remains, as we say, without sense, that
  7075. is, without meaning. Mathematics fulfils this requirement by the
  7076. construction of the figure, which is a phenomenon evident to the senses.
  7077. The same science finds support and significance in number; this in its
  7078. turn finds it in the fingers, or in counters, or in lines and points.
  7079. The conception itself is always produced a priori, together with the
  7080. synthetical principles or formulas from such conceptions; but the proper
  7081. employment of them, and their application to objects, can exist nowhere
  7082. but in experience, the possibility of which, as regards its form, they
  7083. contain a priori.
  7084. That this is also the case with all of the categories and the principles
  7085. based upon them is evident from the fact that we cannot render
  7086. intelligible the possibility of an object corresponding to them without
  7087. having recourse to the conditions of sensibility, consequently, to the
  7088. form of phenomena, to which, as their only proper objects, their use
  7089. must therefore be confined, inasmuch as, if this condition is removed,
  7090. all significance, that is, all relation to an object, disappears, and
  7091. no example can be found to make it comprehensible what sort of things we
  7092. ought to think under such conceptions.
  7093. The conception of quantity cannot be explained except by saying that
  7094. it is the determination of a thing whereby it can be cogitated how
  7095. many times one is placed in it. But this "how many times" is based upon
  7096. successive repetition, consequently upon time and the synthesis of the
  7097. homogeneous therein. Reality, in contradistinction to negation, can be
  7098. explained only by cogitating a time which is either filled therewith or
  7099. is void. If I leave out the notion of permanence (which is existence in
  7100. all time), there remains in the conception of substance nothing but the
  7101. logical notion of subject, a notion of which I endeavour to realize by
  7102. representing to myself something that can exist only as a subject. But
  7103. not only am I perfectly ignorant of any conditions under which this
  7104. logical prerogative can belong to a thing, I can make nothing out of
  7105. the notion, and draw no inference from it, because no object to which
  7106. to apply the conception is determined, and we consequently do not know
  7107. whether it has any meaning at all. In like manner, if I leave out the
  7108. notion of time, in which something follows upon some other thing in
  7109. conformity with a rule, I can find nothing in the pure category, except
  7110. that there is a something of such a sort that from it a conclusion may
  7111. be drawn as to the existence of some other thing. But in this case
  7112. it would not only be impossible to distinguish between a cause and an
  7113. effect, but, as this power to draw conclusions requires conditions of
  7114. which I am quite ignorant, the conception is not determined as to the
  7115. mode in which it ought to apply to an object. The so-called principle:
  7116. "Everything that is contingent has a cause," comes with a gravity and
  7117. self-assumed authority that seems to require no support from without.
  7118. But, I ask, what is meant by contingent? The answer is that the
  7119. non-existence of which is possible. But I should like very well to know
  7120. by what means this possibility of non-existence is to be cognized, if we
  7121. do not represent to ourselves a succession in the series of phenomena,
  7122. and in this succession an existence which follows a non-existence, or
  7123. conversely, consequently, change. For to say, that the non-existence
  7124. of a thing is not self-contradictory is a lame appeal to a logical
  7125. condition, which is no doubt a necessary condition of the existence of
  7126. the conception, but is far from being sufficient for the real objective
  7127. possibility of non-existence. I can annihilate in thought every existing
  7128. substance without self-contradiction, but I cannot infer from this their
  7129. objective contingency in existence, that is to say, the possibility of
  7130. their non-existence in itself. As regards the category of community,
  7131. it may easily be inferred that, as the pure categories of substance and
  7132. causality are incapable of a definition and explanation sufficient to
  7133. determine their object without the aid of intuition, the category
  7134. of reciprocal causality in the relation of substances to each other
  7135. (commercium) is just as little susceptible thereof. Possibility,
  7136. existence, and necessity nobody has ever yet been able to explain
  7137. without being guilty of manifest tautology, when the definition has been
  7138. drawn entirely from the pure understanding. For the substitution of the
  7139. logical possibility of the conception--the condition of which is that
  7140. it be not self-contradictory, for the transcendental possibility of
  7141. things--the condition of which is that there be an object corresponding
  7142. to the conception, is a trick which can only deceive the inexperienced.*
  7143. [*Footnote: In one word, to none of these conceptions belongs a
  7144. corresponding object, and consequently their real possibility cannot
  7145. be demonstrated, if we take away sensuous intuition--the only intuition
  7146. which we possess--and there then remains nothing but the logical
  7147. possibility, that is, the fact that the conception or thought is
  7148. possible--which, however, is not the question; what we want to know
  7149. being, whether it relates to an object and thus possesses any meaning.]
  7150. It follows incontestably, that the pure conceptions of the understanding
  7151. are incapable of transcendental, and must always be of empirical use
  7152. alone, and that the principles of the pure understanding relate only
  7153. to the general conditions of a possible experience, to objects of the
  7154. senses, and never to things in general, apart from the mode in which we
  7155. intuite them.
  7156. Transcendental analytic has accordingly this important result, to wit,
  7157. that the understanding is competent' effect nothing a priori, except the
  7158. anticipation of the form of a possible experience in general, and that,
  7159. as that which is not phenomenon cannot be an object of experience, it
  7160. can never overstep the limits of sensibility, within which alone
  7161. objects are presented to us. Its principles are merely principles of
  7162. the exposition of phenomena, and the proud name of an ontology, which
  7163. professes to present synthetical cognitions a priori of things in
  7164. general in a systematic doctrine, must give place to the modest title of
  7165. analytic of the pure understanding.
  7166. Thought is the act of referring a given intuition to an object. If
  7167. the mode of this intuition is unknown to us, the object is merely
  7168. transcendental, and the conception of the understanding is employed only
  7169. transcendentally, that is, to produce unity in the thought of a manifold
  7170. in general. Now a pure category, in which all conditions of sensuous
  7171. intuition--as the only intuition we possess--are abstracted, does not
  7172. determine an object, but merely expresses the thought of an object in
  7173. general, according to different modes. Now, to employ a conception, the
  7174. function of judgement is required, by which an object is subsumed under
  7175. the conception, consequently the at least formal condition, under which
  7176. something can be given in intuition. Failing this condition of judgement
  7177. (schema), subsumption is impossible; for there is in such a case
  7178. nothing given, which may be subsumed under the conception. The merely
  7179. transcendental use of the categories is therefore, in fact, no use at
  7180. all and has no determined, or even, as regards its form, determinable
  7181. object. Hence it follows that the pure category is incompetent to
  7182. establish a synthetical a priori principle, and that the principles of
  7183. the pure understanding are only of empirical and never of transcendental
  7184. use, and that beyond the sphere of possible experience no synthetical a
  7185. priori principles are possible.
  7186. It may be advisable, therefore, to express ourselves thus. The pure
  7187. categories, apart from the formal conditions of sensibility, have
  7188. a merely transcendental meaning, but are nevertheless not of
  7189. transcendental use, because this is in itself impossible, inasmuch as
  7190. all the conditions of any employment or use of them (in judgements) are
  7191. absent, to wit, the formal conditions of the subsumption of an object
  7192. under these conceptions. As, therefore, in the character of pure
  7193. categories, they must be employed empirically, and cannot be employed
  7194. transcendentally, they are of no use at all, when separated from
  7195. sensibility, that is, they cannot be applied to an object. They are
  7196. merely the pure form of the employment of the understanding in respect
  7197. of objects in general and of thought, without its being at the same time
  7198. possible to think or to determine any object by their means. But there
  7199. lurks at the foundation of this subject an illusion which it is very
  7200. difficult to avoid. The categories are not based, as regards their
  7201. origin, upon sensibility, like the forms of intuition, space, and time;
  7202. they seem, therefore, to be capable of an application beyond the sphere
  7203. of sensuous objects. But this is not the case. They are nothing but mere
  7204. forms of thought, which contain only the logical faculty of uniting a
  7205. priori in consciousness the manifold given in intuition. Apart, then,
  7206. from the only intuition possible for us, they have still less meaning
  7207. than the pure sensuous forms, space and time, for through them an object
  7208. is at least given, while a mode of connection of the manifold, when the
  7209. intuition which alone gives the manifold is wanting, has no meaning at
  7210. all. At the same time, when we designate certain objects as phenomena or
  7211. sensuous existences, thus distinguishing our mode of intuiting them from
  7212. their own nature as things in themselves, it is evident that by this
  7213. very distinction we as it were place the latter, considered in this
  7214. their own nature, although we do not so intuite them, in opposition to
  7215. the former, or, on the other hand, we do so place other possible
  7216. things, which are not objects of our senses, but are cogitated by the
  7217. understanding alone, and call them intelligible existences (noumena).
  7218. Now the question arises whether the pure conceptions of our
  7219. understanding do possess significance in respect of these latter, and
  7220. may possibly be a mode of cognizing them.
  7221. But we are met at the very commencement with an ambiguity, which may
  7222. easily occasion great misapprehension. The understanding, when it terms
  7223. an object in a certain relation phenomenon, at the same time forms out
  7224. of this relation a representation or notion of an object in itself, and
  7225. hence believes that it can form also conceptions of such objects. Now as
  7226. the understanding possesses no other fundamental conceptions besides the
  7227. categories, it takes for granted that an object considered as a thing
  7228. in itself must be capable of being thought by means of these pure
  7229. conceptions, and is thereby led to hold the perfectly undetermined
  7230. conception of an intelligible existence, a something out of the sphere
  7231. of our sensibility, for a determinate conception of an existence which
  7232. we can cognize in some way or other by means of the understanding.
  7233. If, by the term noumenon, we understand a thing so far as it is not an
  7234. object of our sensuous intuition, thus making abstraction of our mode of
  7235. intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the word. But
  7236. if we understand by it an object of a non-sensuous intuition, we in this
  7237. case assume a peculiar mode of intuition, an intellectual intuition, to
  7238. wit, which does not, however, belong to us, of the very possibility of
  7239. which we have no notion--and this is a noumenon in the positive sense.
  7240. The doctrine of sensibility is also the doctrine of noumena in the
  7241. negative sense, that is, of things which the understanding is obliged to
  7242. cogitate apart from any relation to our mode of intuition, consequently
  7243. not as mere phenomena, but as things in themselves. But the
  7244. understanding at the same time comprehends that it cannot employ its
  7245. categories for the consideration of things in themselves, because these
  7246. possess significance only in relation to the unity of intuitions in
  7247. space and time, and that they are competent to determine this unity by
  7248. means of general a priori connecting conceptions only on account of the
  7249. pure ideality of space and time. Where this unity of time is not to be
  7250. met with, as is the case with noumena, the whole use, indeed the whole
  7251. meaning of the categories is entirely lost, for even the possibility of
  7252. things to correspond to the categories is in this case incomprehensible.
  7253. On this point, I need only refer the reader to what I have said at the
  7254. commencement of the General Remark appended to the foregoing chapter.
  7255. Now, the possibility of a thing can never be proved from the fact that
  7256. the conception of it is not self-contradictory, but only by means of
  7257. an intuition corresponding to the conception. If, therefore, we wish to
  7258. apply the categories to objects which cannot be regarded as phenomena,
  7259. we must have an intuition different from the sensuous, and in this case
  7260. the objects would be a noumena in the positive sense of the word. Now,
  7261. as such an intuition, that is, an intellectual intuition, is no part of
  7262. our faculty of cognition, it is absolutely impossible for the categories
  7263. to possess any application beyond the limits of experience. It may be
  7264. true that there are intelligible existences to which our faculty of
  7265. sensuous intuition has no relation, and cannot be applied, but our
  7266. conceptions of the understanding, as mere forms of thought for our
  7267. sensuous intuition, do not extend to these. What, therefore, we call
  7268. noumenon must be understood by us as such in a negative sense.
  7269. If I take away from an empirical intuition all thought (by means of the
  7270. categories), there remains no cognition of any object; for by means of
  7271. mere intuition nothing is cogitated, and, from the existence of such
  7272. or such an affection of sensibility in me, it does not follow that this
  7273. affection or representation has any relation to an object without
  7274. me. But if I take away all intuition, there still remains the form of
  7275. thought, that is, the mode of determining an object for the manifold
  7276. of a possible intuition. Thus the categories do in some measure really
  7277. extend further than sensuous intuition, inasmuch as they think objects
  7278. in general, without regard to the mode (of sensibility) in which
  7279. these objects are given. But they do not for this reason apply to and
  7280. determine a wider sphere of objects, because we cannot assume that such
  7281. can be given, without presupposing the possibility of another than
  7282. the sensuous mode of intuition, a supposition we are not justified in
  7283. making.
  7284. I call a conception problematical which contains in itself no
  7285. contradiction, and which is connected with other cognitions as a
  7286. limitation of given conceptions, but whose objective reality cannot
  7287. be cognized in any manner. The conception of a noumenon, that is, of a
  7288. thing which must be cogitated not as an object of sense, but as a
  7289. thing in itself (solely through the pure understanding), is not
  7290. self-contradictory, for we are not entitled to maintain that sensibility
  7291. is the only possible mode of intuition. Nay, further, this conception is
  7292. necessary to restrain sensuous intuition within the bounds of phenomena,
  7293. and thus to limit the objective validity of sensuous cognition; for
  7294. things in themselves, which lie beyond its province, are called noumena
  7295. for the very purpose of indicating that this cognition does not extend
  7296. its application to all that the understanding thinks. But, after all,
  7297. the possibility of such noumena is quite incomprehensible, and beyond
  7298. the sphere of phenomena, all is for us a mere void; that is to say,
  7299. we possess an understanding whose province does problematically extend
  7300. beyond this sphere, but we do not possess an intuition, indeed, not even
  7301. the conception of a possible intuition, by means of which objects beyond
  7302. the region of sensibility could be given us, and in reference to which
  7303. the understanding might be employed assertorically. The conception of a
  7304. noumenon is therefore merely a limitative conception and therefore only
  7305. of negative use. But it is not an arbitrary or fictitious notion, but
  7306. is connected with the limitation of sensibility, without, however, being
  7307. capable of presenting us with any positive datum beyond this sphere.
  7308. The division of objects into phenomena and noumena, and of the
  7309. world into a mundus sensibilis and intelligibilis is therefore quite
  7310. inadmissible in a positive sense, although conceptions do certainly
  7311. admit of such a division; for the class of noumena have no determinate
  7312. object corresponding to them, and cannot therefore possess objective
  7313. validity. If we abandon the senses, how can it be made conceivable
  7314. that the categories (which are the only conceptions that could serve as
  7315. conceptions for noumena) have any sense or meaning at all, inasmuch
  7316. as something more than the mere unity of thought, namely, a possible
  7317. intuition, is requisite for their application to an object? The
  7318. conception of a noumenon, considered as merely problematical, is,
  7319. however, not only admissible, but, as a limitative conception of
  7320. sensibility, absolutely necessary. But, in this case, a noumenon is not
  7321. a particular intelligible object for our understanding; on the contrary,
  7322. the kind of understanding to which it could belong is itself a problem,
  7323. for we cannot form the most distant conception of the possibility of an
  7324. understanding which should cognize an object, not discursively by
  7325. means of categories, but intuitively in a non-sensuous intuition. Our
  7326. understanding attains in this way a sort of negative extension. That is
  7327. to say, it is not limited by, but rather limits, sensibility, by giving
  7328. the name of noumena to things, not considered as phenomena, but as
  7329. things in themselves. But it at the same time prescribes limits to
  7330. itself, for it confesses itself unable to cognize these by means of the
  7331. categories, and hence is compelled to cogitate them merely as an unknown
  7332. something.
  7333. I find, however, in the writings of modern authors, an entirely
  7334. different use of the expressions, mundus sensibilis and intelligibilis,
  7335. which quite departs from the meaning of the ancients--an acceptation in
  7336. which, indeed, there is to be found no difficulty, but which at the same
  7337. time depends on mere verbal quibbling. According to this meaning,
  7338. some have chosen to call the complex of phenomena, in so far as it is
  7339. intuited, mundus sensibilis, but in so far as the connection thereof is
  7340. cogitated according to general laws of thought, mundus intelligibilis.
  7341. Astronomy, in so far as we mean by the word the mere observation of the
  7342. starry heaven, may represent the former; a system of astronomy, such as
  7343. the Copernican or Newtonian, the latter. But such twisting of words is a
  7344. mere sophistical subterfuge, to avoid a difficult question, by modifying
  7345. its meaning to suit our own convenience. To be sure, understanding and
  7346. reason are employed in the cognition of phenomena; but the question is,
  7347. whether these can be applied when the object is not a phenomenon and in
  7348. this sense we regard it if it is cogitated as given to the understanding
  7349. alone, and not to the senses. The question therefore is whether, over
  7350. and above the empirical use of the understanding, a transcendental use
  7351. is possible, which applies to the noumenon as an object. This question
  7352. we have answered in the negative.
  7353. When therefore we say, the senses represent objects as they appear, the
  7354. understanding as they are, the latter statement must not be understood
  7355. in a transcendental, but only in an empirical signification, that is,
  7356. as they must be represented in the complete connection of phenomena, and
  7357. not according to what they may be, apart from their relation to possible
  7358. experience, consequently not as objects of the pure understanding. For
  7359. this must ever remain unknown to us. Nay, it is also quite unknown to us
  7360. whether any such transcendental or extraordinary cognition is possible
  7361. under any circumstances, at least, whether it is possible by means of
  7362. our categories. Understanding and sensibility, with us, can determine
  7363. objects only in conjunction. If we separate them, we have intuitions
  7364. without conceptions, or conceptions without intuitions; in both cases,
  7365. representations, which we cannot apply to any determinate object.
  7366. If, after all our inquiries and explanations, any one still hesitates to
  7367. abandon the mere transcendental use of the categories, let him attempt
  7368. to construct with them a synthetical proposition. It would, of course,
  7369. be unnecessary for this purpose to construct an analytical proposition,
  7370. for that does not extend the sphere of the understanding, but, being
  7371. concerned only about what is cogitated in the conception itself, it
  7372. leaves it quite undecided whether the conception has any relation to
  7373. objects, or merely indicates the unity of thought--complete abstraction
  7374. being made of the modi in which an object may be given: in such a
  7375. proposition, it is sufficient for the understanding to know what lies
  7376. in the conception--to what it applies is to it indifferent. The attempt
  7377. must therefore be made with a synthetical and so-called transcendental
  7378. principle, for example: "Everything that exists, exists as substance,"
  7379. or, "Everything that is contingent exists as an effect of some other
  7380. thing, viz., of its cause." Now I ask, whence can the understanding draw
  7381. these synthetical propositions, when the conceptions contained therein
  7382. do not relate to possible experience but to things in themselves
  7383. (noumena)? Where is to be found the third term, which is always
  7384. requisite PURE site in a synthetical proposition, which may connect
  7385. in the same proposition conceptions which have no logical (analytical)
  7386. connection with each other? The proposition never will be demonstrated,
  7387. nay, more, the possibility of any such pure assertion never can
  7388. be shown, without making reference to the empirical use of the
  7389. understanding, and thus, ipso facto, completely renouncing pure
  7390. and non-sensuous judgement. Thus the conception of pure and merely
  7391. intelligible objects is completely void of all principles of its
  7392. application, because we cannot imagine any mode in which they might be
  7393. given, and the problematical thought which leaves a place open for
  7394. them serves only, like a void space, to limit the use of empirical
  7395. principles, without containing at the same time any other object of
  7396. cognition beyond their sphere.
  7397. APPENDIX.
  7398. Of the Equivocal Nature or Amphiboly of the Conceptions of Reflection
  7399. from the Confusion of the Transcendental with the Empirical use of the
  7400. Understanding.
  7401. Reflection (reflexio) is not occupied about objects themselves, for the
  7402. purpose of directly obtaining conceptions of them, but is that state of
  7403. the mind in which we set ourselves to discover the subjective conditions
  7404. under which we obtain conceptions. It is the consciousness of the
  7405. relation of given representations to the different sources or faculties
  7406. of cognition, by which alone their relation to each other can be
  7407. rightly determined. The first question which occurs in considering our
  7408. representations is to what faculty of cognition do they belong? To the
  7409. understanding or to the senses? Many judgements are admitted to be true
  7410. from mere habit or inclination; but, because reflection neither precedes
  7411. nor follows, it is held to be a judgement that has its origin in the
  7412. understanding. All judgements do not require examination, that is,
  7413. investigation into the grounds of their truth. For, when they are
  7414. immediately certain (for example: "Between two points there can be only
  7415. one straight line"), no better or less mediate test of their truth can
  7416. be found than that which they themselves contain and express. But
  7417. all judgement, nay, all comparisons require reflection, that is, a
  7418. distinction of the faculty of cognition to which the given conceptions
  7419. belong. The act whereby I compare my representations with the faculty of
  7420. cognition which originates them, and whereby I distinguish whether they
  7421. are compared with each other as belonging to the pure understanding
  7422. or to sensuous intuition, I term transcendental reflection. Now, the
  7423. relations in which conceptions can stand to each other are those of
  7424. identity and difference, agreement and opposition, of the internal and
  7425. external, finally, of the determinable and the determining (matter
  7426. and form). The proper determination of these relations rests on the
  7427. question, to what faculty of cognition they subjectively belong, whether
  7428. to sensibility or understanding? For, on the manner in which we solve
  7429. this question depends the manner in which we must cogitate these
  7430. relations.
  7431. Before constructing any objective judgement, we compare the conceptions
  7432. that are to be placed in the judgement, and observe whether there exists
  7433. identity (of many representations in one conception), if a general
  7434. judgement is to be constructed, or difference, if a particular; whether
  7435. there is agreement when affirmative; and opposition when negative
  7436. judgements are to be constructed, and so on. For this reason we ought
  7437. to call these conceptions, conceptions of comparison (conceptus
  7438. comparationis). But as, when the question is not as to the logical form,
  7439. but as to the content of conceptions, that is to say, whether the things
  7440. themselves are identical or different, in agreement or opposition,
  7441. and so on, the things can have a twofold relation to our faculty
  7442. of cognition, to wit, a relation either to sensibility or to the
  7443. understanding, and as on this relation depends their relation to
  7444. each other, transcendental reflection, that is, the relation of given
  7445. representations to one or the other faculty of cognition, can alone
  7446. determine this latter relation. Thus we shall not be able to discover
  7447. whether the things are identical or different, in agreement or
  7448. opposition, etc., from the mere conception of the things by means
  7449. of comparison (comparatio), but only by distinguishing the mode
  7450. of cognition to which they belong, in other words, by means of
  7451. transcendental reflection. We may, therefore, with justice say, that
  7452. logical reflection is mere comparison, for in it no account is taken of
  7453. the faculty of cognition to which the given conceptions belong, and
  7454. they are consequently, as far as regards their origin, to be treated
  7455. as homogeneous; while transcendental reflection (which applies to the
  7456. objects themselves) contains the ground of the possibility of objective
  7457. comparison of representations with each other, and is therefore very
  7458. different from the former, because the faculties of cognition to which
  7459. they belong are not even the same. Transcendental reflection is a duty
  7460. which no one can neglect who wishes to establish an a priori judgement
  7461. upon things. We shall now proceed to fulfil this duty, and thereby throw
  7462. not a little light on the question as to the determination of the proper
  7463. business of the understanding.
  7464. 1. Identity and Difference. When an object is presented to us several
  7465. times, but always with the same internal determinations (qualitas et
  7466. quantitas), it, if an object of pure understanding, is always the same,
  7467. not several things, but only one thing (numerica identitas); but if a
  7468. phenomenon, we do not concern ourselves with comparing the conception of
  7469. the thing with the conception of some other, but, although they may be
  7470. in this respect perfectly the same, the difference of place at the same
  7471. time is a sufficient ground for asserting the numerical difference of
  7472. these objects (of sense). Thus, in the case of two drops of water, we
  7473. may make complete abstraction of all internal difference (quality and
  7474. quantity), and, the fact that they are intuited at the same time in
  7475. different places, is sufficient to justify us in holding them to
  7476. be numerically different. Leibnitz regarded phenomena as things in
  7477. themselves, consequently as intelligibilia, that is, objects of pure
  7478. understanding (although, on account of the confused nature of their
  7479. representations, he gave them the name of phenomena), and in this
  7480. case his principle of the indiscernible (principium identatis
  7481. indiscernibilium) is not to be impugned. But, as phenomena are objects
  7482. of sensibility, and, as the understanding, in respect of them, must be
  7483. employed empirically and not purely or transcendentally, plurality
  7484. and numerical difference are given by space itself as the condition of
  7485. external phenomena. For one part of space, although it may be perfectly
  7486. similar and equal to another part, is still without it, and for this
  7487. reason alone is different from the latter, which is added to it in order
  7488. to make up a greater space. It follows that this must hold good of
  7489. all things that are in the different parts of space at the same time,
  7490. however similar and equal one may be to another.
  7491. 2. Agreement and Opposition. When reality is represented by the pure
  7492. understanding (realitas noumenon), opposition between realities is
  7493. incogitable--such a relation, that is, that when these realities are
  7494. connected in one subject, they annihilate the effects of each other and
  7495. may be represented in the formula 3 -3 = 0. On the other hand, the
  7496. real in a phenomenon (realitas phaenomenon) may very well be in mutual
  7497. opposition, and, when united in the same subject, the one may completely
  7498. or in part annihilate the effect or consequence of the other; as in the
  7499. case of two moving forces in the same straight line drawing or
  7500. impelling a point in opposite directions, or in the case of a pleasure
  7501. counterbalancing a certain amount of pain.
  7502. 3. The Internal and External. In an object of the pure understanding,
  7503. only that is internal which has no relation (as regards its existence)
  7504. to anything different from itself. On the other hand, the internal
  7505. determinations of a substantia phaenomenon in space are nothing
  7506. but relations, and it is itself nothing more than a complex of mere
  7507. relations. Substance in space we are cognizant of only through forces
  7508. operative in it, either drawing others towards itself (attraction),
  7509. or preventing others from forcing into itself (repulsion and
  7510. impenetrability). We know no other properties that make up the
  7511. conception of substance phenomenal in space, and which we term matter.
  7512. On the other hand, as an object of the pure understanding, every
  7513. substance must have internal determination and forces. But what other
  7514. internal attributes of such an object can I think than those which my
  7515. internal sense presents to me? That, to wit, which in either itself
  7516. thought, or something analogous to it. Hence Leibnitz, who looked upon
  7517. things as noumena, after denying them everything like external relation,
  7518. and therefore also composition or combination, declared that all
  7519. substances, even the component parts of matter, were simple substances
  7520. with powers of representation, in one word, monads.
  7521. 4. Matter and Form. These two conceptions lie at the foundation of all
  7522. other reflection, so inseparably are they connected with every mode of
  7523. exercising the understanding. The former denotes the determinable in
  7524. general, the second its determination, both in a transcendental sense,
  7525. abstraction being made of every difference in that which is given, and
  7526. of the mode in which it is determined. Logicians formerly termed the
  7527. universal, matter, the specific difference of this or that part of
  7528. the universal, form. In a judgement one may call the given conceptions
  7529. logical matter (for the judgement), the relation of these to each other
  7530. (by means of the copula), the form of the judgement. In an object, the
  7531. composite parts thereof (essentialia) are the matter; the mode in which
  7532. they are connected in the object, the form. In respect to things
  7533. in general, unlimited reality was regarded as the matter of all
  7534. possibility, the limitation thereof (negation) as the form, by which
  7535. one thing is distinguished from another according to transcendental
  7536. conceptions. The understanding demands that something be given (at least
  7537. in the conception), in order to be able to determine it in a certain
  7538. manner. Hence, in a conception of the pure understanding, the matter
  7539. precedes the form, and for this reason Leibnitz first assumed the
  7540. existence of things (monads) and of an internal power of representation
  7541. in them, in order to found upon this their external relation and the
  7542. community their state (that is, of their representations). Hence, with
  7543. him, space and time were possible--the former through the relation of
  7544. substances, the latter through the connection of their determinations
  7545. with each other, as causes and effects. And so would it really be,
  7546. if the pure understanding were capable of an immediate application
  7547. to objects, and if space and time were determinations of things in
  7548. themselves. But being merely sensuous intuitions, in which we determine
  7549. all objects solely as phenomena, the form of intuition (as a subjective
  7550. property of sensibility) must antecede all matter (sensations),
  7551. consequently space and time must antecede all phenomena and all data
  7552. of experience, and rather make experience itself possible. But the
  7553. intellectual philosopher could not endure that the form should precede
  7554. the things themselves and determine their possibility; an objection
  7555. perfectly correct, if we assume that we intuite things as they are,
  7556. although with confused representation. But as sensuous intuition is a
  7557. peculiar subjective condition, which is a priori at the foundation of
  7558. all perception, and the form of which is primitive, the form must be
  7559. given per se, and so far from matter (or the things themselves which
  7560. appear) lying at the foundation of experience (as we must conclude,
  7561. if we judge by mere conceptions), the very possibility of itself
  7562. presupposes, on the contrary, a given formal intuition (space and time).
  7563. REMARK ON THE AMPHIBOLY OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF REFLECTION.
  7564. Let me be allowed to term the position which we assign to a
  7565. conception either in the sensibility or in the pure understanding, the
  7566. transcendental place. In this manner, the appointment of the position
  7567. which must be taken by each conception according to the difference
  7568. in its use, and the directions for determining this place to all
  7569. conceptions according to rules, would be a transcendental topic, a
  7570. doctrine which would thoroughly shield us from the surreptitious devices
  7571. of the pure understanding and the delusions which thence arise, as it
  7572. would always distinguish to what faculty of cognition each conception
  7573. properly belonged. Every conception, every title, under which many
  7574. cognitions rank together, may be called a logical place. Upon this is
  7575. based the logical topic of Aristotle, of which teachers and rhetoricians
  7576. could avail themselves, in order, under certain titles of thought, to
  7577. observe what would best suit the matter they had to treat, and thus
  7578. enable themselves to quibble and talk with fluency and an appearance of
  7579. profundity.
  7580. Transcendental topic, on the contrary, contains nothing more than the
  7581. above-mentioned four titles of all comparison and distinction, which
  7582. differ from categories in this respect, that they do not represent the
  7583. object according to that which constitutes its conception (quantity,
  7584. reality), but set forth merely the comparison of representations, which
  7585. precedes our conceptions of things. But this comparison requires a
  7586. previous reflection, that is, a determination of the place to which the
  7587. representations of the things which are compared belong, whether,
  7588. to wit, they are cogitated by the pure understanding, or given by
  7589. sensibility.
  7590. Conceptions may be logically compared without the trouble of inquiring
  7591. to what faculty their objects belong, whether as noumena, to the
  7592. understanding, or as phenomena, to sensibility. If, however, we wish to
  7593. employ these conceptions in respect of objects, previous transcendental
  7594. reflection is necessary. Without this reflection I should make a very
  7595. unsafe use of these conceptions, and construct pretended synthetical
  7596. propositions which critical reason cannot acknowledge and which
  7597. are based solely upon a transcendental amphiboly, that is, upon a
  7598. substitution of an object of pure understanding for a phenomenon.
  7599. For want of this doctrine of transcendental topic, and consequently
  7600. deceived by the amphiboly of the conceptions of reflection, the
  7601. celebrated Leibnitz constructed an intellectual system of the world,
  7602. or rather, believed himself competent to cognize the internal nature of
  7603. things, by comparing all objects merely with the understanding and the
  7604. abstract formal conceptions of thought. Our table of the conceptions of
  7605. reflection gives us the unexpected advantage of being able to exhibit
  7606. the distinctive peculiarities of his system in all its parts, and at the
  7607. same time of exposing the fundamental principle of this peculiar mode of
  7608. thought, which rested upon naught but a misconception. He compared all
  7609. things with each other merely by means of conceptions, and naturally
  7610. found no other differences than those by which the understanding
  7611. distinguishes its pure conceptions one from another. The conditions
  7612. of sensuous intuition, which contain in themselves their own means of
  7613. distinction, he did not look upon as primitive, because sensibility
  7614. was to him but a confused mode of representation and not any particular
  7615. source of representations. A phenomenon was for him the representation
  7616. of the thing in itself, although distinguished from cognition by the
  7617. understanding only in respect of the logical form--the former with its
  7618. usual want of analysis containing, according to him, a certain mixture
  7619. of collateral representations in its conception of a thing, which it is
  7620. the duty of the understanding to separate and distinguish. In one word,
  7621. Leibnitz intellectualized phenomena, just as Locke, in his system
  7622. of noogony (if I may be allowed to make use of such expressions),
  7623. sensualized the conceptions of the understanding, that is to say,
  7624. declared them to be nothing more than empirical or abstract conceptions
  7625. of reflection. Instead of seeking in the understanding and sensibility
  7626. two different sources of representations, which, however, can present us
  7627. with objective judgements of things only in conjunction, each of
  7628. these great men recognized but one of these faculties, which, in their
  7629. opinion, applied immediately to things in themselves, the other having
  7630. no duty but that of confusing or arranging the representations of the
  7631. former.
  7632. Accordingly, the objects of sense were compared by Leibnitz as things in
  7633. general merely in the understanding.
  7634. 1st. He compares them in regard to their identity or difference--as
  7635. judged by the understanding. As, therefore, he considered merely the
  7636. conceptions of objects, and not their position in intuition, in
  7637. which alone objects can be given, and left quite out of sight the
  7638. transcendental locale of these conceptions--whether, that is, their
  7639. object ought to be classed among phenomena, or among things in
  7640. themselves, it was to be expected that he should extend the application
  7641. of the principle of indiscernibles, which is valid solely of conceptions
  7642. of things in general, to objects of sense (mundus phaenomenon), and that
  7643. he should believe that he had thereby contributed in no small degree to
  7644. extend our knowledge of nature. In truth, if I cognize in all its inner
  7645. determinations a drop of water as a thing in itself, I cannot look upon
  7646. one drop as different from another, if the conception of the one is
  7647. completely identical with that of the other. But if it is a phenomenon
  7648. in space, it has a place not merely in the understanding (among
  7649. conceptions), but also in sensuous external intuition (in space), and in
  7650. this case, the physical locale is a matter of indifference in regard to
  7651. the internal determinations of things, and one place, B, may contain
  7652. a thing which is perfectly similar and equal to another in a place, A,
  7653. just as well as if the two things were in every respect different from
  7654. each other. Difference of place without any other conditions, makes the
  7655. plurality and distinction of objects as phenomena, not only possible in
  7656. itself, but even necessary. Consequently, the above so-called law is not
  7657. a law of nature. It is merely an analytical rule for the comparison of
  7658. things by means of mere conceptions.
  7659. 2nd. The principle: "Realities (as simple affirmations) never logically
  7660. contradict each other," is a proposition perfectly true respecting the
  7661. relation of conceptions, but, whether as regards nature, or things in
  7662. themselves (of which we have not the slightest conception), is without
  7663. any the least meaning. For real opposition, in which A -B is = 0,
  7664. exists everywhere, an opposition, that is, in which one reality united
  7665. with another in the same subject annihilates the effects of the other--a
  7666. fact which is constantly brought before our eyes by the different
  7667. antagonistic actions and operations in nature, which, nevertheless, as
  7668. depending on real forces, must be called realitates phaenomena. General
  7669. mechanics can even present us with the empirical condition of this
  7670. opposition in an a priori rule, as it directs its attention to the
  7671. opposition in the direction of forces--a condition of which the
  7672. transcendental conception of reality can tell us nothing. Although M.
  7673. Leibnitz did not announce this proposition with precisely the pomp of
  7674. a new principle, he yet employed it for the establishment of
  7675. new propositions, and his followers introduced it into their
  7676. Leibnitzio-Wolfian system of philosophy. According to this principle,
  7677. for example, all evils are but consequences of the limited nature of
  7678. created beings, that is, negations, because these are the only opposite
  7679. of reality. (In the mere conception of a thing in general this is really
  7680. the case, but not in things as phenomena.) In like manner, the upholders
  7681. of this system deem it not only possible, but natural also, to connect
  7682. and unite all reality in one being, because they acknowledge no other
  7683. sort of opposition than that of contradiction (by which the conception
  7684. itself of a thing is annihilated), and find themselves unable to
  7685. conceive an opposition of reciprocal destruction, so to speak, in which
  7686. one real cause destroys the effect of another, and the conditions of
  7687. whose representation we meet with only in sensibility.
  7688. 3rd. The Leibnitzian monadology has really no better foundation than on
  7689. this philosopher's mode of falsely representing the difference of
  7690. the internal and external solely in relation to the understanding.
  7691. Substances, in general, must have something inward, which is therefore
  7692. free from external relations, consequently from that of composition
  7693. also. The simple--that which can be represented by a unit--is therefore
  7694. the foundation of that which is internal in things in themselves. The
  7695. internal state of substances cannot therefore consist in place, shape,
  7696. contact, or motion, determinations which are all external relations,
  7697. and we can ascribe to them no other than that whereby we internally
  7698. determine our faculty of sense itself, that is to say, the state of
  7699. representation. Thus, then, were constructed the monads, which were to
  7700. form the elements of the universe, the active force of which consists in
  7701. representation, the effects of this force being thus entirely confined
  7702. to themselves.
  7703. For the same reason, his view of the possible community of substances
  7704. could not represent it but as a predetermined harmony, and by no means
  7705. as a physical influence. For inasmuch as everything is occupied only
  7706. internally, that is, with its own representations, the state of the
  7707. representations of one substance could not stand in active and living
  7708. connection with that of another, but some third cause operating on all
  7709. without exception was necessary to make the different states correspond
  7710. with one another. And this did not happen by means of assistance applied
  7711. in each particular case (systema assistentiae), but through the unity of
  7712. the idea of a cause occupied and connected with all substances, in which
  7713. they necessarily receive, according to the Leibnitzian school, their
  7714. existence and permanence, consequently also reciprocal correspondence,
  7715. according to universal laws.
  7716. 4th. This philosopher's celebrated doctrine of space and time, in which
  7717. he intellectualized these forms of sensibility, originated in the same
  7718. delusion of transcendental reflection. If I attempt to represent by the
  7719. mere understanding, the external relations of things, I can do so only
  7720. by employing the conception of their reciprocal action, and if I wish
  7721. to connect one state of the same thing with another state, I must avail
  7722. myself of the notion of the order of cause and effect. And thus Leibnitz
  7723. regarded space as a certain order in the community of substances, and
  7724. time as the dynamical sequence of their states. That which space and
  7725. time possess proper to themselves and independent of things, he ascribed
  7726. to a necessary confusion in our conceptions of them, whereby that which
  7727. is a mere form of dynamical relations is held to be a self-existent
  7728. intuition, antecedent even to things themselves. Thus space and time
  7729. were the intelligible form of the connection of things (substances and
  7730. their states) in themselves. But things were intelligible substances
  7731. (substantiae noumena). At the same time, he made these conceptions valid
  7732. of phenomena, because he did not allow to sensibility a peculiar mode of
  7733. intuition, but sought all, even the empirical representation of objects,
  7734. in the understanding, and left to sense naught but the despicable task
  7735. of confusing and disarranging the representations of the former.
  7736. But even if we could frame any synthetical proposition concerning things
  7737. in themselves by means of the pure understanding (which is impossible),
  7738. it could not apply to phenomena, which do not represent things in
  7739. themselves. In such a case I should be obliged in transcendental
  7740. reflection to compare my conceptions only under the conditions of
  7741. sensibility, and so space and time would not be determinations of things
  7742. in themselves, but of phenomena. What things may be in themselves, I
  7743. know not and need not know, because a thing is never presented to me
  7744. otherwise than as a phenomenon.
  7745. I must adopt the same mode of procedure with the other conceptions
  7746. of reflection. Matter is substantia phaenomenon. That in it which is
  7747. internal I seek to discover in all parts of space which it occupies, and
  7748. in all the functions and operations it performs, and which are indeed
  7749. never anything but phenomena of the external sense. I cannot therefore
  7750. find anything that is absolutely, but only what is comparatively
  7751. internal, and which itself consists of external relations. The
  7752. absolutely internal in matter, and as it should be according to the pure
  7753. understanding, is a mere chimera, for matter is not an object for
  7754. the pure understanding. But the transcendental object, which is the
  7755. foundation of the phenomenon which we call matter, is a mere nescio
  7756. quid, the nature of which we could not understand, even though someone
  7757. were found able to tell us. For we can understand nothing that does not
  7758. bring with it something in intuition corresponding to the expressions
  7759. employed. If, by the complaint of being unable to perceive the internal
  7760. nature of things, it is meant that we do not comprehend by the pure
  7761. understanding what the things which appear to us may be in themselves,
  7762. it is a silly and unreasonable complaint; for those who talk thus really
  7763. desire that we should be able to cognize, consequently to intuite,
  7764. things without senses, and therefore wish that we possessed a faculty
  7765. of cognition perfectly different from the human faculty, not merely in
  7766. degree, but even as regards intuition and the mode thereof, so that thus
  7767. we should not be men, but belong to a class of beings, the possibility
  7768. of whose existence, much less their nature and constitution, we have
  7769. no means of cognizing. By observation and analysis of phenomena we
  7770. penetrate into the interior of nature, and no one can say what progress
  7771. this knowledge may make in time. But those transcendental questions
  7772. which pass beyond the limits of nature, we could never answer, even
  7773. although all nature were laid open to us, because we have not the power
  7774. of observing our own mind with any other intuition than that of our
  7775. internal sense. For herein lies the mystery of the origin and source
  7776. of our faculty of sensibility. Its application to an object, and the
  7777. transcendental ground of this unity of subjective and objective, lie too
  7778. deeply concealed for us, who cognize ourselves only through the
  7779. internal sense, consequently as phenomena, to be able to discover in our
  7780. existence anything but phenomena, the non-sensuous cause of which we at
  7781. the same time earnestly desire to penetrate to.
  7782. The great utility of this critique of conclusions arrived at by the
  7783. processes of mere reflection consists in its clear demonstration of the
  7784. nullity of all conclusions respecting objects which are compared
  7785. with each other in the understanding alone, while it at the same time
  7786. confirms what we particularly insisted on, namely, that, although
  7787. phenomena are not included as things in themselves among the objects of
  7788. the pure understanding, they are nevertheless the only things by which
  7789. our cognition can possess objective reality, that is to say, which give
  7790. us intuitions to correspond with our conceptions.
  7791. When we reflect in a purely logical manner, we do nothing more than
  7792. compare conceptions in our understanding, to discover whether both have
  7793. the same content, whether they are self-contradictory or not, whether
  7794. anything is contained in either conception, which of the two is given,
  7795. and which is merely a mode of thinking that given. But if I apply these
  7796. conceptions to an object in general (in the transcendental sense),
  7797. without first determining whether it is an object of sensuous or
  7798. intellectual intuition, certain limitations present themselves, which
  7799. forbid us to pass beyond the conceptions and render all empirical use
  7800. of them impossible. And thus these limitations prove that the
  7801. representation of an object as a thing in general is not only
  7802. insufficient, but, without sensuous determination and independently of
  7803. empirical conditions, self-contradictory; that we must therefore make
  7804. abstraction of all objects, as in logic, or, admitting them, must think
  7805. them under conditions of sensuous intuition; that, consequently, the
  7806. intelligible requires an altogether peculiar intuition, which we do not
  7807. possess, and in the absence of which it is for us nothing; while, on the
  7808. other hand phenomena cannot be objects in themselves. For, when I merely
  7809. think things in general, the difference in their external relations
  7810. cannot constitute a difference in the things themselves; on the
  7811. contrary, the former presupposes the latter, and if the conception of
  7812. one of two things is not internally different from that of the other,
  7813. I am merely thinking the same thing in different relations. Further,
  7814. by the addition of one affirmation (reality) to the other, the positive
  7815. therein is really augmented, and nothing is abstracted or withdrawn
  7816. from it; hence the real in things cannot be in contradiction with or
  7817. opposition to itself--and so on.
  7818. The true use of the conceptions of reflection in the employment of the
  7819. understanding has, as we have shown, been so misconceived by Leibnitz,
  7820. one of the most acute philosophers of either ancient or modern times,
  7821. that he has been misled into the construction of a baseless system of
  7822. intellectual cognition, which professes to determine its objects without
  7823. the intervention of the senses. For this reason, the exposition of the
  7824. cause of the amphiboly of these conceptions, as the origin of these
  7825. false principles, is of great utility in determining with certainty the
  7826. proper limits of the understanding.
  7827. It is right to say whatever is affirmed or denied of the whole of a
  7828. conception can be affirmed or denied of any part of it (dictum de omni
  7829. et nullo); but it would be absurd so to alter this logical proposition
  7830. as to say whatever is not contained in a general conception is likewise
  7831. not contained in the particular conceptions which rank under it; for
  7832. the latter are particular conceptions, for the very reason that
  7833. their content is greater than that which is cogitated in the general
  7834. conception. And yet the whole intellectual system of Leibnitz is based
  7835. upon this false principle, and with it must necessarily fall to the
  7836. ground, together with all the ambiguous principles in reference to the
  7837. employment of the understanding which have thence originated.
  7838. Leibnitz's principle of the identity of indiscernibles or
  7839. indistinguishables is really based on the presupposition that, if in the
  7840. conception of a thing a certain distinction is not to be found, it is
  7841. also not to be met with in things themselves; that, consequently,
  7842. all things are completely identical (numero eadem) which are not
  7843. distinguishable from each other (as to quality or quantity) in our
  7844. conceptions of them. But, as in the mere conception of anything
  7845. abstraction has been made of many necessary conditions of intuition,
  7846. that of which abstraction has been made is rashly held to be
  7847. non-existent, and nothing is attributed to the thing but what is
  7848. contained in its conception.
  7849. The conception of a cubic foot of space, however I may think it, is
  7850. in itself completely identical. But two cubic feet in space are
  7851. nevertheless distinct from each other from the sole fact of their being
  7852. in different places (they are numero diversa); and these places are
  7853. conditions of intuition, wherein the object of this conception is
  7854. given, and which do not belong to the conception, but to the faculty of
  7855. sensibility. In like manner, there is in the conception of a thing no
  7856. contradiction when a negative is not connected with an affirmative;
  7857. and merely affirmative conceptions cannot, in conjunction, produce any
  7858. negation. But in sensuous intuition, wherein reality (take for example,
  7859. motion) is given, we find conditions (opposite directions)--of which
  7860. abstraction has been made in the conception of motion in general--which
  7861. render possible a contradiction or opposition (not indeed of a logical
  7862. kind)--and which from pure positives produce zero = 0. We are therefore
  7863. not justified in saying that all reality is in perfect agreement
  7864. and harmony, because no contradiction is discoverable among its
  7865. conceptions.* According to mere conceptions, that which is internal
  7866. is the substratum of all relations or external determinations. When,
  7867. therefore, I abstract all conditions of intuition, and confine myself
  7868. solely to the conception of a thing in general, I can make abstraction
  7869. of all external relations, and there must nevertheless remain a
  7870. conception of that which indicates no relation, but merely internal
  7871. determinations. Now it seems to follow that in everything (substance)
  7872. there is something which is absolutely internal and which antecedes all
  7873. external determinations, inasmuch as it renders them possible; and
  7874. that therefore this substratum is something which does not contain any
  7875. external relations and is consequently simple (for corporeal things are
  7876. never anything but relations, at least of their parts external to
  7877. each other); and, inasmuch as we know of no other absolutely internal
  7878. determinations than those of the internal sense, this substratum is not
  7879. only simple, but also, analogously with our internal sense, determined
  7880. through representations, that is to say, all things are properly monads,
  7881. or simple beings endowed with the power of representation. Now all this
  7882. would be perfectly correct, if the conception of a thing were the
  7883. only necessary condition of the presentation of objects of external
  7884. intuition. It is, on the contrary, manifest that a permanent phenomenon
  7885. in space (impenetrable extension) can contain mere relations, and
  7886. nothing that is absolutely internal, and yet be the primary substratum
  7887. of all external perception. By mere conceptions I cannot think anything
  7888. external, without, at the same time, thinking something internal, for
  7889. the reason that conceptions of relations presuppose given things, and
  7890. without these are impossible. But, as an intuition there is something
  7891. (that is, space, which, with all it contains, consists of purely formal,
  7892. or, indeed, real relations) which is not found in the mere conception of
  7893. a thing in general, and this presents to us the substratum which could
  7894. not be cognized through conceptions alone, I cannot say: because a thing
  7895. cannot be represented by mere conceptions without something absolutely
  7896. internal, there is also, in the things themselves which are contained
  7897. under these conceptions, and in their intuition nothing external to
  7898. which something absolutely internal does not serve as the foundation.
  7899. For, when we have made abstraction of all the conditions of intuition,
  7900. there certainly remains in the mere conception nothing but the internal
  7901. in general, through which alone the external is possible. But this
  7902. necessity, which is grounded upon abstraction alone, does not obtain in
  7903. the case of things themselves, in so far as they are given in intuition
  7904. with such determinations as express mere relations, without having
  7905. anything internal as their foundation; for they are not things of a
  7906. thing of which we can neither for they are not things in themselves, but
  7907. only phenomena. What we cognize in matter is nothing but relations (what
  7908. we call its internal determinations are but comparatively internal). But
  7909. there are some self-subsistent and permanent, through which a determined
  7910. object is given. That I, when abstraction is made of these relations,
  7911. have nothing more to think, does not destroy the conception of a thing
  7912. as phenomenon, nor the conception of an object in abstracto, but it does
  7913. away with the possibility of an object that is determinable according to
  7914. mere conceptions, that is, of a noumenon. It is certainly startling to
  7915. hear that a thing consists solely of relations; but this thing is simply
  7916. a phenomenon, and cannot be cogitated by means of the mere categories:
  7917. it does itself consist in the mere relation of something in general to
  7918. the senses. In the same way, we cannot cogitate relations of things in
  7919. abstracto, if we commence with conceptions alone, in any other manner
  7920. than that one is the cause of determinations in the other; for that is
  7921. itself the conception of the understanding or category of relation. But,
  7922. as in this case we make abstraction of all intuition, we lose altogether
  7923. the mode in which the manifold determines to each of its parts its
  7924. place, that is, the form of sensibility (space); and yet this mode
  7925. antecedes all empirical causality.
  7926. [*Footnote: If any one wishes here to have recourse to the usual
  7927. subterfuge, and to say, that at least realitates noumena cannot be in
  7928. opposition to each other, it will be requisite for him to adduce an
  7929. example of this pure and non-sensuous reality, that it may be understood
  7930. whether the notion represents something or nothing. But an example
  7931. cannot be found except in experience, which never presents to us
  7932. anything more than phenomena; and thus the proposition means nothing
  7933. more than that the conception which contains only affirmatives does not
  7934. contain anything negative--a proposition nobody ever doubted.]
  7935. If by intelligible objects we understand things which can be thought
  7936. by means of the pure categories, without the need of the schemata of
  7937. sensibility, such objects are impossible. For the condition of the
  7938. objective use of all our conceptions of understanding is the mode of
  7939. our sensuous intuition, whereby objects are given; and, if we make
  7940. abstraction of the latter, the former can have no relation to an object.
  7941. And even if we should suppose a different kind of intuition from our
  7942. own, still our functions of thought would have no use or signification
  7943. in respect thereof. But if we understand by the term, objects of a
  7944. non-sensuous intuition, in respect of which our categories are not
  7945. valid, and of which we can accordingly have no knowledge (neither
  7946. intuition nor conception), in this merely negative sense noumena must be
  7947. admitted. For this is no more than saying that our mode of intuition is
  7948. not applicable to all things, but only to objects of our senses,
  7949. that consequently its objective validity is limited, and that room is
  7950. therefore left for another kind of intuition, and thus also for things
  7951. that may be objects of it. But in this sense the conception of a
  7952. noumenon is problematical, that is to say, it is the notion of that it
  7953. that it is possible, nor that it is impossible, inasmuch as we do not
  7954. know of any mode of intuition besides the sensuous, or of any other sort
  7955. of conceptions than the categories--a mode of intuition and a kind of
  7956. conception neither of which is applicable to a non-sensuous object. We
  7957. are on this account incompetent to extend the sphere of our objects
  7958. of thought beyond the conditions of our sensibility, and to assume the
  7959. existence of objects of pure thought, that is, of noumena, inasmuch as
  7960. these have no true positive signification. For it must be confessed
  7961. of the categories that they are not of themselves sufficient for the
  7962. cognition of things in themselves and, without the data of sensibility,
  7963. are mere subjective forms of the unity of the understanding. Thought is
  7964. certainly not a product of the senses, and in so far is not limited by
  7965. them, but it does not therefore follow that it may be employed purely
  7966. and without the intervention of sensibility, for it would then be
  7967. without reference to an object. And we cannot call a noumenon an object
  7968. of pure thought; for the representation thereof is but the problematical
  7969. conception of an object for a perfectly different intuition and
  7970. a perfectly different understanding from ours, both of which are
  7971. consequently themselves problematical. The conception of a noumenon is
  7972. therefore not the conception of an object, but merely a problematical
  7973. conception inseparably connected with the limitation of our sensibility.
  7974. That is to say, this conception contains the answer to the question:
  7975. "Are there objects quite unconnected with, and independent of, our
  7976. intuition?"--a question to which only an indeterminate answer can be
  7977. given. That answer is: "Inasmuch as sensuous intuition does not apply
  7978. to all things without distinction, there remains room for other and
  7979. different objects." The existence of these problematical objects
  7980. is therefore not absolutely denied, in the absence of a determinate
  7981. conception of them, but, as no category is valid in respect of them,
  7982. neither must they be admitted as objects for our understanding.
  7983. Understanding accordingly limits sensibility, without at the same time
  7984. enlarging its own field. While, moreover, it forbids sensibility to
  7985. apply its forms and modes to things in themselves and restricts it
  7986. to the sphere of phenomena, it cogitates an object in itself, only,
  7987. however, as a transcendental object, which is the cause of a phenomenon
  7988. (consequently not itself a phenomenon), and which cannot be thought
  7989. either as a quantity or as reality, or as substance (because these
  7990. conceptions always require sensuous forms in which to determine an
  7991. object)--an object, therefore, of which we are quite unable to say
  7992. whether it can be met with in ourselves or out of us, whether it would
  7993. be annihilated together with sensibility, or, if this were taken away,
  7994. would continue to exist. If we wish to call this object a noumenon,
  7995. because the representation of it is non-sensuous, we are at liberty
  7996. to do so. But as we can apply to it none of the conceptions of our
  7997. understanding, the representation is for us quite void, and is available
  7998. only for the indication of the limits of our sensuous intuition, thereby
  7999. leaving at the same time an empty space, which we are competent to
  8000. fill by the aid neither of possible experience, nor of the pure
  8001. understanding.
  8002. The critique of the pure understanding, accordingly, does not permit us
  8003. to create for ourselves a new field of objects beyond those which are
  8004. presented to us as phenomena, and to stray into intelligible worlds;
  8005. nay, it does not even allow us to endeavour to form so much as a
  8006. conception of them. The specious error which leads to this--and which is
  8007. a perfectly excusable one--lies in the fact that the employment of the
  8008. understanding, contrary to its proper purpose and destination, is made
  8009. transcendental, and objects, that is, possible intuitions, are made to
  8010. regulate themselves according to conceptions, instead of the conceptions
  8011. arranging themselves according to the intuitions, on which alone their
  8012. own objective validity rests. Now the reason of this again is that
  8013. apperception, and with it thought, antecedes all possible determinate
  8014. arrangement of representations. Accordingly we think something in
  8015. general and determine it on the one hand sensuously, but, on the other,
  8016. distinguish the general and in abstracto represented object from this
  8017. particular mode of intuiting it. In this case there remains a mode of
  8018. determining the object by mere thought, which is really but a logical
  8019. form without content, which, however, seems to us to be a mode of
  8020. the existence of the object in itself (noumenon), without regard to
  8021. intuition which is limited to our senses.
  8022. Before ending this transcendental analytic, we must make an addition,
  8023. which, although in itself of no particular importance, seems to be
  8024. necessary to the completeness of the system. The highest conception,
  8025. with which a transcendental philosophy commonly begins, is the division
  8026. into possible and impossible. But as all division presupposes a divided
  8027. conception, a still higher one must exist, and this is the conception of
  8028. an object in general--problematically understood and without its being
  8029. decided whether it is something or nothing. As the categories are the
  8030. only conceptions which apply to objects in general, the distinguishing
  8031. of an object, whether it is something or nothing, must proceed according
  8032. to the order and direction of the categories.
  8033. 1. To the categories of quantity, that is, the conceptions of all, many,
  8034. and one, the conception which annihilates all, that is, the conception
  8035. of none, is opposed. And thus the object of a conception, to which no
  8036. intuition can be found to correspond, is = nothing. That is, it is a
  8037. conception without an object (ens rationis), like noumena, which cannot
  8038. be considered possible in the sphere of reality, though they must not
  8039. therefore be held to be impossible--or like certain new fundamental
  8040. forces in matter, the existence of which is cogitable without
  8041. contradiction, though, as examples from experience are not forthcoming,
  8042. they must not be regarded as possible.
  8043. 2. Reality is something; negation is nothing, that is, a conception of
  8044. the absence of an object, as cold, a shadow (nihil privativum).
  8045. 3. The mere form of intuition, without substance, is in itself no
  8046. object, but the merely formal condition of an object (as phenomenon),
  8047. as pure space and pure time. These are certainly something, as forms
  8048. of intuition, but are not themselves objects which are intuited (ens
  8049. imaginarium).
  8050. 4. The object of a conception which is self-contradictory, is nothing,
  8051. because the conception is nothing--is impossible, as a figure composed
  8052. of two straight lines (nihil negativum).
  8053. The table of this division of the conception of nothing (the
  8054. corresponding division of the conception of something does not require
  8055. special description) must therefore be arranged as follows:
  8056. NOTHING
  8057. AS
  8058. 1
  8059. As Empty Conception
  8060. without object,
  8061. ens rationis
  8062. 2 3
  8063. Empty object of Empty intuition
  8064. a conception, without object,
  8065. nihil privativum ens imaginarium
  8066. 4
  8067. Empty object
  8068. without conception,
  8069. nihil negativum
  8070. We see that the ens rationis is distinguished from the nihil negativum
  8071. or pure nothing by the consideration that the former must not be
  8072. reckoned among possibilities, because it is a mere fiction--though
  8073. not self-contradictory, while the latter is completely opposed to
  8074. all possibility, inasmuch as the conception annihilates itself. Both,
  8075. however, are empty conceptions. On the other hand, the nihil privativum
  8076. and ens imaginarium are empty data for conceptions. If light be not
  8077. given to the senses, we cannot represent to ourselves darkness, and if
  8078. extended objects are not perceived, we cannot represent space. Neither
  8079. the negation, nor the mere form of intuition can, without something
  8080. real, be an object.
  8081. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC. SECOND DIVISION.
  8082. TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. INTRODUCTION.
  8083. I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance.
  8084. We termed dialectic in general a logic of appearance. This does not
  8085. signify a doctrine of probability; for probability is truth, only
  8086. cognized upon insufficient grounds, and though the information it gives
  8087. us is imperfect, it is not therefore deceitful. Hence it must not be
  8088. separated from the analytical part of logic. Still less must phenomenon
  8089. and appearance be held to be identical. For truth or illusory appearance
  8090. does not reside in the object, in so far as it is intuited, but in the
  8091. judgement upon the object, in so far as it is thought. It is, therefore,
  8092. quite correct to say that the senses do not err, not because they always
  8093. judge correctly, but because they do not judge at all. Hence truth and
  8094. error, consequently also, illusory appearance as the cause of error, are
  8095. only to be found in a judgement, that is, in the relation of an object
  8096. to our understanding. In a cognition which completely harmonizes with
  8097. the laws of the understanding, no error can exist. In a representation
  8098. of the senses--as not containing any judgement--there is also no error.
  8099. But no power of nature can of itself deviate from its own laws. Hence
  8100. neither the understanding per se (without the influence of another
  8101. cause), nor the senses per se, would fall into error; the former could
  8102. not, because, if it acts only according to its own laws, the effect (the
  8103. judgement) must necessarily accord with these laws. But in accordance
  8104. with the laws of the understanding consists the formal element in all
  8105. truth. In the senses there is no judgement--neither a true nor a false
  8106. one. But, as we have no source of cognition besides these two, it
  8107. follows that error is caused solely by the unobserved influence of
  8108. the sensibility upon the understanding. And thus it happens that the
  8109. subjective grounds of a judgement and are confounded with the objective,
  8110. and cause them to deviate from their proper determination,* just as a
  8111. body in motion would always of itself proceed in a straight line, but
  8112. if another impetus gives to it a different direction, it will then
  8113. start off into a curvilinear line of motion. To distinguish the peculiar
  8114. action of the understanding from the power which mingles with it, it is
  8115. necessary to consider an erroneous judgement as the diagonal between two
  8116. forces, that determine the judgement in two different directions, which,
  8117. as it were, form an angle, and to resolve this composite operation into
  8118. the simple ones of the understanding and the sensibility. In pure
  8119. a priori judgements this must be done by means of transcendental
  8120. reflection, whereby, as has been already shown, each representation
  8121. has its place appointed in the corresponding faculty of cognition, and
  8122. consequently the influence of the one faculty upon the other is made
  8123. apparent.
  8124. [*Footnote: Sensibility, subjected to the understanding, as the object
  8125. upon which the understanding employs its functions, is the source of
  8126. real cognitions. But, in so far as it exercises an influence upon the
  8127. action of the understanding and determines it to judgement, sensibility
  8128. is itself the cause of error.]
  8129. It is not at present our business to treat of empirical illusory
  8130. appearance (for example, optical illusion), which occurs in the
  8131. empirical application of otherwise correct rules of the understanding,
  8132. and in which the judgement is misled by the influence of imagination.
  8133. Our purpose is to speak of transcendental illusory appearance, which
  8134. influences principles--that are not even applied to experience, for in
  8135. this case we should possess a sure test of their correctness--but which
  8136. leads us, in disregard of all the warnings of criticism, completely
  8137. beyond the empirical employment of the categories and deludes us with
  8138. the chimera of an extension of the sphere of the pure understanding.
  8139. We shall term those principles the application of which is confined
  8140. entirely within the limits of possible experience, immanent; those,
  8141. on the other hand, which transgress these limits, we shall call
  8142. transcendent principles. But by these latter I do not understand
  8143. principles of the transcendental use or misuse of the categories, which
  8144. is in reality a mere fault of the judgement when not under due restraint
  8145. from criticism, and therefore not paying sufficient attention to the
  8146. limits of the sphere in which the pure understanding is allowed to
  8147. exercise its functions; but real principles which exhort us to break
  8148. down all those barriers, and to lay claim to a perfectly new field of
  8149. cognition, which recognizes no line of demarcation. Thus transcendental
  8150. and transcendent are not identical terms. The principles of the
  8151. pure understanding, which we have already propounded, ought to be
  8152. of empirical and not of transcendental use, that is, they are not
  8153. applicable to any object beyond the sphere of experience. A principle
  8154. which removes these limits, nay, which authorizes us to overstep them,
  8155. is called transcendent. If our criticism can succeed in exposing the
  8156. illusion in these pretended principles, those which are limited in their
  8157. employment to the sphere of experience may be called, in opposition to
  8158. the others, immanent principles of the pure understanding.
  8159. Logical illusion, which consists merely in the imitation of the form of
  8160. reason (the illusion in sophistical syllogisms), arises entirely from
  8161. a want of due attention to logical rules. So soon as the attention
  8162. is awakened to the case before us, this illusion totally disappears.
  8163. Transcendental illusion, on the contrary, does not cease to exist, even
  8164. after it has been exposed, and its nothingness clearly perceived by
  8165. means of transcendental criticism. Take, for example, the illusion in
  8166. the proposition: "The world must have a beginning in time." The cause of
  8167. this is as follows. In our reason, subjectively considered as a faculty
  8168. of human cognition, there exist fundamental rules and maxims of its
  8169. exercise, which have completely the appearance of objective principles.
  8170. Now from this cause it happens that the subjective necessity of a
  8171. certain connection of our conceptions, is regarded as an objective
  8172. necessity of the determination of things in themselves. This illusion it
  8173. is impossible to avoid, just as we cannot avoid perceiving that the sea
  8174. appears to be higher at a distance than it is near the shore, because we
  8175. see the former by means of higher rays than the latter, or, which is a
  8176. still stronger case, as even the astronomer cannot prevent himself from
  8177. seeing the moon larger at its rising than some time afterwards, although
  8178. he is not deceived by this illusion.
  8179. Transcendental dialectic will therefore content itself with exposing
  8180. the illusory appearance in transcendental judgements, and guarding us
  8181. against it; but to make it, as in the case of logical illusion, entirely
  8182. disappear and cease to be illusion is utterly beyond its power. For we
  8183. have here to do with a natural and unavoidable illusion, which rests
  8184. upon subjective principles and imposes these upon us as objective, while
  8185. logical dialectic, in the detection of sophisms, has to do merely with
  8186. an error in the logical consequence of the propositions, or with an
  8187. artificially constructed illusion, in imitation of the natural error.
  8188. There is, therefore, a natural and unavoidable dialectic of pure
  8189. reason--not that in which the bungler, from want of the requisite
  8190. knowledge, involves himself, nor that which the sophist devises for the
  8191. purpose of misleading, but that which is an inseparable adjunct of human
  8192. reason, and which, even after its illusions have been exposed, does not
  8193. cease to deceive, and continually to lead reason into momentary errors,
  8194. which it becomes necessary continually to remove.
  8195. II. Of Pure Reason as the Seat of Transcendental Illusory Appearance.
  8196. A. OF REASON IN GENERAL.
  8197. All our knowledge begins with sense, proceeds thence to understanding,
  8198. and ends with reason, beyond which nothing higher can be discovered in
  8199. the human mind for elaborating the matter of intuition and subjecting it
  8200. to the highest unity of thought. At this stage of our inquiry it is my
  8201. duty to give an explanation of this, the highest faculty of cognition,
  8202. and I confess I find myself here in some difficulty. Of reason, as of
  8203. the understanding, there is a merely formal, that is, logical use, in
  8204. which it makes abstraction of all content of cognition; but there is
  8205. also a real use, inasmuch as it contains in itself the source of certain
  8206. conceptions and principles, which it does not borrow either from the
  8207. senses or the understanding. The former faculty has been long defined by
  8208. logicians as the faculty of mediate conclusion in contradistinction to
  8209. immediate conclusions (consequentiae immediatae); but the nature of the
  8210. latter, which itself generates conceptions, is not to be understood
  8211. from this definition. Now as a division of reason into a logical and
  8212. a transcendental faculty presents itself here, it becomes necessary to
  8213. seek for a higher conception of this source of cognition which shall
  8214. comprehend both conceptions. In this we may expect, according to the
  8215. analogy of the conceptions of the understanding, that the logical
  8216. conception will give us the key to the transcendental, and that the
  8217. table of the functions of the former will present us with the clue to
  8218. the conceptions of reason.
  8219. In the former part of our transcendental logic, we defined the
  8220. understanding to be the faculty of rules; reason may be distinguished
  8221. from understanding as the faculty of principles.
  8222. The term principle is ambiguous, and commonly signifies merely a
  8223. cognition that may be employed as a principle, although it is not in
  8224. itself, and as regards its proper origin, entitled to the distinction.
  8225. Every general proposition, even if derived from experience by the
  8226. process of induction, may serve as the major in a syllogism; but it is
  8227. not for that reason a principle. Mathematical axioms (for example, there
  8228. can be only one straight line between two points) are general a priori
  8229. cognitions, and are therefore rightly denominated principles, relatively
  8230. to the cases which can be subsumed under them. But I cannot for
  8231. this reason say that I cognize this property of a straight line from
  8232. principles--I cognize it only in pure intuition.
  8233. Cognition from principles, then, is that cognition in which I cognize
  8234. the particular in the general by means of conceptions. Thus every
  8235. syllogism is a form of the deduction of a cognition from a principle.
  8236. For the major always gives a conception, through which everything that
  8237. is subsumed under the condition thereof is cognized according to a
  8238. principle. Now as every general cognition may serve as the major in a
  8239. syllogism, and the understanding presents us with such general a
  8240. priori propositions, they may be termed principles, in respect of their
  8241. possible use.
  8242. But if we consider these principles of the pure understanding in
  8243. relation to their origin, we shall find them to be anything rather
  8244. than cognitions from conceptions. For they would not even be possible
  8245. a priori, if we could not rely on the assistance of pure intuition (in
  8246. mathematics), or on that of the conditions of a possible experience.
  8247. That everything that happens has a cause, cannot be concluded from the
  8248. general conception of that which happens; on the contrary the principle
  8249. of causality instructs us as to the mode of obtaining from that which
  8250. happens a determinate empirical conception.
  8251. Synthetical cognitions from conceptions the understanding cannot supply,
  8252. and they alone are entitled to be called principles. At the same time,
  8253. all general propositions may be termed comparative principles.
  8254. It has been a long-cherished wish--that (who knows how late), may one
  8255. day, be happily accomplished--that the principles of the endless variety
  8256. of civil laws should be investigated and exposed; for in this way alone
  8257. can we find the secret of simplifying legislation. But in this case,
  8258. laws are nothing more than limitations of our freedom upon conditions
  8259. under which it subsists in perfect harmony with itself; they
  8260. consequently have for their object that which is completely our own
  8261. work, and of which we ourselves may be the cause by means of these
  8262. conceptions. But how objects as things in themselves--how the nature of
  8263. things is subordinated to principles and is to be determined, according
  8264. to conceptions, is a question which it seems well nigh impossible to
  8265. answer. Be this, however, as it may--for on this point our investigation
  8266. is yet to be made--it is at least manifest from what we have said that
  8267. cognition from principles is something very different from cognition by
  8268. means of the understanding, which may indeed precede other cognitions
  8269. in the form of a principle, but in itself--in so far as it is
  8270. synthetical--is neither based upon mere thought, nor contains a general
  8271. proposition drawn from conceptions alone.
  8272. The understanding may be a faculty for the production of unity of
  8273. phenomena by virtue of rules; the reason is a faculty for the production
  8274. of unity of rules (of the understanding) under principles. Reason,
  8275. therefore, never applies directly to experience, or to any sensuous
  8276. object; its object is, on the contrary, the understanding, to the
  8277. manifold cognition of which it gives a unity a priori by means of
  8278. conceptions--a unity which may be called rational unity, and which is
  8279. of a nature very different from that of the unity produced by the
  8280. understanding.
  8281. The above is the general conception of the faculty of reason, in so
  8282. far as it has been possible to make it comprehensible in the absence of
  8283. examples. These will be given in the sequel.
  8284. B. OF THE LOGICAL USE OF REASON.
  8285. A distinction is commonly made between that which is immediately
  8286. cognized and that which is inferred or concluded. That in a figure
  8287. which is bounded by three straight lines there are three angles, is an
  8288. immediate cognition; but that these angles are together equal to two
  8289. right angles, is an inference or conclusion. Now, as we are constantly
  8290. employing this mode of thought and have thus become quite accustomed to
  8291. it, we no longer remark the above distinction, and, as in the case of
  8292. the so-called deceptions of sense, consider as immediately perceived,
  8293. what has really been inferred. In every reasoning or syllogism, there
  8294. is a fundamental proposition, afterwards a second drawn from it, and
  8295. finally the conclusion, which connects the truth in the first with the
  8296. truth in the second--and that infallibly. If the judgement concluded
  8297. is so contained in the first proposition that it can be deduced from
  8298. it without the meditation of a third notion, the conclusion is called
  8299. immediate (consequentia immediata); I prefer the term conclusion of
  8300. the understanding. But if, in addition to the fundamental cognition, a
  8301. second judgement is necessary for the production of the conclusion, it
  8302. is called a conclusion of the reason. In the proposition: All men are
  8303. mortal, are contained the propositions: Some men are mortal, Nothing
  8304. that is not mortal is a man, and these are therefore immediate
  8305. conclusions from the first. On the other hand, the proposition: all the
  8306. learned are mortal, is not contained in the main proposition (for the
  8307. conception of a learned man does not occur in it), and it can be deduced
  8308. from the main proposition only by means of a mediating judgement.
  8309. In every syllogism I first cogitate a rule (the major) by means of
  8310. the understanding. In the next place I subsume a cognition under the
  8311. condition of the rule (and this is the minor) by means of the judgement.
  8312. And finally I determine my cognition by means of the predicate of the
  8313. rule (this is the conclusio), consequently, I determine it a priori
  8314. by means of the reason. The relations, therefore, which the major
  8315. proposition, as the rule, represents between a cognition and its
  8316. condition, constitute the different kinds of syllogisms. These are just
  8317. threefold--analogously with all judgements, in so far as they differ
  8318. in the mode of expressing the relation of a cognition in the
  8319. understanding--namely, categorical, hypothetical, and disjunctive.
  8320. When as often happens, the conclusion is a judgement which may follow
  8321. from other given judgements, through which a perfectly different object
  8322. is cogitated, I endeavour to discover in the understanding whether the
  8323. assertion in this conclusion does not stand under certain conditions
  8324. according to a general rule. If I find such a condition, and if the
  8325. object mentioned in the conclusion can be subsumed under the given
  8326. condition, then this conclusion follows from a rule which is also valid
  8327. for other objects of cognition. From this we see that reason endeavours
  8328. to subject the great variety of the cognitions of the understanding to
  8329. the smallest possible number of principles (general conditions), and
  8330. thus to produce in it the highest unity.
  8331. C. OF THE PURE USE OF REASON.
  8332. Can we isolate reason, and, if so, is it in this case a peculiar source
  8333. of conceptions and judgements which spring from it alone, and through
  8334. which it can be applied to objects; or is it merely a subordinate
  8335. faculty, whose duty it is to give a certain form to given cognitions--a
  8336. form which is called logical, and through which the cognitions of the
  8337. understanding are subordinated to each other, and lower rules to higher
  8338. (those, to wit, whose condition comprises in its sphere the condition
  8339. of the others), in so far as this can be done by comparison? This is the
  8340. question which we have at present to answer. Manifold variety of rules
  8341. and unity of principles is a requirement of reason, for the purpose of
  8342. bringing the understanding into complete accordance with itself, just as
  8343. understanding subjects the manifold content of intuition to conceptions,
  8344. and thereby introduces connection into it. But this principle prescribes
  8345. no law to objects, and does not contain any ground of the possibility of
  8346. cognizing or of determining them as such, but is merely a subjective
  8347. law for the proper arrangement of the content of the understanding.
  8348. The purpose of this law is, by a comparison of the conceptions of the
  8349. understanding, to reduce them to the smallest possible number, although,
  8350. at the same time, it does not justify us in demanding from objects
  8351. themselves such a uniformity as might contribute to the convenience and
  8352. the enlargement of the sphere of the understanding, or in expecting that
  8353. it will itself thus receive from them objective validity. In one word,
  8354. the question is: "does reason in itself, that is, does pure reason
  8355. contain a priori synthetical principles and rules, and what are those
  8356. principles?"
  8357. The formal and logical procedure of reason in syllogisms gives
  8358. us sufficient information in regard to the ground on which the
  8359. transcendental principle of reason in its pure synthetical cognition
  8360. will rest.
  8361. 1. Reason, as observed in the syllogistic process, is not applicable to
  8362. intuitions, for the purpose of subjecting them to rules--for this is the
  8363. province of the understanding with its categories--but to conceptions
  8364. and judgements. If pure reason does apply to objects and the intuition
  8365. of them, it does so not immediately, but mediately--through the
  8366. understanding and its judgements, which have a direct relation to
  8367. the senses and their intuition, for the purpose of determining their
  8368. objects. The unity of reason is therefore not the unity of a possible
  8369. experience, but is essentially different from this unity, which is that
  8370. of the understanding. That everything which happens has a cause, is not
  8371. a principle cognized and prescribed by reason. This principle makes the
  8372. unity of experience possible and borrows nothing from reason, which,
  8373. without a reference to possible experience, could never have produced by
  8374. means of mere conceptions any such synthetical unity.
  8375. 2. Reason, in its logical use, endeavours to discover the general
  8376. condition of its judgement (the conclusion), and a syllogism is itself
  8377. nothing but a judgement by means of the subsumption of its condition
  8378. under a general rule (the major). Now as this rule may itself be
  8379. subjected to the same process of reason, and thus the condition of the
  8380. condition be sought (by means of a prosyllogism) as long as the process
  8381. can be continued, it is very manifest that the peculiar principle of
  8382. reason in its logical use is to find for the conditioned cognition of
  8383. the understanding the unconditioned whereby the unity of the former is
  8384. completed.
  8385. But this logical maxim cannot be a principle of pure reason, unless we
  8386. admit that, if the conditioned is given, the whole series of conditions
  8387. subordinated to one another--a series which is consequently itself
  8388. unconditioned--is also given, that is, contained in the object and its
  8389. connection.
  8390. But this principle of pure reason is evidently synthetical; for,
  8391. analytically, the conditioned certainly relates to some condition, but
  8392. not to the unconditioned. From this principle also there must originate
  8393. different synthetical propositions, of which the pure understanding is
  8394. perfectly ignorant, for it has to do only with objects of a possible
  8395. experience, the cognition and synthesis of which is always conditioned.
  8396. The unconditioned, if it does really exist, must be especially
  8397. considered in regard to the determinations which distinguish it from
  8398. whatever is conditioned, and will thus afford us material for many a
  8399. priori synthetical propositions.
  8400. The principles resulting from this highest principle of pure reason
  8401. will, however, be transcendent in relation to phenomena, that is to
  8402. say, it will be impossible to make any adequate empirical use of this
  8403. principle. It is therefore completely different from all principles of
  8404. the understanding, the use made of which is entirely immanent, their
  8405. object and purpose being merely the possibility of experience. Now our
  8406. duty in the transcendental dialectic is as follows. To discover whether
  8407. the principle that the series of conditions (in the synthesis of
  8408. phenomena, or of thought in general) extends to the unconditioned is
  8409. objectively true, or not; what consequences result therefrom affecting
  8410. the empirical use of the understanding, or rather whether there exists
  8411. any such objectively valid proposition of reason, and whether it is not,
  8412. on the contrary, a merely logical precept which directs us to ascend
  8413. perpetually to still higher conditions, to approach completeness in the
  8414. series of them, and thus to introduce into our cognition the highest
  8415. possible unity of reason. We must ascertain, I say, whether this
  8416. requirement of reason has not been regarded, by a misunderstanding, as
  8417. a transcendental principle of pure reason, which postulates a thorough
  8418. completeness in the series of conditions in objects themselves. We
  8419. must show, moreover, the misconceptions and illusions that intrude into
  8420. syllogisms, the major proposition of which pure reason has supplied--a
  8421. proposition which has perhaps more of the character of a petitio than
  8422. of a postulatum--and that proceed from experience upwards to its
  8423. conditions. The solution of these problems is our task in transcendental
  8424. dialectic, which we are about to expose even at its source, that lies
  8425. deep in human reason. We shall divide it into two parts, the first of
  8426. which will treat of the transcendent conceptions of pure reason, the
  8427. second of transcendent and dialectical syllogisms.
  8428. BOOK I. -- OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON.
  8429. The conceptions of pure reason--we do not here speak of the possibility
  8430. of them--are not obtained by reflection, but by inference or
  8431. conclusion. The conceptions of understanding are also cogitated a priori
  8432. antecedently to experience, and render it possible; but they contain
  8433. nothing but the unity of reflection upon phenomena, in so far as these
  8434. must necessarily belong to a possible empirical consciousness. Through
  8435. them alone are cognition and the determination of an object possible. It
  8436. is from them, accordingly, that we receive material for reasoning, and
  8437. antecedently to them we possess no a priori conceptions of objects from
  8438. which they might be deduced, On the other hand, the sole basis of
  8439. their objective reality consists in the necessity imposed on them, as
  8440. containing the intellectual form of all experience, of restricting their
  8441. application and influence to the sphere of experience.
  8442. But the term, conception of reason, or rational conception, itself
  8443. indicates that it does not confine itself within the limits of
  8444. experience, because its object-matter is a cognition, of which every
  8445. empirical cognition is but a part--nay, the whole of possible experience
  8446. may be itself but a part of it--a cognition to which no actual
  8447. experience ever fully attains, although it does always pertain to it.
  8448. The aim of rational conceptions is the comprehension, as that of the
  8449. conceptions of understanding is the understanding of perceptions.
  8450. If they contain the unconditioned, they relate to that to which all
  8451. experience is subordinate, but which is never itself an object of
  8452. experience--that towards which reason tends in all its conclusions from
  8453. experience, and by the standard of which it estimates the degree
  8454. of their empirical use, but which is never itself an element in an
  8455. empirical synthesis. If, notwithstanding, such conceptions possess
  8456. objective validity, they may be called conceptus ratiocinati
  8457. (conceptions legitimately concluded); in cases where they do not,
  8458. they have been admitted on account of having the appearance of
  8459. being correctly concluded, and may be called conceptus ratiocinantes
  8460. (sophistical conceptions). But as this can only be sufficiently
  8461. demonstrated in that part of our treatise which relates to the
  8462. dialectical conclusions of reason, we shall omit any consideration of
  8463. it in this place. As we called the pure conceptions of the understanding
  8464. categories, we shall also distinguish those of pure reason by a new name
  8465. and call them transcendental ideas. These terms, however, we must in the
  8466. first place explain and justify.
  8467. SECTION I--Of Ideas in General.
  8468. Despite the great wealth of words which European languages possess, the
  8469. thinker finds himself often at a loss for an expression exactly suited
  8470. to his conception, for want of which he is unable to make himself
  8471. intelligible either to others or to himself. To coin new words is a
  8472. pretension to legislation in language which is seldom successful; and,
  8473. before recourse is taken to so desperate an expedient, it is advisable
  8474. to examine the dead and learned languages, with the hope and the
  8475. probability that we may there meet with some adequate expression of the
  8476. notion we have in our minds. In this case, even if the original meaning
  8477. of the word has become somewhat uncertain, from carelessness or want of
  8478. caution on the part of the authors of it, it is always better to adhere
  8479. to and confirm its proper meaning--even although it may be doubtful
  8480. whether it was formerly used in exactly this sense--than to make our
  8481. labour vain by want of sufficient care to render ourselves intelligible.
  8482. For this reason, when it happens that there exists only a single word to
  8483. express a certain conception, and this word, in its usual acceptation,
  8484. is thoroughly adequate to the conception, the accurate distinction of
  8485. which from related conceptions is of great importance, we ought not to
  8486. employ the expression improvidently, or, for the sake of variety and
  8487. elegance of style, use it as a synonym for other cognate words. It
  8488. is our duty, on the contrary, carefully to preserve its peculiar
  8489. signification, as otherwise it easily happens that when the attention of
  8490. the reader is no longer particularly attracted to the expression, and it
  8491. is lost amid the multitude of other words of very different import, the
  8492. thought which it conveyed, and which it alone conveyed, is lost with it.
  8493. Plato employed the expression idea in a way that plainly showed he meant
  8494. by it something which is never derived from the senses, but which
  8495. far transcends even the conceptions of the understanding (with which
  8496. Aristotle occupied himself), inasmuch as in experience nothing perfectly
  8497. corresponding to them could be found. Ideas are, according to him,
  8498. archetypes of things themselves, and not merely keys to possible
  8499. experiences, like the categories. In his view they flow from the
  8500. highest reason, by which they have been imparted to human reason, which,
  8501. however, exists no longer in its original state, but is obliged with
  8502. great labour to recall by reminiscence--which is called philosophy--the
  8503. old but now sadly obscured ideas. I will not here enter upon any
  8504. literary investigation of the sense which this sublime philosopher
  8505. attached to this expression. I shall content myself with remarking that
  8506. it is nothing unusual, in common conversation as well as in written
  8507. works, by comparing the thoughts which an author has delivered upon a
  8508. subject, to understand him better than he understood himself inasmuch
  8509. as he may not have sufficiently determined his conception, and thus have
  8510. sometimes spoken, nay even thought, in opposition to his own opinions.
  8511. Plato perceived very clearly that our faculty of cognition has the
  8512. feeling of a much higher vocation than that of merely spelling out
  8513. phenomena according to synthetical unity, for the purpose of being able
  8514. to read them as experience, and that our reason naturally raises itself
  8515. to cognitions far too elevated to admit of the possibility of an
  8516. object given by experience corresponding to them--cognitions which are
  8517. nevertheless real, and are not mere phantoms of the brain.
  8518. This philosopher found his ideas especially in all that is practical,*
  8519. that is, which rests upon freedom, which in its turn ranks under
  8520. cognitions that are the peculiar product of reason. He who would derive
  8521. from experience the conceptions of virtue, who would make (as many
  8522. have really done) that, which at best can but serve as an imperfectly
  8523. illustrative example, a model for or the formation of a perfectly
  8524. adequate idea on the subject, would in fact transform virtue into a
  8525. nonentity changeable according to time and circumstance and utterly
  8526. incapable of being employed as a rule. On the contrary, every one is
  8527. conscious that, when any one is held up to him as a model of virtue, he
  8528. compares this so-called model with the true original which he possesses
  8529. in his own mind and values him according to this standard. But this
  8530. standard is the idea of virtue, in relation to which all possible
  8531. objects of experience are indeed serviceable as examples--proofs of
  8532. the practicability in a certain degree of that which the conception of
  8533. virtue demands--but certainly not as archetypes. That the actions of
  8534. man will never be in perfect accordance with all the requirements of the
  8535. pure ideas of reason, does not prove the thought to be chimerical. For
  8536. only through this idea are all judgements as to moral merit or demerit
  8537. possible; it consequently lies at the foundation of every approach to
  8538. moral perfection, however far removed from it the obstacles in human
  8539. nature--indeterminable as to degree--may keep us.
  8540. [*Footnote: He certainly extended the application of his conception
  8541. to speculative cognitions also, provided they were given pure and
  8542. completely a priori, nay, even to mathematics, although this science
  8543. cannot possess an object otherwhere than in Possible experience.
  8544. I cannot follow him in this, and as little can I follow him in his
  8545. mystical deduction of these ideas, or in his hypostatization of them;
  8546. although, in truth, the elevated and exaggerated language which he
  8547. employed in describing them is quite capable of an interpretation more
  8548. subdued and more in accordance with fact and the nature of things.]
  8549. The Platonic Republic has become proverbial as an example--and a
  8550. striking one--of imaginary perfection, such as can exist only in the
  8551. brain of the idle thinker; and Brucker ridicules the philosopher
  8552. for maintaining that a prince can never govern well, unless he is
  8553. participant in the ideas. But we should do better to follow up this
  8554. thought and, where this admirable thinker leaves us without assistance,
  8555. employ new efforts to place it in clearer light, rather than carelessly
  8556. fling it aside as useless, under the very miserable and pernicious
  8557. pretext of impracticability. A constitution of the greatest possible
  8558. human freedom according to laws, by which the liberty of every
  8559. individual can consist with the liberty of every other (not of the
  8560. greatest possible happiness, for this follows necessarily from the
  8561. former), is, to say the least, a necessary idea, which must be placed
  8562. at the foundation not only of the first plan of the constitution of a
  8563. state, but of all its laws. And, in this, it not necessary at the outset
  8564. to take account of the obstacles which lie in our way--obstacles which
  8565. perhaps do not necessarily arise from the character of human nature, but
  8566. rather from the previous neglect of true ideas in legislation. For there
  8567. is nothing more pernicious and more unworthy of a philosopher, than the
  8568. vulgar appeal to a so-called adverse experience, which indeed would not
  8569. have existed, if those institutions had been established at the proper
  8570. time and in accordance with ideas; while, instead of this, conceptions,
  8571. crude for the very reason that they have been drawn from experience,
  8572. have marred and frustrated all our better views and intentions. The more
  8573. legislation and government are in harmony with this idea, the more rare
  8574. do punishments become and thus it is quite reasonable to maintain,
  8575. as Plato did, that in a perfect state no punishments at all would be
  8576. necessary. Now although a perfect state may never exist, the idea is
  8577. not on that account the less just, which holds up this maximum as the
  8578. archetype or standard of a constitution, in order to bring legislative
  8579. government always nearer and nearer to the greatest possible perfection.
  8580. For at what precise degree human nature must stop in its progress, and
  8581. how wide must be the chasm which must necessarily exist between the
  8582. idea and its realization, are problems which no one can or ought to
  8583. determine--and for this reason, that it is the destination of freedom to
  8584. overstep all assigned limits between itself and the idea.
  8585. But not only in that wherein human reason is a real causal agent and
  8586. where ideas are operative causes (of actions and their objects), that is
  8587. to say, in the region of ethics, but also in regard to nature herself,
  8588. Plato saw clear proofs of an origin from ideas. A plant, and animal,
  8589. the regular order of nature--probably also the disposition of the whole
  8590. universe--give manifest evidence that they are possible only by means
  8591. of and according to ideas; that, indeed, no one creature, under the
  8592. individual conditions of its existence, perfectly harmonizes with the
  8593. idea of the most perfect of its kind--just as little as man with
  8594. the idea of humanity, which nevertheless he bears in his soul as the
  8595. archetypal standard of his actions; that, notwithstanding, these ideas
  8596. are in the highest sense individually, unchangeably, and completely
  8597. determined, and are the original causes of things; and that the totality
  8598. of connected objects in the universe is alone fully adequate to that
  8599. idea. Setting aside the exaggerations of expression in the writings of
  8600. this philosopher, the mental power exhibited in this ascent from the
  8601. ectypal mode of regarding the physical world to the architectonic
  8602. connection thereof according to ends, that is, ideas, is an effort which
  8603. deserves imitation and claims respect. But as regards the principles of
  8604. ethics, of legislation, and of religion, spheres in which ideas
  8605. alone render experience possible, although they never attain to full
  8606. expression therein, he has vindicated for himself a position of peculiar
  8607. merit, which is not appreciated only because it is judged by the very
  8608. empirical rules, the validity of which as principles is destroyed by
  8609. ideas. For as regards nature, experience presents us with rules and is
  8610. the source of truth, but in relation to ethical laws experience is the
  8611. parent of illusion, and it is in the highest degree reprehensible to
  8612. limit or to deduce the laws which dictate what I ought to do, from what
  8613. is done.
  8614. We must, however, omit the consideration of these important subjects,
  8615. the development of which is in reality the peculiar duty and dignity of
  8616. philosophy, and confine ourselves for the present to the more humble but
  8617. not less useful task of preparing a firm foundation for those majestic
  8618. edifices of moral science. For this foundation has been hitherto
  8619. insecure from the many subterranean passages which reason in its
  8620. confident but vain search for treasures has made in all directions.
  8621. Our present duty is to make ourselves perfectly acquainted with the
  8622. transcendental use made of pure reason, its principles and ideas, that
  8623. we may be able properly to determine and value its influence and real
  8624. worth. But before bringing these introductory remarks to a close, I
  8625. beg those who really have philosophy at heart--and their number is but
  8626. small--if they shall find themselves convinced by the considerations
  8627. following as well as by those above, to exert themselves to preserve to
  8628. the expression idea its original signification, and to take care that
  8629. it be not lost among those other expressions by which all sorts of
  8630. representations are loosely designated--that the interests of science
  8631. may not thereby suffer. We are in no want of words to denominate
  8632. adequately every mode of representation, without the necessity of
  8633. encroaching upon terms which are proper to others. The following is
  8634. a graduated list of them. The genus is representation in general
  8635. (representatio). Under it stands representation with consciousness
  8636. (perceptio). A perception which relates solely to the subject as a
  8637. modification of its state, is a sensation (sensatio), an objective
  8638. perception is a cognition (cognitio). A cognition is either an intuition
  8639. or a conception (intuitus vel conceptus). The former has an immediate
  8640. relation to the object and is singular and individual; the latter has
  8641. but a mediate relation, by means of a characteristic mark which may be
  8642. common to several things. A conception is either empirical or pure. A
  8643. pure conception, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding
  8644. alone, and is not the conception of a pure sensuous image, is
  8645. called notio. A conception formed from notions, which transcends the
  8646. possibility of experience, is an idea, or a conception of reason. To
  8647. one who has accustomed himself to these distinctions, it must be quite
  8648. intolerable to hear the representation of the colour red called an idea.
  8649. It ought not even to be called a notion or conception of understanding.
  8650. SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas.
  8651. Transcendental analytic showed us how the mere logical form of
  8652. our cognition can contain the origin of pure conceptions a priori,
  8653. conceptions which represent objects antecedently to all experience, or
  8654. rather, indicate the synthetical unity which alone renders possible an
  8655. empirical cognition of objects. The form of judgements--converted into a
  8656. conception of the synthesis of intuitions--produced the categories
  8657. which direct the employment of the understanding in experience. This
  8658. consideration warrants us to expect that the form of syllogisms, when
  8659. applied to synthetical unity of intuitions, following the rule of the
  8660. categories, will contain the origin of particular a priori conceptions,
  8661. which we may call pure conceptions of reason or transcendental ideas,
  8662. and which will determine the use of the understanding in the totality of
  8663. experience according to principles.
  8664. The function of reason in arguments consists in the universality of
  8665. a cognition according to conceptions, and the syllogism itself is
  8666. a judgement which is determined a priori in the whole extent of its
  8667. condition. The proposition: "Caius is mortal," is one which may be
  8668. obtained from experience by the aid of the understanding alone; but my
  8669. wish is to find a conception which contains the condition under which
  8670. the predicate of this judgement is given--in this case, the conception
  8671. of man--and after subsuming under this condition, taken in its whole
  8672. extent (all men are mortal), I determine according to it the cognition
  8673. of the object thought, and say: "Caius is mortal."
  8674. Hence, in the conclusion of a syllogism we restrict a predicate to a
  8675. certain object, after having thought it in the major in its whole extent
  8676. under a certain condition. This complete quantity of the extent in
  8677. relation to such a condition is called universality (universalitas). To
  8678. this corresponds totality (universitas) of conditions in the synthesis
  8679. of intuitions. The transcendental conception of reason is therefore
  8680. nothing else than the conception of the totality of the conditions of
  8681. a given conditioned. Now as the unconditioned alone renders possible
  8682. totality of conditions, and, conversely, the totality of conditions is
  8683. itself always unconditioned; a pure rational conception in general
  8684. can be defined and explained by means of the conception of the
  8685. unconditioned, in so far as it contains a basis for the synthesis of the
  8686. conditioned.
  8687. To the number of modes of relation which the understanding cogitates by
  8688. means of the categories, the number of pure rational conceptions will
  8689. correspond. We must therefore seek for, first, an unconditioned of
  8690. the categorical synthesis in a subject; secondly, of the hypothetical
  8691. synthesis of the members of a series; thirdly, of the disjunctive
  8692. synthesis of parts in a system.
  8693. There are exactly the same number of modes of syllogisms, each of which
  8694. proceeds through prosyllogisms to the unconditioned--one to the subject
  8695. which cannot be employed as predicate, another to the presupposition
  8696. which supposes nothing higher than itself, and the third to an aggregate
  8697. of the members of the complete division of a conception. Hence the pure
  8698. rational conceptions of totality in the synthesis of conditions have a
  8699. necessary foundation in the nature of human reason--at least as modes of
  8700. elevating the unity of the understanding to the unconditioned. They
  8701. may have no valid application, corresponding to their transcendental
  8702. employment, in concreto, and be thus of no greater utility than
  8703. to direct the understanding how, while extending them as widely
  8704. as possible, to maintain its exercise and application in perfect
  8705. consistence and harmony.
  8706. But, while speaking here of the totality of conditions and of the
  8707. unconditioned as the common title of all conceptions of reason, we again
  8708. light upon an expression which we find it impossible to dispense with,
  8709. and which nevertheless, owing to the ambiguity attaching to it from long
  8710. abuse, we cannot employ with safety. The word absolute is one of the few
  8711. words which, in its original signification, was perfectly adequate to
  8712. the conception it was intended to convey--a conception which no other
  8713. word in the same language exactly suits, and the loss--or, which is
  8714. the same thing, the incautious and loose employment--of which must
  8715. be followed by the loss of the conception itself. And, as it is a
  8716. conception which occupies much of the attention of reason, its loss
  8717. would be greatly to the detriment of all transcendental philosophy. The
  8718. word absolute is at present frequently used to denote that something can
  8719. be predicated of a thing considered in itself and intrinsically. In this
  8720. sense absolutely possible would signify that which is possible in itself
  8721. (interne)--which is, in fact, the least that one can predicate of an
  8722. object. On the other hand, it is sometimes employed to indicate that
  8723. a thing is valid in all respects--for example, absolute sovereignty.
  8724. Absolutely possible would in this sense signify that which is possible
  8725. in all relations and in every respect; and this is the most that can be
  8726. predicated of the possibility of a thing. Now these significations do
  8727. in truth frequently coincide. Thus, for example, that which is
  8728. intrinsically impossible, is also impossible in all relations, that is,
  8729. absolutely impossible. But in most cases they differ from each other
  8730. toto caelo, and I can by no means conclude that, because a thing is in
  8731. itself possible, it is also possible in all relations, and therefore
  8732. absolutely. Nay, more, I shall in the sequel show that absolute
  8733. necessity does not by any means depend on internal necessity, and
  8734. that, therefore, it must not be considered as synonymous with it. Of an
  8735. opposite which is intrinsically impossible, we may affirm that it is in
  8736. all respects impossible, and that, consequently, the thing itself, of
  8737. which this is the opposite, is absolutely necessary; but I cannot reason
  8738. conversely and say, the opposite of that which is absolutely necessary
  8739. is intrinsically impossible, that is, that the absolute necessity of
  8740. things is an internal necessity. For this internal necessity is in
  8741. certain cases a mere empty word with which the least conception cannot
  8742. be connected, while the conception of the necessity of a thing in all
  8743. relations possesses very peculiar determinations. Now as the loss of a
  8744. conception of great utility in speculative science cannot be a matter of
  8745. indifference to the philosopher, I trust that the proper determination
  8746. and careful preservation of the expression on which the conception
  8747. depends will likewise be not indifferent to him.
  8748. In this enlarged signification, then, shall I employ the word absolute,
  8749. in opposition to that which is valid only in some particular respect;
  8750. for the latter is restricted by conditions, the former is valid without
  8751. any restriction whatever.
  8752. Now the transcendental conception of reason has for its object nothing
  8753. else than absolute totality in the synthesis of conditions and does not
  8754. rest satisfied till it has attained to the absolutely, that is, in all
  8755. respects and relations, unconditioned. For pure reason leaves to the
  8756. understanding everything that immediately relates to the object of
  8757. intuition or rather to their synthesis in imagination. The former
  8758. restricts itself to the absolute totality in the employment of
  8759. the conceptions of the understanding and aims at carrying out the
  8760. synthetical unity which is cogitated in the category, even to the
  8761. unconditioned. This unity may hence be called the rational unity of
  8762. phenomena, as the other, which the category expresses, may be termed the
  8763. unity of the understanding. Reason, therefore, has an immediate relation
  8764. to the use of the understanding, not indeed in so far as the latter
  8765. contains the ground of possible experience (for the conception of the
  8766. absolute totality of conditions is not a conception that can be employed
  8767. in experience, because no experience is unconditioned), but solely
  8768. for the purpose of directing it to a certain unity, of which the
  8769. understanding has no conception, and the aim of which is to collect into
  8770. an absolute whole all acts of the understanding. Hence the objective
  8771. employment of the pure conceptions of reason is always transcendent,
  8772. while that of the pure conceptions of the understanding must, according
  8773. to their nature, be always immanent, inasmuch as they are limited to
  8774. possible experience.
  8775. I understand by idea a necessary conception of reason, to which
  8776. no corresponding object can be discovered in the world of sense.
  8777. Accordingly, the pure conceptions of reason at present under
  8778. consideration are transcendental ideas. They are conceptions of pure
  8779. reason, for they regard all empirical cognition as determined by means
  8780. of an absolute totality of conditions. They are not mere fictions, but
  8781. natural and necessary products of reason, and have hence a necessary
  8782. relation to the whole sphere of the exercise of the understanding.
  8783. And, finally, they are transcendent, and overstep the limits of all
  8784. experiences, in which, consequently, no object can ever be presented
  8785. that would be perfectly adequate to a transcendental idea. When we use
  8786. the word idea, we say, as regards its object (an object of the pure
  8787. understanding), a great deal, but as regards its subject (that is, in
  8788. respect of its reality under conditions of experience), exceedingly
  8789. little, because the idea, as the conception of a maximum, can never be
  8790. completely and adequately presented in concreto. Now, as in the merely
  8791. speculative employment of reason the latter is properly the sole aim,
  8792. and as in this case the approximation to a conception, which is never
  8793. attained in practice, is the same thing as if the conception were
  8794. non-existent--it is commonly said of the conception of this kind, "it is
  8795. only an idea." So we might very well say, "the absolute totality of all
  8796. phenomena is only an idea," for, as we never can present an adequate
  8797. representation of it, it remains for us a problem incapable of solution.
  8798. On the other hand, as in the practical use of the understanding we have
  8799. only to do with action and practice according to rules, an idea of pure
  8800. reason can always be given really in concreto, although only partially,
  8801. nay, it is the indispensable condition of all practical employment of
  8802. reason. The practice or execution of the idea is always limited
  8803. and defective, but nevertheless within indeterminable boundaries,
  8804. consequently always under the influence of the conception of an absolute
  8805. perfection. And thus the practical idea is always in the highest degree
  8806. fruitful, and in relation to real actions indispensably necessary.
  8807. In the idea, pure reason possesses even causality and the power of
  8808. producing that which its conception contains. Hence we cannot say of
  8809. wisdom, in a disparaging way, "it is only an idea." For, for the very
  8810. reason that it is the idea of the necessary unity of all possible aims,
  8811. it must be for all practical exertions and endeavours the primitive
  8812. condition and rule--a rule which, if not constitutive, is at least
  8813. limitative.
  8814. Now, although we must say of the transcendental conceptions of reason,
  8815. "they are only ideas," we must not, on this account, look upon them as
  8816. superfluous and nugatory. For, although no object can be determined by
  8817. them, they can be of great utility, unobserved and at the basis of
  8818. the edifice of the understanding, as the canon for its extended and
  8819. self-consistent exercise--a canon which, indeed, does not enable it to
  8820. cognize more in an object than it would cognize by the help of its own
  8821. conceptions, but which guides it more securely in its cognition. Not
  8822. to mention that they perhaps render possible a transition from our
  8823. conceptions of nature and the non-ego to the practical conceptions, and
  8824. thus produce for even ethical ideas keeping, so to speak, and connection
  8825. with the speculative cognitions of reason. The explication of all this
  8826. must be looked for in the sequel.
  8827. But setting aside, in conformity with our original purpose, the
  8828. consideration of the practical ideas, we proceed to contemplate reason
  8829. in its speculative use alone, nay, in a still more restricted sphere, to
  8830. wit, in the transcendental use; and here must strike into the same path
  8831. which we followed in our deduction of the categories. That is to say, we
  8832. shall consider the logical form of the cognition of reason, that we
  8833. may see whether reason may not be thereby a source of conceptions which
  8834. enables us to regard objects in themselves as determined synthetically a
  8835. priori, in relation to one or other of the functions of reason.
  8836. Reason, considered as the faculty of a certain logical form of
  8837. cognition, is the faculty of conclusion, that is, of mediate
  8838. judgement--by means of the subsumption of the condition of a possible
  8839. judgement under the condition of a given judgement. The given judgement
  8840. is the general rule (major). The subsumption of the condition of another
  8841. possible judgement under the condition of the rule is the minor. The
  8842. actual judgement, which enounces the assertion of the rule in the
  8843. subsumed case, is the conclusion (conclusio). The rule predicates
  8844. something generally under a certain condition. The condition of the rule
  8845. is satisfied in some particular case. It follows that what was valid
  8846. in general under that condition must also be considered as valid in the
  8847. particular case which satisfies this condition. It is very plain that
  8848. reason attains to a cognition, by means of acts of the understanding
  8849. which constitute a series of conditions. When I arrive at the
  8850. proposition, "All bodies are changeable," by beginning with the more
  8851. remote cognition (in which the conception of body does not appear, but
  8852. which nevertheless contains the condition of that conception), "All
  8853. compound is changeable," by proceeding from this to a less remote
  8854. cognition, which stands under the condition of the former, "Bodies are
  8855. compound," and hence to a third, which at length connects for me the
  8856. remote cognition (changeable) with the one before me, "Consequently,
  8857. bodies are changeable"--I have arrived at a cognition (conclusion)
  8858. through a series of conditions (premisses). Now every series, whose
  8859. exponent (of the categorical or hypothetical judgement) is given, can be
  8860. continued; consequently the same procedure of reason conducts us to the
  8861. ratiocinatio polysyllogistica, which is a series of syllogisms, that can
  8862. be continued either on the side of the conditions (per prosyllogismos)
  8863. or of the conditioned (per episyllogismos) to an indefinite extent.
  8864. But we very soon perceive that the chain or series of prosyllogisms,
  8865. that is, of deduced cognitions on the side of the grounds or conditions
  8866. of a given cognition, in other words, the ascending series of syllogisms
  8867. must have a very different relation to the faculty of reason from that
  8868. of the descending series, that is, the progressive procedure of reason
  8869. on the side of the conditioned by means of episyllogisms. For, as in
  8870. the former case the cognition (conclusio) is given only as conditioned,
  8871. reason can attain to this cognition only under the presupposition that
  8872. all the members of the series on the side of the conditions are
  8873. given (totality in the series of premisses), because only under this
  8874. supposition is the judgement we may be considering possible a priori;
  8875. while on the side of the conditioned or the inferences, only an
  8876. incomplete and becoming, and not a presupposed or given series,
  8877. consequently only a potential progression, is cogitated. Hence, when
  8878. a cognition is contemplated as conditioned, reason is compelled to
  8879. consider the series of conditions in an ascending line as completed and
  8880. given in their totality. But if the very same condition is considered
  8881. at the same time as the condition of other cognitions, which together
  8882. constitute a series of inferences or consequences in a descending
  8883. line, reason may preserve a perfect indifference, as to how far this
  8884. progression may extend a parte posteriori, and whether the totality of
  8885. this series is possible, because it stands in no need of such a series
  8886. for the purpose of arriving at the conclusion before it, inasmuch as
  8887. this conclusion is sufficiently guaranteed and determined on grounds a
  8888. parte priori. It may be the case, that upon the side of the conditions
  8889. the series of premisses has a first or highest condition, or it may
  8890. not possess this, and so be a parte priori unlimited; but it must,
  8891. nevertheless, contain totality of conditions, even admitting that we
  8892. never could succeed in completely apprehending it; and the whole series
  8893. must be unconditionally true, if the conditioned, which is considered
  8894. as an inference resulting from it, is to be held as true. This is a
  8895. requirement of reason, which announces its cognition as determined a
  8896. priori and as necessary, either in itself--and in this case it needs no
  8897. grounds to rest upon--or, if it is deduced, as a member of a series of
  8898. grounds, which is itself unconditionally true.
  8899. SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas.
  8900. We are not at present engaged with a logical dialectic, which makes
  8901. complete abstraction of the content of cognition and aims only at
  8902. unveiling the illusory appearance in the form of syllogisms. Our subject
  8903. is transcendental dialectic, which must contain, completely a priori,
  8904. the origin of certain cognitions drawn from pure reason, and the origin
  8905. of certain deduced conceptions, the object of which cannot be given
  8906. empirically and which therefore lie beyond the sphere of the faculty
  8907. of understanding. We have observed, from the natural relation which
  8908. the transcendental use of our cognition, in syllogisms as well as in
  8909. judgements, must have to the logical, that there are three kinds of
  8910. dialectical arguments, corresponding to the three modes of conclusion,
  8911. by which reason attains to cognitions on principles; and that in all
  8912. it is the business of reason to ascend from the conditioned synthesis,
  8913. beyond which the understanding never proceeds, to the unconditioned
  8914. which the understanding never can reach.
  8915. Now the most general relations which can exist in our representations
  8916. are: 1st, the relation to the subject; 2nd, the relation to objects,
  8917. either as phenomena, or as objects of thought in general. If we connect
  8918. this subdivision with the main division, all the relations of our
  8919. representations, of which we can form either a conception or an idea,
  8920. are threefold: 1. The relation to the subject; 2. The relation to the
  8921. manifold of the object as a phenomenon; 3. The relation to all things in
  8922. general.
  8923. Now all pure conceptions have to do in general with the synthetical
  8924. unity of representations; conceptions of pure reason (transcendental
  8925. ideas), on the other hand, with the unconditional synthetical unity
  8926. of all conditions. It follows that all transcendental ideas arrange
  8927. themselves in three classes, the first of which contains the absolute
  8928. (unconditioned) unity of the thinking subject, the second the absolute
  8929. unity of the series of the conditions of a phenomenon, the third the
  8930. absolute unity of the condition of all objects of thought in general.
  8931. The thinking subject is the object-matter of Psychology; the sum total
  8932. of all phenomena (the world) is the object-matter of Cosmology; and the
  8933. thing which contains the highest condition of the possibility of all
  8934. that is cogitable (the being of all beings) is the object-matter of all
  8935. Theology. Thus pure reason presents us with the idea of a transcendental
  8936. doctrine of the soul (psychologia rationalis), of a transcendental
  8937. science of the world (cosmologia rationalis), and finally of
  8938. a transcendental doctrine of God (theologia transcendentalis).
  8939. Understanding cannot originate even the outline of any of these
  8940. sciences, even when connected with the highest logical use of reason,
  8941. that is, all cogitable syllogisms--for the purpose of proceeding from
  8942. one object (phenomenon) to all others, even to the utmost limits of
  8943. the empirical synthesis. They are, on the contrary, pure and genuine
  8944. products, or problems, of pure reason.
  8945. What modi of the pure conceptions of reason these transcendental ideas
  8946. are will be fully exposed in the following chapter. They follow
  8947. the guiding thread of the categories. For pure reason never relates
  8948. immediately to objects, but to the conceptions of these contained in the
  8949. understanding. In like manner, it will be made manifest in the detailed
  8950. explanation of these ideas--how reason, merely through the synthetical
  8951. use of the same function which it employs in a categorical syllogism,
  8952. necessarily attains to the conception of the absolute unity of the
  8953. thinking subject--how the logical procedure in hypothetical ideas
  8954. necessarily produces the idea of the absolutely unconditioned in a
  8955. series of given conditions, and finally--how the mere form of the
  8956. disjunctive syllogism involves the highest conception of a being of
  8957. all beings: a thought which at first sight seems in the highest degree
  8958. paradoxical.
  8959. An objective deduction, such as we were able to present in the case of
  8960. the categories, is impossible as regards these transcendental ideas. For
  8961. they have, in truth, no relation to any object, in experience, for the
  8962. very reason that they are only ideas. But a subjective deduction of them
  8963. from the nature of our reason is possible, and has been given in the
  8964. present chapter.
  8965. It is easy to perceive that the sole aim of pure reason is the absolute
  8966. totality of the synthesis on the side of the conditions, and that it
  8967. does not concern itself with the absolute completeness on the Part of
  8968. the conditioned. For of the former alone does she stand in need, in
  8969. order to preposit the whole series of conditions, and thus present them
  8970. to the understanding a priori. But if we once have a completely (and
  8971. unconditionally) given condition, there is no further necessity,
  8972. in proceeding with the series, for a conception of reason; for the
  8973. understanding takes of itself every step downward, from the condition
  8974. to the conditioned. Thus the transcendental ideas are available only for
  8975. ascending in the series of conditions, till we reach the unconditioned,
  8976. that is, principles. As regards descending to the conditioned, on the
  8977. other hand, we find that there is a widely extensive logical use which
  8978. reason makes of the laws of the understanding, but that a transcendental
  8979. use thereof is impossible; and that when we form an idea of the absolute
  8980. totality of such a synthesis, for example, of the whole series of
  8981. all future changes in the world, this idea is a mere ens rationis, an
  8982. arbitrary fiction of thought, and not a necessary presupposition of
  8983. reason. For the possibility of the conditioned presupposes the totality
  8984. of its conditions, but not of its consequences. Consequently, this
  8985. conception is not a transcendental idea--and it is with these alone that
  8986. we are at present occupied.
  8987. Finally, it is obvious that there exists among the transcendental ideas
  8988. a certain connection and unity, and that pure reason, by means of them,
  8989. collects all its cognitions into one system. From the cognition of self
  8990. to the cognition of the world, and through these to the supreme being,
  8991. the progression is so natural, that it seems to resemble the logical
  8992. march of reason from the premisses to the conclusion.* Now whether there
  8993. lies unobserved at the foundation of these ideas an analogy of the
  8994. same kind as exists between the logical and transcendental procedure of
  8995. reason, is another of those questions, the answer to which we must not
  8996. expect till we arrive at a more advanced stage in our inquiries. In this
  8997. cursory and preliminary view, we have, meanwhile, reached our aim. For
  8998. we have dispelled the ambiguity which attached to the transcendental
  8999. conceptions of reason, from their being commonly mixed up with
  9000. other conceptions in the systems of philosophers, and not properly
  9001. distinguished from the conceptions of the understanding; we have exposed
  9002. their origin and, thereby, at the same time their determinate number,
  9003. and presented them in a systematic connection, and have thus marked out
  9004. and enclosed a definite sphere for pure reason.
  9005. [*Footnote: The science of Metaphysics has for the proper object of its
  9006. inquiries only three grand ideas: GOD, FREEDOM, and IMMORTALITY, and it
  9007. aims at showing, that the second conception, conjoined with the first,
  9008. must lead to the third, as a necessary conclusion. All the other
  9009. subjects with which it occupies itself, are merely means for the
  9010. attainment and realization of these ideas. It does not require these
  9011. ideas for the construction of a science of nature, but, on the contrary,
  9012. for the purpose of passing beyond the sphere of nature. A complete
  9013. insight into and comprehension of them would render Theology, Ethics,
  9014. and, through the conjunction of both, Religion, solely dependent on the
  9015. speculative faculty of reason. In a systematic representation of these
  9016. ideas the above-mentioned arrangement--the synthetical one--would be the
  9017. most suitable; but in the investigation which must necessarily precede
  9018. it, the analytical, which reverses this arrangement, would be better
  9019. adapted to our purpose, as in it we should proceed from that which
  9020. experience immediately presents to us--psychology, to cosmology, and
  9021. thence to theology.]
  9022. BOOK II.-- OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON.
  9023. It may be said that the object of a merely transcendental idea is
  9024. something of which we have no conception, although the idea may be a
  9025. necessary product of reason according to its original laws. For, in
  9026. fact, a conception of an object that is adequate to the idea given
  9027. by reason, is impossible. For such an object must be capable of being
  9028. presented and intuited in a Possible experience. But we should express
  9029. our meaning better, and with less risk of being misunderstood, if
  9030. we said that we can have no knowledge of an object, which perfectly
  9031. corresponds to an idea, although we may possess a problematical
  9032. conception thereof.
  9033. Now the transcendental (subjective) reality at least of the pure
  9034. conceptions of reason rests upon the fact that we are led to such ideas
  9035. by a necessary procedure of reason. There must therefore be syllogisms
  9036. which contain no empirical premisses, and by means of which we conclude
  9037. from something that we do know, to something of which we do not even
  9038. possess a conception, to which we, nevertheless, by an unavoidable
  9039. illusion, ascribe objective reality. Such arguments are, as regards
  9040. their result, rather to be termed sophisms than syllogisms, although
  9041. indeed, as regards their origin, they are very well entitled to the
  9042. latter name, inasmuch as they are not fictions or accidental products of
  9043. reason, but are necessitated by its very nature. They are sophisms, not
  9044. of men, but of pure reason herself, from which the Wisest cannot free
  9045. himself. After long labour he may be able to guard against the error,
  9046. but he can never be thoroughly rid of the illusion which continually
  9047. mocks and misleads him.
  9048. Of these dialectical arguments there are three kinds, corresponding to
  9049. the number of the ideas which their conclusions present. In the argument
  9050. or syllogism of the first class, I conclude, from the transcendental
  9051. conception of the subject contains no manifold, the absolute unity
  9052. of the subject itself, of which I cannot in this manner attain to a
  9053. conception. This dialectical argument I shall call the transcendental
  9054. paralogism. The second class of sophistical arguments is occupied with
  9055. the transcendental conception of the absolute totality of the series of
  9056. conditions for a given phenomenon, and I conclude, from the fact that
  9057. I have always a self-contradictory conception of the unconditioned
  9058. synthetical unity of the series upon one side, the truth of the opposite
  9059. unity, of which I have nevertheless no conception. The condition of
  9060. reason in these dialectical arguments, I shall term the antinomy of pure
  9061. reason. Finally, according to the third kind of sophistical argument,
  9062. I conclude, from the totality of the conditions of thinking objects in
  9063. general, in so far as they can be given, the absolute synthetical unity
  9064. of all conditions of the possibility of things in general; that is, from
  9065. things which I do not know in their mere transcendental conception, I
  9066. conclude a being of all beings which I know still less by means of a
  9067. transcendental conception, and of whose unconditioned necessity I can
  9068. form no conception whatever. This dialectical argument I shall call the
  9069. ideal of pure reason.
  9070. CHAPTER I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason.
  9071. The logical paralogism consists in the falsity of an argument in respect
  9072. of its form, be the content what it may. But a transcendental paralogism
  9073. has a transcendental foundation, and concludes falsely, while the form
  9074. is correct and unexceptionable. In this manner the paralogism has
  9075. its foundation in the nature of human reason, and is the parent of an
  9076. unavoidable, though not insoluble, mental illusion.
  9077. We now come to a conception which was not inserted in the general list
  9078. of transcendental conceptions, and yet must be reckoned with them,
  9079. but at the same time without in the least altering, or indicating a
  9080. deficiency in that table. This is the conception, or, if the term is
  9081. preferred, the judgement, "I think." But it is readily perceived that
  9082. this thought is as it were the vehicle of all conceptions in general,
  9083. and consequently of transcendental conceptions also, and that it is
  9084. therefore regarded as a transcendental conception, although it can
  9085. have no peculiar claim to be so ranked, inasmuch as its only use is to
  9086. indicate that all thought is accompanied by consciousness. At the same
  9087. time, pure as this conception is from empirical content (impressions
  9088. of the senses), it enables us to distinguish two different kinds of
  9089. objects. "I," as thinking, am an object of the internal sense, and am
  9090. called soul. That which is an object of the external senses is called
  9091. body. Thus the expression, "I," as a thinking being, designates the
  9092. object-matter of psychology, which may be called "the rational doctrine
  9093. of the soul," inasmuch as in this science I desire to know nothing of
  9094. the soul but what, independently of all experience (which determines me
  9095. in concreto), may be concluded from this conception "I," in so far as it
  9096. appears in all thought.
  9097. Now, the rational doctrine of the soul is really an undertaking of
  9098. this kind. For if the smallest empirical element of thought, if any
  9099. particular perception of my internal state, were to be introduced among
  9100. the grounds of cognition of this science, it would not be a rational,
  9101. but an empirical doctrine of the soul. We have thus before us a
  9102. pretended science, raised upon the single proposition, "I think," whose
  9103. foundation or want of foundation we may very properly, and agreeably
  9104. with the nature of a transcendental philosophy, here examine. It
  9105. ought not to be objected that in this proposition, which expresses the
  9106. perception of one's self, an internal experience is asserted, and that
  9107. consequently the rational doctrine of the soul which is founded upon it,
  9108. is not pure, but partly founded upon an empirical principle. For this
  9109. internal perception is nothing more than the mere apperception, "I
  9110. think," which in fact renders all transcendental conceptions possible,
  9111. in which we say, "I think substance, cause, etc." For internal
  9112. experience in general and its possibility, or perception in general, and
  9113. its relation to other perceptions, unless some particular distinction
  9114. or determination thereof is empirically given, cannot be regarded as
  9115. empirical cognition, but as cognition of the empirical, and belongs
  9116. to the investigation of the possibility of every experience, which
  9117. is certainly transcendental. The smallest object of experience (for
  9118. example, only pleasure or pain), that should be included in the general
  9119. representation of self-consciousness, would immediately change the
  9120. rational into an empirical psychology.
  9121. "I think" is therefore the only text of rational psychology, from which
  9122. it must develop its whole system. It is manifest that this thought, when
  9123. applied to an object (myself), can contain nothing but transcendental
  9124. predicates thereof; because the least empirical predicate would destroy
  9125. the purity of the science and its independence of all experience.
  9126. But we shall have to follow here the guidance of the categories--only,
  9127. as in the present case a thing, "I," as thinking being, is at first
  9128. given, we shall--not indeed change the order of the categories as it
  9129. stands in the table--but begin at the category of substance, by which at
  9130. the a thing in itself is represented and proceeds backwards through
  9131. the series. The topic of the rational doctrine of the soul, from which
  9132. everything else it may contain must be deduced, is accordingly as
  9133. follows:
  9134. 1 2
  9135. The Soul is SUBSTANCE As regards its quality
  9136. it is SIMPLE
  9137. 3
  9138. As regards the different
  9139. times in which it exists,
  9140. it is numerically identical,
  9141. that is UNITY, not Plurality.
  9142. 4
  9143. It is in relation to possible objects in space*
  9144. [*Footnote: The reader, who may not so easily perceive the psychological
  9145. sense of these expressions, taken here in their transcendental
  9146. abstraction, and cannot guess why the latter attribute of the soul
  9147. belongs to the category of existence, will find the expressions
  9148. sufficiently explained and justified in the sequel. I have, moreover, to
  9149. apologize for the Latin terms which have been employed, instead of their
  9150. German synonyms, contrary to the rules of correct writing. But I judged
  9151. it better to sacrifice elegance to perspicuity.]
  9152. From these elements originate all the conceptions of pure psychology,
  9153. by combination alone, without the aid of any other principle. This
  9154. substance, merely as an object of the internal sense, gives
  9155. the conception of Immateriality; as simple substance, that of
  9156. Incorruptibility; its identity, as intellectual substance, gives the
  9157. conception of Personality; all these three together, Spirituality.
  9158. Its relation to objects in space gives us the conception of connection
  9159. (commercium) with bodies. Thus it represents thinking substance as the
  9160. principle of life in matter, that is, as a soul (anima), and as the
  9161. ground of Animality; and this, limited and determined by the conception
  9162. of spirituality, gives us that of Immortality.
  9163. Now to these conceptions relate four paralogisms of a transcendental
  9164. psychology, which is falsely held to be a science of pure reason,
  9165. touching the nature of our thinking being. We can, however, lay at
  9166. the foundation of this science nothing but the simple and in itself
  9167. perfectly contentless representation "I" which cannot even be called
  9168. a conception, but merely a consciousness which accompanies all
  9169. conceptions. By this "I," or "He," or "It," who or which thinks, nothing
  9170. more is represented than a transcendental subject of thought = x, which
  9171. is cognized only by means of the thoughts that are its predicates, and
  9172. of which, apart from these, we cannot form the least conception. Hence
  9173. in a perpetual circle, inasmuch as we must always employ it, in order
  9174. to frame any judgement respecting it. And this inconvenience we find it
  9175. impossible to rid ourselves of, because consciousness in itself is not
  9176. so much a representation distinguishing a particular object, as a form
  9177. of representation in general, in so far as it may be termed cognition;
  9178. for in and by cognition alone do I think anything.
  9179. It must, however, appear extraordinary at first sight that the condition
  9180. under which I think, and which is consequently a property of my subject,
  9181. should be held to be likewise valid for every existence which thinks,
  9182. and that we can presume to base upon a seemingly empirical proposition
  9183. a judgement which is apodeictic and universal, to wit, that everything
  9184. which thinks is constituted as the voice of my consciousness declares it
  9185. to be, that is, as a self-conscious being. The cause of this belief is
  9186. to be found in the fact that we necessarily attribute to things a priori
  9187. all the properties which constitute conditions under which alone we
  9188. can cogitate them. Now I cannot obtain the least representation of
  9189. a thinking being by means of external experience, but solely through
  9190. self-consciousness. Such objects are consequently nothing more than the
  9191. transference of this consciousness of mine to other things which can
  9192. only thus be represented as thinking beings. The proposition, "I think,"
  9193. is, in the present case, understood in a problematical sense, not in
  9194. so far as it contains a perception of an existence (like the Cartesian
  9195. "Cogito, ergo sum"),[Footnote: "I think, therefore I am."] but in regard
  9196. to its mere possibility--for the purpose of discovering what properties
  9197. may be inferred from so simple a proposition and predicated of the
  9198. subject of it.
  9199. If at the foundation of our pure rational cognition of thinking beings
  9200. there lay more than the mere Cogito--if we could likewise call in aid
  9201. observations on the play of our thoughts, and the thence derived natural
  9202. laws of the thinking self, there would arise an empirical psychology
  9203. which would be a kind of physiology of the internal sense and might
  9204. possibly be capable of explaining the phenomena of that sense. But it
  9205. could never be available for discovering those properties which do not
  9206. belong to possible experience (such as the quality of simplicity),
  9207. nor could it make any apodeictic enunciation on the nature of thinking
  9208. beings: it would therefore not be a rational psychology.
  9209. Now, as the proposition "I think" (in the problematical sense) contains
  9210. the form of every judgement in general and is the constant accompaniment
  9211. of all the categories, it is manifest that conclusions are drawn from
  9212. it only by a transcendental employment of the understanding. This use of
  9213. the understanding excludes all empirical elements; and we cannot, as
  9214. has been shown above, have any favourable conception beforehand of
  9215. its procedure. We shall therefore follow with a critical eye this
  9216. proposition through all the predicaments of pure psychology; but we
  9217. shall, for brevity's sake, allow this examination to proceed in an
  9218. uninterrupted connection.
  9219. Before entering on this task, however, the following general remark may
  9220. help to quicken our attention to this mode of argument. It is not
  9221. merely through my thinking that I cognize an object, but only through my
  9222. determining a given intuition in relation to the unity of consciousness
  9223. in which all thinking consists. It follows that I cognize myself, not
  9224. through my being conscious of myself as thinking, but only when I am
  9225. conscious of the intuition of myself as determined in relation to the
  9226. function of thought. All the modi of self-consciousness in thought
  9227. are hence not conceptions of objects (conceptions of the
  9228. understanding--categories); they are mere logical functions, which do
  9229. not present to thought an object to be cognized, and cannot therefore
  9230. present my Self as an object. Not the consciousness of the determining,
  9231. but only that of the determinable self, that is, of my internal
  9232. intuition (in so far as the manifold contained in it can be connected
  9233. conformably with the general condition of the unity of apperception in
  9234. thought), is the object.
  9235. 1. In all judgements I am the determining subject of that relation which
  9236. constitutes a judgement. But that the I which thinks, must be considered
  9237. as in thought always a subject, and as a thing which cannot be a
  9238. predicate to thought, is an apodeictic and identical proposition. But
  9239. this proposition does not signify that I, as an object, am, for
  9240. myself, a self-subsistent being or substance. This latter
  9241. statement--an ambitious one--requires to be supported by data which are
  9242. not to be discovered in thought; and are perhaps (in so far as I
  9243. consider the thinking self merely as such) not to be discovered in the
  9244. thinking self at all.
  9245. 2. That the I or Ego of apperception, and consequently in all thought,
  9246. is singular or simple, and cannot be resolved into a plurality of
  9247. subjects, and therefore indicates a logically simple subject--this is
  9248. self-evident from the very conception of an Ego, and is consequently an
  9249. analytical proposition. But this is not tantamount to declaring that
  9250. the thinking Ego is a simple substance--for this would be a synthetical
  9251. proposition. The conception of substance always relates to intuitions,
  9252. which with me cannot be other than sensuous, and which consequently lie
  9253. completely out of the sphere of the understanding and its thought:
  9254. but to this sphere belongs the affirmation that the Ego is simple
  9255. in thought. It would indeed be surprising, if the conception of
  9256. "substance," which in other cases requires so much labour to distinguish
  9257. from the other elements presented by intuition--so much trouble, too,
  9258. to discover whether it can be simple (as in the case of the parts of
  9259. matter)--should be presented immediately to me, as if by revelation, in
  9260. the poorest mental representation of all.
  9261. 3. The proposition of the identity of my Self amidst all the manifold
  9262. representations of which I am conscious, is likewise a proposition lying
  9263. in the conceptions themselves, and is consequently analytical. But
  9264. this identity of the subject, of which I am conscious in all its
  9265. representations, does not relate to or concern the intuition of the
  9266. subject, by which it is given as an object. This proposition cannot
  9267. therefore enounce the identity of the person, by which is understood the
  9268. consciousness of the identity of its own substance as a thinking being
  9269. in all change and variation of circumstances. To prove this, we
  9270. should require not a mere analysis of the proposition, but synthetical
  9271. judgements based upon a given intuition.
  9272. 4. I distinguish my own existence, as that of a thinking being, from
  9273. that of other things external to me--among which my body also is
  9274. reckoned. This is also an analytical proposition, for other things are
  9275. exactly those which I think as different or distinguished from myself.
  9276. But whether this consciousness of myself is possible without things
  9277. external to me; and whether therefore I can exist merely as a thinking
  9278. being (without being man)--cannot be known or inferred from this
  9279. proposition.
  9280. Thus we have gained nothing as regards the cognition of myself as
  9281. object, by the analysis of the consciousness of my Self in thought. The
  9282. logical exposition of thought in general is mistaken for a metaphysical
  9283. determination of the object.
  9284. Our Critique would be an investigation utterly superfluous, if there
  9285. existed a possibility of proving a priori, that all thinking beings
  9286. are in themselves simple substances, as such, therefore, possess
  9287. the inseparable attribute of personality, and are conscious of their
  9288. existence apart from and unconnected with matter. For we should thus
  9289. have taken a step beyond the world of sense, and have penetrated into
  9290. the sphere of noumena; and in this case the right could not be denied
  9291. us of extending our knowledge in this sphere, of establishing ourselves,
  9292. and, under a favouring star, appropriating to ourselves possessions
  9293. in it. For the proposition: "Every thinking being, as such, is simple
  9294. substance," is an a priori synthetical proposition; because in the first
  9295. place it goes beyond the conception which is the subject of it, and adds
  9296. to the mere notion of a thinking being the mode of its existence, and in
  9297. the second place annexes a predicate (that of simplicity) to the latter
  9298. conception--a predicate which it could not have discovered in the sphere
  9299. of experience. It would follow that a priori synthetical propositions
  9300. are possible and legitimate, not only, as we have maintained, in
  9301. relation to objects of possible experience, and as principles of the
  9302. possibility of this experience itself, but are applicable to things
  9303. in themselves--an inference which makes an end of the whole of this
  9304. Critique, and obliges us to fall back on the old mode of metaphysical
  9305. procedure. But indeed the danger is not so great, if we look a little
  9306. closer into the question.
  9307. There lurks in the procedure of rational Psychology a paralogism, which
  9308. is represented in the following syllogism:
  9309. That which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subject, does not exist
  9310. otherwise than as subject, and is therefore substance.
  9311. A thinking being, considered merely as such, cannot be cogitated
  9312. otherwise than as subject.
  9313. Therefore it exists also as such, that is, as substance.
  9314. In the major we speak of a being that can be cogitated generally and in
  9315. every relation, consequently as it may be given in intuition. But in the
  9316. minor we speak of the same being only in so far as it regards itself as
  9317. subject, relatively to thought and the unity of consciousness, but
  9318. not in relation to intuition, by which it is presented as an object to
  9319. thought. Thus the conclusion is here arrived at by a Sophisma figurae
  9320. dictionis.*
  9321. [*Footnote: Thought is taken in the two premisses in two totally
  9322. different senses. In the major it is considered as relating and applying
  9323. to objects in general, consequently to objects of intuition also. In
  9324. the minor, we understand it as relating merely to self-consciousness. In
  9325. this sense, we do not cogitate an object, but merely the relation to the
  9326. self-consciousness of the subject, as the form of thought. In the former
  9327. premiss we speak of things which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as
  9328. subjects. In the second, we do not speak of things, but of thought (all
  9329. objects being abstracted), in which the Ego is always the subject of
  9330. consciousness. Hence the conclusion cannot be, "I cannot exist otherwise
  9331. than as subject"; but only "I can, in cogitating my existence, employ
  9332. my Ego only as the subject of the judgement." But this is an identical
  9333. proposition, and throws no light on the mode of my existence.]
  9334. That this famous argument is a mere paralogism, will be plain to any one
  9335. who will consider the general remark which precedes our exposition of
  9336. the principles of the pure understanding, and the section on noumena.
  9337. For it was there proved that the conception of a thing, which can
  9338. exist per se--only as a subject and never as a predicate, possesses
  9339. no objective reality; that is to say, we can never know whether there
  9340. exists any object to correspond to the conception; consequently, the
  9341. conception is nothing more than a conception, and from it we derive
  9342. no proper knowledge. If this conception is to indicate by the term
  9343. substance, an object that can be given, if it is to become a cognition,
  9344. we must have at the foundation of the cognition a permanent intuition,
  9345. as the indispensable condition of its objective reality. For through
  9346. intuition alone can an object be given. But in internal intuition
  9347. there is nothing permanent, for the Ego is but the consciousness of my
  9348. thought. If then, we appeal merely to thought, we cannot discover
  9349. the necessary condition of the application of the conception of
  9350. substance--that is, of a subject existing per se--to the subject as
  9351. a thinking being. And thus the conception of the simple nature of
  9352. substance, which is connected with the objective reality of this
  9353. conception, is shown to be also invalid, and to be, in fact, nothing
  9354. more than the logical qualitative unity of self-consciousness in
  9355. thought; whilst we remain perfectly ignorant whether the subject is
  9356. composite or not.
  9357. Refutation of the Argument of Mendelssohn for the Substantiality or
  9358. Permanence of the Soul.
  9359. This acute philosopher easily perceived the insufficiency of the common
  9360. argument which attempts to prove that the soul--it being granted that it
  9361. is a simple being--cannot perish by dissolution or decomposition; he
  9362. saw it is not impossible for it to cease to be by extinction, or
  9363. disappearance. He endeavoured to prove in his Phaedo, that the soul
  9364. cannot be annihilated, by showing that a simple being cannot cease to
  9365. exist. Inasmuch as, he said, a simple existence cannot diminish, nor
  9366. gradually lose portions of its being, and thus be by degrees reduced
  9367. to nothing (for it possesses no parts, and therefore no multiplicity),
  9368. between the moment in which it is, and the moment in which it is not,
  9369. no time can be discovered--which is impossible. But this philosopher
  9370. did not consider that, granting the soul to possess this simple nature,
  9371. which contains no parts external to each other and consequently no
  9372. extensive quantity, we cannot refuse to it any less than to any other
  9373. being, intensive quantity, that is, a degree of reality in regard to
  9374. all its faculties, nay, to all that constitutes its existence. But this
  9375. degree of reality can become less and less through an infinite series
  9376. of smaller degrees. It follows, therefore, that this supposed
  9377. substance--this thing, the permanence of which is not assured in any
  9378. other way, may, if not by decomposition, by gradual loss (remissio)
  9379. of its powers (consequently by elanguescence, if I may employ this
  9380. expression), be changed into nothing. For consciousness itself has
  9381. always a degree, which may be lessened.* Consequently the faculty of
  9382. being conscious may be diminished; and so with all other faculties. The
  9383. permanence of the soul, therefore, as an object of the internal sense,
  9384. remains undemonstrated, nay, even indemonstrable. Its permanence in
  9385. life is evident, per se, inasmuch as the thinking being (as man) is to
  9386. itself, at the same time, an object of the external senses. But this
  9387. does not authorize the rational psychologist to affirm, from mere
  9388. conceptions, its permanence beyond life.*[2]
  9389. [*Footnote: Clearness is not, as logicians maintain, the consciousness
  9390. of a representation. For a certain degree of consciousness, which may
  9391. not, however, be sufficient for recollection, is to be met with in many
  9392. dim representations. For without any consciousness at all, we should not
  9393. be able to recognize any difference in the obscure representations we
  9394. connect; as we really can do with many conceptions, such as those
  9395. of right and justice, and those of the musician, who strikes at once
  9396. several notes in improvising a piece of music. But a representation is
  9397. clear, in which our consciousness is sufficient for the consciousness
  9398. of the difference of this representation from others. If we are only
  9399. conscious that there is a difference, but are not conscious of the
  9400. difference--that is, what the difference is--the representation must be
  9401. termed obscure. There is, consequently, an infinite series of degrees of
  9402. consciousness down to its entire disappearance.]
  9403. [*[2]Footnote: There are some who think they have done enough to
  9404. establish a new possibility in the mode of the existence of souls, when
  9405. they have shown that there is no contradiction in their hypotheses on
  9406. this subject. Such are those who affirm the possibility of thought--of
  9407. which they have no other knowledge than what they derive from its use in
  9408. connecting empirical intuitions presented in this our human life--after
  9409. this life has ceased. But it is very easy to embarrass them by the
  9410. introduction of counter-possibilities, which rest upon quite as good a
  9411. foundation. Such, for example, is the possibility of the division of
  9412. a simple substance into several substances; and conversely, of
  9413. the coalition of several into one simple substance. For, although
  9414. divisibility presupposes composition, it does not necessarily require
  9415. a composition of substances, but only of the degrees (of the several
  9416. faculties) of one and the same substance. Now we can cogitate all
  9417. the powers and faculties of the soul--even that of consciousness--as
  9418. diminished by one half, the substance still remaining. In the same way
  9419. we can represent to ourselves without contradiction, this obliterated
  9420. half as preserved, not in the soul, but without it; and we can believe
  9421. that, as in this case every thing that is real in the soul, and has a
  9422. degree--consequently its entire existence--has been halved, a particular
  9423. substance would arise out of the soul. For the multiplicity, which has
  9424. been divided, formerly existed, but not as a multiplicity of substances,
  9425. but of every reality as the quantum of existence in it; and the unity of
  9426. substance was merely a mode of existence, which by this division alone
  9427. has been transformed into a plurality of subsistence. In the same manner
  9428. several simple substances might coalesce into one, without anything
  9429. being lost except the plurality of subsistence, inasmuch as the
  9430. one substance would contain the degree of reality of all the former
  9431. substances. Perhaps, indeed, the simple substances, which appear under
  9432. the form of matter, might (not indeed by a mechanical or chemical
  9433. influence upon each other, but by an unknown influence, of which the
  9434. former would be but the phenomenal appearance), by means of such a
  9435. dynamical division of the parent-souls, as intensive quantities, produce
  9436. other souls, while the former repaired the loss thus sustained with
  9437. new matter of the same sort. I am far from allowing any value to such
  9438. chimeras; and the principles of our analytic have clearly proved that
  9439. no other than an empirical use of the categories--that of substance,
  9440. for example--is possible. But if the rationalist is bold enough to
  9441. construct, on the mere authority of the faculty of thought--without any
  9442. intuition, whereby an object is given--a self-subsistent being, merely
  9443. because the unity of apperception in thought cannot allow him to believe
  9444. it a composite being, instead of declaring, as he ought to do, that he
  9445. is unable to explain the possibility of a thinking nature; what ought to
  9446. hinder the materialist, with as complete an independence of experience,
  9447. to employ the principle of the rationalist in a directly opposite
  9448. manner--still preserving the formal unity required by his opponent?]
  9449. If, now, we take the above propositions--as they must be accepted as
  9450. valid for all thinking beings in the system of rational psychology--in
  9451. synthetical connection, and proceed, from the category of relation,
  9452. with the proposition: "All thinking beings are, as such, substances,"
  9453. backwards through the series, till the circle is completed; we come
  9454. at last to their existence, of which, in this system of rational
  9455. psychology, substances are held to be conscious, independently of
  9456. external things; nay, it is asserted that, in relation to the permanence
  9457. which is a necessary characteristic of substance, they can of
  9458. themselves determine external things. It follows that idealism--at least
  9459. problematical idealism, is perfectly unavoidable in this rationalistic
  9460. system. And, if the existence of outward things is not held to be
  9461. requisite to the determination of the existence of a substance in time,
  9462. the existence of these outward things at all, is a gratuitous assumption
  9463. which remains without the possibility of a proof.
  9464. But if we proceed analytically--the "I think" as a proposition
  9465. containing in itself an existence as given, consequently modality being
  9466. the principle--and dissect this proposition, in order to ascertain its
  9467. content, and discover whether and how this Ego determines its existence
  9468. in time and space without the aid of anything external; the propositions
  9469. of rationalistic psychology would not begin with the conception of a
  9470. thinking being, but with a reality, and the properties of a thinking
  9471. being in general would be deduced from the mode in which this reality is
  9472. cogitated, after everything empirical had been abstracted; as is shown
  9473. in the following table:
  9474. 1
  9475. I think,
  9476. 2 3
  9477. as Subject, as simple Subject,
  9478. 4
  9479. as identical Subject,
  9480. in every state of my thought.
  9481. Now, inasmuch as it is not determined in this second proposition,
  9482. whether I can exist and be cogitated only as subject, and not also as a
  9483. predicate of another being, the conception of a subject is here taken in
  9484. a merely logical sense; and it remains undetermined, whether substance
  9485. is to be cogitated under the conception or not. But in the third
  9486. proposition, the absolute unity of apperception--the simple Ego in the
  9487. representation to which all connection and separation, which constitute
  9488. thought, relate, is of itself important; even although it presents
  9489. us with no information about the constitution or subsistence of the
  9490. subject. Apperception is something real, and the simplicity of its
  9491. nature is given in the very fact of its possibility. Now in space there
  9492. is nothing real that is at the same time simple; for points, which are
  9493. the only simple things in space, are merely limits, but not constituent
  9494. parts of space. From this follows the impossibility of a definition
  9495. on the basis of materialism of the constitution of my Ego as a merely
  9496. thinking subject. But, because my existence is considered in the first
  9497. proposition as given, for it does not mean, "Every thinking being
  9498. exists" (for this would be predicating of them absolute necessity),
  9499. but only, "I exist thinking"; the proposition is quite empirical, and
  9500. contains the determinability of my existence merely in relation to my
  9501. representations in time. But as I require for this purpose something
  9502. that is permanent, such as is not given in internal intuition; the
  9503. mode of my existence, whether as substance or as accident, cannot
  9504. be determined by means of this simple self-consciousness. Thus,
  9505. if materialism is inadequate to explain the mode in which I exist,
  9506. spiritualism is likewise as insufficient; and the conclusion is that we
  9507. are utterly unable to attain to any knowledge of the constitution of
  9508. the soul, in so far as relates to the possibility of its existence apart
  9509. from external objects.
  9510. And, indeed, how should it be possible, merely by the aid of the unity
  9511. of consciousness--which we cognize only for the reason that it is
  9512. indispensable to the possibility of experience--to pass the bounds of
  9513. experience (our existence in this life); and to extend our cognition
  9514. to the nature of all thinking beings by means of the empirical--but
  9515. in relation to every sort of intuition, perfectly undetermined--proposition,
  9516. "I think"?
  9517. There does not then exist any rational psychology as a doctrine
  9518. furnishing any addition to our knowledge of ourselves. It is nothing
  9519. more than a discipline, which sets impassable limits to speculative
  9520. reason in this region of thought, to prevent it, on the one hand, from
  9521. throwing itself into the arms of a soulless materialism, and, on the
  9522. other, from losing itself in the mazes of a baseless spiritualism.
  9523. It teaches us to consider this refusal of our reason to give any
  9524. satisfactory answer to questions which reach beyond the limits of this
  9525. our human life, as a hint to abandon fruitless speculation; and to
  9526. direct, to a practical use, our knowledge of ourselves--which, although
  9527. applicable only to objects of experience, receives its principles from a
  9528. higher source, and regulates its procedure as if our destiny reached far
  9529. beyond the boundaries of experience and life.
  9530. From all this it is evident that rational psychology has its origin in
  9531. a mere misunderstanding. The unity of consciousness, which lies at the
  9532. basis of the categories, is considered to be an intuition of the subject
  9533. as an object; and the category of substance is applied to the intuition.
  9534. But this unity is nothing more than the unity in thought, by which no
  9535. object is given; to which therefore the category of substance--which
  9536. always presupposes a given intuition--cannot be applied. Consequently,
  9537. the subject cannot be cognized. The subject of the categories cannot,
  9538. therefore, for the very reason that it cogitates these, frame any
  9539. conception of itself as an object of the categories; for, to
  9540. cogitate these, it must lay at the foundation its own pure
  9541. self-consciousness--the very thing that it wishes to explain and
  9542. describe. In like manner, the subject, in which the representation of
  9543. time has its basis, cannot determine, for this very reason, its own
  9544. existence in time. Now, if the latter is impossible, the former, as an
  9545. attempt to determine itself by means of the categories as a thinking
  9546. being in general, is no less so.*
  9547. [*Footnote: The "I think" is, as has been already stated, an empirical
  9548. proposition, and contains the proposition, "I exist." But I cannot say,
  9549. "Everything, which thinks, exists"; for in this case the property of
  9550. thought would constitute all beings possessing it, necessary beings.
  9551. Hence my existence cannot be considered as an inference from the
  9552. proposition, "I think," as Descartes maintained--because in this case
  9553. the major premiss, "Everything, which thinks, exists," must precede--but
  9554. the two propositions are identical. The proposition, "I think,"
  9555. expresses an undetermined empirical intuition, that perception (proving
  9556. consequently that sensation, which must belong to sensibility, lies at
  9557. the foundation of this proposition); but it precedes experience, whose
  9558. province it is to determine an object of perception by means of the
  9559. categories in relation to time; and existence in this proposition is not
  9560. a category, as it does not apply to an undetermined given object, but
  9561. only to one of which we have a conception, and about which we wish to
  9562. know whether it does or does not exist, out of, and apart from this
  9563. conception. An undetermined perception signifies here merely something
  9564. real that has been given, only, however, to thought in general--but
  9565. not as a phenomenon, nor as a thing in itself (noumenon), but only
  9566. as something that really exists, and is designated as such in the
  9567. proposition, "I think." For it must be remarked that, when I call the
  9568. proposition, "I think," an empirical proposition, I do not thereby mean
  9569. that the Ego in the proposition is an empirical representation; on the
  9570. contrary, it is purely intellectual, because it belongs to thought in
  9571. general. But without some empirical representation, which presents to
  9572. the mind material for thought, the mental act, "I think," would not take
  9573. place; and the empirical is only the condition of the application or
  9574. employment of the pure intellectual faculty.]
  9575. Thus, then, appears the vanity of the hope of establishing a cognition
  9576. which is to extend its rule beyond the limits of experience--a cognition
  9577. which is one of the highest interests of humanity; and thus is proved
  9578. the futility of the attempt of speculative philosophy in this region of
  9579. thought. But, in this interest of thought, the severity of criticism has
  9580. rendered to reason a not unimportant service, by the demonstration of
  9581. the impossibility of making any dogmatical affirmation concerning an
  9582. object of experience beyond the boundaries of experience. She has thus
  9583. fortified reason against all affirmations of the contrary. Now, this can
  9584. be accomplished in only two ways. Either our proposition must be
  9585. proved apodeictically; or, if this is unsuccessful, the sources of this
  9586. inability must be sought for, and, if these are discovered to exist in
  9587. the natural and necessary limitation of our reason, our opponents must
  9588. submit to the same law of renunciation and refrain from advancing claims
  9589. to dogmatic assertion.
  9590. But the right, say rather the necessity to admit a future life, upon
  9591. principles of the practical conjoined with the speculative use
  9592. of reason, has lost nothing by this renunciation; for the merely
  9593. speculative proof has never had any influence upon the common reason of
  9594. men. It stands upon the point of a hair, so that even the schools have
  9595. been able to preserve it from falling only by incessantly discussing
  9596. it and spinning it like a top; and even in their eyes it has never been
  9597. able to present any safe foundation for the erection of a theory.
  9598. The proofs which have been current among men, preserve their value
  9599. undiminished; nay, rather gain in clearness and unsophisticated power,
  9600. by the rejection of the dogmatical assumptions of speculative reason.
  9601. For reason is thus confined within her own peculiar province--the
  9602. arrangement of ends or aims, which is at the same time the arrangement
  9603. of nature; and, as a practical faculty, without limiting itself to the
  9604. latter, it is justified in extending the former, and with it our own
  9605. existence, beyond the boundaries of experience and life. If we turn our
  9606. attention to the analogy of the nature of living beings in this world,
  9607. in the consideration of which reason is obliged to accept as a principle
  9608. that no organ, no faculty, no appetite is useless, and that nothing is
  9609. superfluous, nothing disproportionate to its use, nothing unsuited to
  9610. its end; but that, on the contrary, everything is perfectly conformed to
  9611. its destination in life--we shall find that man, who alone is the final
  9612. end and aim of this order, is still the only animal that seems to be
  9613. excepted from it. For his natural gifts--not merely as regards the
  9614. talents and motives that may incite him to employ them, but especially
  9615. the moral law in him--stretch so far beyond all mere earthly utility and
  9616. advantage, that he feels himself bound to prize the mere consciousness
  9617. of probity, apart from all advantageous consequences--even the shadowy
  9618. gift of posthumous fame--above everything; and he is conscious of an
  9619. inward call to constitute himself, by his conduct in this world--without
  9620. regard to mere sublunary interests--the citizen of a better. This
  9621. mighty, irresistible proof--accompanied by an ever-increasing knowledge
  9622. of the conformability to a purpose in everything we see around us,
  9623. by the conviction of the boundless immensity of creation, by the
  9624. consciousness of a certain illimitableness in the possible extension
  9625. of our knowledge, and by a desire commensurate therewith--remains to
  9626. humanity, even after the theoretical cognition of ourselves has failed
  9627. to establish the necessity of an existence after death.
  9628. Conclusion of the Solution of the Psychological Paralogism.
  9629. The dialectical illusion in rational psychology arises from our
  9630. confounding an idea of reason (of a pure intelligence) with the
  9631. conception--in every respect undetermined--of a thinking being in
  9632. general. I cogitate myself in behalf of a possible experience, at
  9633. the same time making abstraction of all actual experience; and infer
  9634. therefrom that I can be conscious of myself apart from experience
  9635. and its empirical conditions. I consequently confound the possible
  9636. abstraction of my empirically determined existence with the supposed
  9637. consciousness of a possible separate existence of my thinking self;
  9638. and I believe that I cognize what is substantial in myself as a
  9639. transcendental subject, when I have nothing more in thought than the
  9640. unity of consciousness, which lies at the basis of all determination of
  9641. cognition.
  9642. The task of explaining the community of the soul with the body does not
  9643. properly belong to the psychology of which we are here speaking;
  9644. because it proposes to prove the personality of the soul apart from this
  9645. communion (after death), and is therefore transcendent in the proper
  9646. sense of the word, although occupying itself with an object of
  9647. experience--only in so far, however, as it ceases to be an object of
  9648. experience. But a sufficient answer may be found to the question in
  9649. our system. The difficulty which lies in the execution of this task
  9650. consists, as is well known, in the presupposed heterogeneity of the
  9651. object of the internal sense (the soul) and the objects of the external
  9652. senses; inasmuch as the formal condition of the intuition of the one is
  9653. time, and of that of the other space also. But if we consider that both
  9654. kinds of objects do not differ internally, but only in so far as the
  9655. one appears externally to the other--consequently, that what lies at the
  9656. basis of phenomena, as a thing in itself, may not be heterogeneous; this
  9657. difficulty disappears. There then remains no other difficulty than is to
  9658. be found in the question--how a community of substances is possible;
  9659. a question which lies out of the region of psychology, and which the
  9660. reader, after what in our analytic has been said of primitive forces
  9661. and faculties, will easily judge to be also beyond the region of human
  9662. cognition.
  9663. GENERAL REMARK
  9664. On the Transition from Rational Psychology to Cosmology.
  9665. The proposition, "I think," or, "I exist thinking," is an empirical
  9666. proposition. But such a proposition must be based on empirical
  9667. intuition, and the object cogitated as a phenomenon; and thus our
  9668. theory appears to maintain that the soul, even in thought, is merely
  9669. a phenomenon; and in this way our consciousness itself, in fact, abuts
  9670. upon nothing.
  9671. Thought, per se, is merely the purely spontaneous logical function which
  9672. operates to connect the manifold of a possible intuition; and it does
  9673. not represent the subject of consciousness as a phenomenon--for this
  9674. reason alone, that it pays no attention to the question whether the
  9675. mode of intuiting it is sensuous or intellectual. I therefore do not
  9676. represent myself in thought either as I am, or as I appear to myself; I
  9677. merely cogitate myself as an object in general, of the mode of intuiting
  9678. which I make abstraction. When I represent myself as the subject of
  9679. thought, or as the ground of thought, these modes of representation are
  9680. not related to the categories of substance or of cause; for these are
  9681. functions of thought applicable only to our sensuous intuition. The
  9682. application of these categories to the Ego would, however, be necessary,
  9683. if I wished to make myself an object of knowledge. But I wish to be
  9684. conscious of myself only as thinking; in what mode my Self is given
  9685. in intuition, I do not consider, and it may be that I, who think, am a
  9686. phenomenon--although not in so far as I am a thinking being; but in
  9687. the consciousness of myself in mere thought I am a being, though this
  9688. consciousness does not present to me any property of this being as
  9689. material for thought.
  9690. But the proposition, "I think," in so far as it declares, "I exist
  9691. thinking," is not the mere representation of a logical function.
  9692. It determines the subject (which is in this case an object also) in
  9693. relation to existence; and it cannot be given without the aid of the
  9694. internal sense, whose intuition presents to us an object, not as a thing
  9695. in itself, but always as a phenomenon. In this proposition there is
  9696. therefore something more to be found than the mere spontaneity of
  9697. thought; there is also the receptivity of intuition, that is, my thought
  9698. of myself applied to the empirical intuition of myself. Now, in this
  9699. intuition the thinking self must seek the conditions of the employment
  9700. of its logical functions as categories of substance, cause, and so
  9701. forth; not merely for the purpose of distinguishing itself as an object
  9702. in itself by means of the representation "I," but also for the purpose
  9703. of determining the mode of its existence, that is, of cognizing
  9704. itself as noumenon. But this is impossible, for the internal empirical
  9705. intuition is sensuous, and presents us with nothing but phenomenal data,
  9706. which do not assist the object of pure consciousness in its attempt
  9707. to cognize itself as a separate existence, but are useful only as
  9708. contributions to experience.
  9709. But, let it be granted that we could discover, not in experience, but in
  9710. certain firmly-established a priori laws of the use of pure reason--laws
  9711. relating to our existence, authority to consider ourselves as
  9712. legislating a priori in relation to our own existence and as determining
  9713. this existence; we should, on this supposition, find ourselves possessed
  9714. of a spontaneity, by which our actual existence would be determinable,
  9715. without the aid of the conditions of empirical intuition. We should also
  9716. become aware that in the consciousness of our existence there was an
  9717. a priori content, which would serve to determine our own existence--an
  9718. existence only sensuously determinable--relatively, however, to a
  9719. certain internal faculty in relation to an intelligible world.
  9720. But this would not give the least help to the attempts of rational
  9721. psychology. For this wonderful faculty, which the consciousness of
  9722. the moral law in me reveals, would present me with a principle of the
  9723. determination of my own existence which is purely intellectual--but by
  9724. what predicates? By none other than those which are given in sensuous
  9725. intuition. Thus I should find myself in the same position in rational
  9726. psychology which I formerly occupied, that is to say, I should
  9727. find myself still in need of sensuous intuitions, in order to give
  9728. significance to my conceptions of substance and cause, by means of which
  9729. alone I can possess a knowledge of myself: but these intuitions can
  9730. never raise me above the sphere of experience. I should be justified,
  9731. however, in applying these conceptions, in regard to their practical
  9732. use, which is always directed to objects of experience--in conformity
  9733. with their analogical significance when employed theoretically--to
  9734. freedom and its subject. At the same time, I should understand by them
  9735. merely the logical functions of subject and predicate, of principle and
  9736. consequence, in conformity with which all actions are so determined,
  9737. that they are capable of being explained along with the laws of nature,
  9738. conformably to the categories of substance and cause, although
  9739. they originate from a very different principle. We have made these
  9740. observations for the purpose of guarding against misunderstanding, to
  9741. which the doctrine of our intuition of self as a phenomenon is exposed.
  9742. We shall have occasion to perceive their utility in the sequel.
  9743. CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason.
  9744. We showed in the introduction to this part of our work, that all
  9745. transcendental illusion of pure reason arose from dialectical arguments,
  9746. the schema of which logic gives us in its three formal species of
  9747. syllogisms--just as the categories find their logical schema in the
  9748. four functions of all judgements. The first kind of these sophistical
  9749. arguments related to the unconditioned unity of the subjective
  9750. conditions of all representations in general (of the subject or soul),
  9751. in correspondence with the categorical syllogisms, the major of which,
  9752. as the principle, enounces the relation of a predicate to a subject.
  9753. The second kind of dialectical argument will therefore be concerned,
  9754. following the analogy with hypothetical syllogisms, with the
  9755. unconditioned unity of the objective conditions in the phenomenon;
  9756. and, in this way, the theme of the third kind to be treated of in the
  9757. following chapter will be the unconditioned unity of the objective
  9758. conditions of the possibility of objects in general.
  9759. But it is worthy of remark that the transcendental paralogism produced
  9760. in the mind only a one-third illusion, in regard to the idea of the
  9761. subject of our thought; and the conceptions of reason gave no ground to
  9762. maintain the contrary proposition. The advantage is completely on the
  9763. side of Pneumatism; although this theory itself passes into naught, in
  9764. the crucible of pure reason.
  9765. Very different is the case when we apply reason to the objective
  9766. synthesis of phenomena. Here, certainly, reason establishes, with much
  9767. plausibility, its principle of unconditioned unity; but it very soon
  9768. falls into such contradictions that it is compelled, in relation to
  9769. cosmology, to renounce its pretensions.
  9770. For here a new phenomenon of human reason meets us--a perfectly natural
  9771. antithetic, which does not require to be sought for by subtle sophistry,
  9772. but into which reason of itself unavoidably falls. It is thereby
  9773. preserved, to be sure, from the slumber of a fancied conviction--which
  9774. a merely one-sided illusion produces; but it is at the same time
  9775. compelled, either, on the one hand, to abandon itself to a despairing
  9776. scepticism, or, on the other, to assume a dogmatical confidence and
  9777. obstinate persistence in certain assertions, without granting a fair
  9778. hearing to the other side of the question. Either is the death of a
  9779. sound philosophy, although the former might perhaps deserve the title of
  9780. the euthanasia of pure reason.
  9781. Before entering this region of discord and confusion, which the conflict
  9782. of the laws of pure reason (antinomy) produces, we shall present the
  9783. reader with some considerations, in explanation and justification of the
  9784. method we intend to follow in our treatment of this subject. I term all
  9785. transcendental ideas, in so far as they relate to the absolute totality
  9786. in the synthesis of phenomena, cosmical conceptions; partly on
  9787. account of this unconditioned totality, on which the conception of the
  9788. world-whole is based--a conception, which is itself an idea--partly
  9789. because they relate solely to the synthesis of phenomena--the empirical
  9790. synthesis; while, on the other hand, the absolute totality in the
  9791. synthesis of the conditions of all possible things gives rise to
  9792. an ideal of pure reason, which is quite distinct from the cosmical
  9793. conception, although it stands in relation with it. Hence, as the
  9794. paralogisms of pure reason laid the foundation for a dialectical
  9795. psychology, the antinomy of pure reason will present us with the
  9796. transcendental principles of a pretended pure (rational) cosmology--not,
  9797. however, to declare it valid and to appropriate it, but--as the very
  9798. term of a conflict of reason sufficiently indicates, to present it as an
  9799. idea which cannot be reconciled with phenomena and experience.
  9800. SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas.
  9801. That We may be able to enumerate with systematic precision these ideas
  9802. according to a principle, we must remark, in the first place, that it
  9803. is from the understanding alone that pure and transcendental conceptions
  9804. take their origin; that the reason does not properly give birth to any
  9805. conception, but only frees the conception of the understanding from the
  9806. unavoidable limitation of a possible experience, and thus endeavours to
  9807. raise it above the empirical, though it must still be in connection with
  9808. it. This happens from the fact that, for a given conditioned, reason
  9809. demands absolute totality on the side of the conditions (to which the
  9810. understanding submits all phenomena), and thus makes of the category a
  9811. transcendental idea. This it does that it may be able to give absolute
  9812. completeness to the empirical synthesis, by continuing it to the
  9813. unconditioned (which is not to be found in experience, but only in
  9814. the idea). Reason requires this according to the principle: If the
  9815. conditioned is given the whole of the conditions, and consequently the
  9816. absolutely unconditioned, is also given, whereby alone the former was
  9817. possible. First, then, the transcendental ideas are properly nothing but
  9818. categories elevated to the unconditioned; and they may be arranged in
  9819. a table according to the titles of the latter. But, secondly, all the
  9820. categories are not available for this purpose, but only those in which
  9821. the synthesis constitutes a series--of conditions subordinated to, not
  9822. co-ordinated with, each other. Absolute totality is required of reason
  9823. only in so far as concerns the ascending series of the conditions of
  9824. a conditioned; not, consequently, when the question relates to
  9825. the descending series of consequences, or to the aggregate of the
  9826. co-ordinated conditions of these consequences. For, in relation to a
  9827. given conditioned, conditions are presupposed and considered to be given
  9828. along with it. On the other hand, as the consequences do not render
  9829. possible their conditions, but rather presuppose them--in the
  9830. consideration of the procession of consequences (or in the descent from
  9831. the given condition to the conditioned), we may be quite unconcerned
  9832. whether the series ceases or not; and their totality is not a necessary
  9833. demand of reason.
  9834. Thus we cogitate--and necessarily--a given time completely elapsed up
  9835. to a given moment, although that time is not determinable by us. But
  9836. as regards time future, which is not the condition of arriving at the
  9837. present, in order to conceive it; it is quite indifferent whether we
  9838. consider future time as ceasing at some point, or as prolonging itself
  9839. to infinity. Take, for example, the series m, n, o, in which n is given
  9840. as conditioned in relation to m, but at the same time as the condition
  9841. of o, and let the series proceed upwards from the conditioned n to m (l,
  9842. k, i, etc.), and also downwards from the condition n to the conditioned
  9843. o (p, q, r, etc.)--I must presuppose the former series, to be able
  9844. to consider n as given, and n is according to reason (the totality of
  9845. conditions) possible only by means of that series. But its possibility
  9846. does not rest on the following series o, p, q, r, which for this
  9847. reason cannot be regarded as given, but only as capable of being given
  9848. (dabilis).
  9849. I shall term the synthesis of the series on the side of the
  9850. conditions--from that nearest to the given phenomenon up to the more
  9851. remote--regressive; that which proceeds on the side of the conditioned,
  9852. from the immediate consequence to the more remote, I shall call the
  9853. progressive synthesis. The former proceeds in antecedentia, the latter
  9854. in consequentia. The cosmological ideas are therefore occupied with the
  9855. totality of the regressive synthesis, and proceed in antecedentia, not
  9856. in consequentia. When the latter takes place, it is an arbitrary and
  9857. not a necessary problem of pure reason; for we require, for the complete
  9858. understanding of what is given in a phenomenon, not the consequences
  9859. which succeed, but the grounds or principles which precede.
  9860. In order to construct the table of ideas in correspondence with the
  9861. table of categories, we take first the two primitive quanta of all our
  9862. intuitions, time and space. Time is in itself a series (and the formal
  9863. condition of all series), and hence, in relation to a given present,
  9864. we must distinguish a priori in it the antecedentia as conditions
  9865. (time past) from the consequentia (time future). Consequently, the
  9866. transcendental idea of the absolute totality of the series of the
  9867. conditions of a given conditioned, relates merely to all past time.
  9868. According to the idea of reason, the whole past time, as the condition
  9869. of the given moment, is necessarily cogitated as given. But, as
  9870. regards space, there exists in it no distinction between progressus and
  9871. regressus; for it is an aggregate and not a series--its parts existing
  9872. together at the same time. I can consider a given point of time in
  9873. relation to past time only as conditioned, because this given moment
  9874. comes into existence only through the past time rather through the
  9875. passing of the preceding time. But as the parts of space are not
  9876. subordinated, but co-ordinated to each other, one part cannot be the
  9877. condition of the possibility of the other; and space is not in itself,
  9878. like time, a series. But the synthesis of the manifold parts of
  9879. space--(the syntheses whereby we apprehend space)--is nevertheless
  9880. successive; it takes place, therefore, in time, and contains a series.
  9881. And as in this series of aggregated spaces (for example, the feet in a
  9882. rood), beginning with a given portion of space, those which continue
  9883. to be annexed form the condition of the limits of the former--the
  9884. measurement of a space must also be regarded as a synthesis of the
  9885. series of the conditions of a given conditioned. It differs, however, in
  9886. this respect from that of time, that the side of the conditioned is
  9887. not in itself distinguishable from the side of the condition; and,
  9888. consequently, regressus and progressus in space seem to be identical.
  9889. But, inasmuch as one part of space is not given, but only limited,
  9890. by and through another, we must also consider every limited space
  9891. as conditioned, in so far as it presupposes some other space as
  9892. the condition of its limitation, and so on. As regards limitation,
  9893. therefore, our procedure in space is also a regressus, and the
  9894. transcendental idea of the absolute totality of the synthesis in a
  9895. series of conditions applies to space also; and I am entitled to demand
  9896. the absolute totality of the phenomenal synthesis in space as well as in
  9897. time. Whether my demand can be satisfied is a question to be answered in
  9898. the sequel.
  9899. Secondly, the real in space--that is, matter--is conditioned. Its
  9900. internal conditions are its parts, and the parts of parts its remote
  9901. conditions; so that in this case we find a regressive synthesis, the
  9902. absolute totality of which is a demand of reason. But this cannot be
  9903. obtained otherwise than by a complete division of parts, whereby the
  9904. real in matter becomes either nothing or that which is not matter,
  9905. that is to say, the simple. Consequently we find here also a series of
  9906. conditions and a progress to the unconditioned.
  9907. Thirdly, as regards the categories of a real relation between phenomena,
  9908. the category of substance and its accidents is not suitable for the
  9909. formation of a transcendental idea; that is to say, reason has no
  9910. ground, in regard to it, to proceed regressively with conditions. For
  9911. accidents (in so far as they inhere in a substance) are co-ordinated
  9912. with each other, and do not constitute a series. And, in relation to
  9913. substance, they are not properly subordinated to it, but are the mode
  9914. of existence of the substance itself. The conception of the substantial
  9915. might nevertheless seem to be an idea of the transcendental reason.
  9916. But, as this signifies nothing more than the conception of an object
  9917. in general, which subsists in so far as we cogitate in it merely a
  9918. transcendental subject without any predicates; and as the question here
  9919. is of an unconditioned in the series of phenomena--it is clear that
  9920. the substantial can form no member thereof. The same holds good of
  9921. substances in community, which are mere aggregates and do not form a
  9922. series. For they are not subordinated to each other as conditions of the
  9923. possibility of each other; which, however, may be affirmed of spaces,
  9924. the limits of which are never determined in themselves, but always by
  9925. some other space. It is, therefore, only in the category of causality
  9926. that we can find a series of causes to a given effect, and in which
  9927. we ascend from the latter, as the conditioned, to the former as the
  9928. conditions, and thus answer the question of reason.
  9929. Fourthly, the conceptions of the possible, the actual, and the necessary
  9930. do not conduct us to any series--excepting only in so far as the
  9931. contingent in existence must always be regarded as conditioned, and as
  9932. indicating, according to a law of the understanding, a condition, under
  9933. which it is necessary to rise to a higher, till in the totality of the
  9934. series, reason arrives at unconditioned necessity.
  9935. There are, accordingly, only four cosmological ideas, corresponding
  9936. with the four titles of the categories. For we can select only such as
  9937. necessarily furnish us with a series in the synthesis of the manifold.
  9938. 1
  9939. The absolute Completeness
  9940. of the
  9941. COMPOSITION
  9942. of the given totality of all phenomena.
  9943. 2
  9944. The absolute Completeness
  9945. of the
  9946. DIVISION
  9947. of given totality in a phenomenon.
  9948. 3
  9949. The absolute Completeness
  9950. of the
  9951. ORIGINATION
  9952. of a phenomenon.
  9953. 4
  9954. The absolute Completeness
  9955. of the DEPENDENCE of the EXISTENCE
  9956. of what is changeable in a phenomenon.
  9957. We must here remark, in the first place, that the idea of absolute
  9958. totality relates to nothing but the exposition of phenomena, and
  9959. therefore not to the pure conception of a totality of things. Phenomena
  9960. are here, therefore, regarded as given, and reason requires the absolute
  9961. completeness of the conditions of their possibility, in so far as these
  9962. conditions constitute a series--consequently an absolutely (that is, in
  9963. every respect) complete synthesis, whereby a phenomenon can be explained
  9964. according to the laws of the understanding.
  9965. Secondly, it is properly the unconditioned alone that reason seeks in
  9966. this serially and regressively conducted synthesis of conditions. It
  9967. wishes, to speak in another way, to attain to completeness in the series
  9968. of premisses, so as to render it unnecessary to presuppose others.
  9969. This unconditioned is always contained in the absolute totality of the
  9970. series, when we endeavour to form a representation of it in thought.
  9971. But this absolutely complete synthesis is itself but an idea; for it is
  9972. impossible, at least before hand, to know whether any such synthesis is
  9973. possible in the case of phenomena. When we represent all existence in
  9974. thought by means of pure conceptions of the understanding, without any
  9975. conditions of sensuous intuition, we may say with justice that for a
  9976. given conditioned the whole series of conditions subordinated to each
  9977. other is also given; for the former is only given through the latter.
  9978. But we find in the case of phenomena a particular limitation of the mode
  9979. in which conditions are given, that is, through the successive synthesis
  9980. of the manifold of intuition, which must be complete in the regress. Now
  9981. whether this completeness is sensuously possible, is a problem. But the
  9982. idea of it lies in the reason--be it possible or impossible to connect
  9983. with the idea adequate empirical conceptions. Therefore, as in the
  9984. absolute totality of the regressive synthesis of the manifold in a
  9985. phenomenon (following the guidance of the categories, which represent it
  9986. as a series of conditions to a given conditioned) the unconditioned is
  9987. necessarily contained--it being still left unascertained whether and
  9988. how this totality exists; reason sets out from the idea of totality,
  9989. although its proper and final aim is the unconditioned--of the whole
  9990. series, or of a part thereof.
  9991. This unconditioned may be cogitated--either as existing only in the
  9992. entire series, all the members of which therefore would be
  9993. without exception conditioned and only the totality absolutely
  9994. unconditioned--and in this case the regressus is called infinite; or
  9995. the absolutely unconditioned is only a part of the series, to which the
  9996. other members are subordinated, but which Is not itself submitted to
  9997. any other condition.* In the former case the series is a parte priori
  9998. unlimited (without beginning), that is, infinite, and nevertheless
  9999. completely given. But the regress in it is never completed, and can only
  10000. be called potentially infinite. In the second case there exists a first
  10001. in the series. This first is called, in relation to past time, the
  10002. beginning of the world; in relation to space, the limit of the world; in
  10003. relation to the parts of a given limited whole, the simple; in relation
  10004. to causes, absolute spontaneity (liberty); and in relation to the
  10005. existence of changeable things, absolute physical necessity.
  10006. [*Footnote: The absolute totality of the series of conditions to a given
  10007. conditioned is always unconditioned; because beyond it there exist no
  10008. other conditions, on which it might depend. But the absolute totality of
  10009. such a series is only an idea, or rather a problematical conception, the
  10010. possibility of which must be investigated--particularly in relation to
  10011. the mode in which the unconditioned, as the transcendental idea which is
  10012. the real subject of inquiry, may be contained therein.]
  10013. We possess two expressions, world and nature, which are generally
  10014. interchanged. The first denotes the mathematical total of all phenomena
  10015. and the totality of their synthesis--in its progress by means of
  10016. composition, as well as by division. And the world is termed nature,*
  10017. when it is regarded as a dynamical whole--when our attention is not
  10018. directed to the aggregation in space and time, for the purpose of
  10019. cogitating it as a quantity, but to the unity in the existence of
  10020. phenomena. In this case the condition of that which happens is called
  10021. a cause; the unconditioned causality of the cause in a phenomenon is
  10022. termed liberty; the conditioned cause is called in a more limited sense
  10023. a natural cause. The conditioned in existence is termed contingent, and
  10024. the unconditioned necessary. The unconditioned necessity of phenomena
  10025. may be called natural necessity.
  10026. [*Footnote: Nature, understood adjective (formaliter), signifies the
  10027. complex of the determinations of a thing, connected according to an
  10028. internal principle of causality. On the other hand, we understand by
  10029. nature, substantive (materialiter), the sum total of phenomena, in
  10030. so far as they, by virtue of an internal principle of causality, are
  10031. connected with each other throughout. In the former sense we speak of
  10032. the nature of liquid matter, of fire, etc., and employ the word only
  10033. adjective; while, if speaking of the objects of nature, we have in our
  10034. minds the idea of a subsisting whole.]
  10035. The ideas which we are at present engaged in discussing I have called
  10036. cosmological ideas; partly because by the term world is understood the
  10037. entire content of all phenomena, and our ideas are directed solely to
  10038. the unconditioned among phenomena; partly also, because world, in the
  10039. transcendental sense, signifies the absolute totality of the content
  10040. of existing things, and we are directing our attention only to the
  10041. completeness of the synthesis--although, properly, only in regression.
  10042. In regard to the fact that these ideas are all transcendent, and,
  10043. although they do not transcend phenomena as regards their mode, but
  10044. are concerned solely with the world of sense (and not with noumena),
  10045. nevertheless carry their synthesis to a degree far above all possible
  10046. experience--it still seems to me that we can, with perfect propriety,
  10047. designate them cosmical conceptions. As regards the distinction between
  10048. the mathematically and the dynamically unconditioned which is the aim of
  10049. the regression of the synthesis, I should call the two former, in a
  10050. more limited signification, cosmical conceptions, the remaining two
  10051. transcendent physical conceptions. This distinction does not at present
  10052. seem to be of particular importance, but we shall afterwards find it to
  10053. be of some value.
  10054. SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason.
  10055. Thetic is the term applied to every collection of dogmatical
  10056. propositions. By antithetic I do not understand dogmatical assertions
  10057. of the opposite, but the self-contradiction of seemingly dogmatical
  10058. cognitions (thesis cum antithesis), in none of which we can discover
  10059. any decided superiority. Antithetic is not, therefore, occupied with
  10060. one-sided statements, but is engaged in considering the contradictory
  10061. nature of the general cognitions of reason and its causes.
  10062. Transcendental antithetic is an investigation into the antinomy of pure
  10063. reason, its causes and result. If we employ our reason not merely in
  10064. the application of the principles of the understanding to objects of
  10065. experience, but venture with it beyond these boundaries, there arise
  10066. certain sophistical propositions or theorems. These assertions have
  10067. the following peculiarities: They can find neither confirmation
  10068. nor confutation in experience; and each is in itself not only
  10069. self-consistent, but possesses conditions of its necessity in the very
  10070. nature of reason--only that, unluckily, there exist just as valid and
  10071. necessary grounds for maintaining the contrary proposition.
  10072. The questions which naturally arise in the consideration of this
  10073. dialectic of pure reason, are therefore: 1st. In what propositions is
  10074. pure reason unavoidably subject to an antinomy? 2nd. What are the causes
  10075. of this antinomy? 3rd. Whether and in what way can reason free itself
  10076. from this self-contradiction?
  10077. A dialectical proposition or theorem of pure reason must, according
  10078. to what has been said, be distinguishable from all sophistical
  10079. propositions, by the fact that it is not an answer to an arbitrary
  10080. question, which may be raised at the mere pleasure of any person, but
  10081. to one which human reason must necessarily encounter in its progress. In
  10082. the second place, a dialectical proposition, with its opposite, does not
  10083. carry the appearance of a merely artificial illusion, which disappears
  10084. as soon as it is investigated, but a natural and unavoidable illusion,
  10085. which, even when we are no longer deceived by it, continues to mock us
  10086. and, although rendered harmless, can never be completely removed.
  10087. This dialectical doctrine will not relate to the unity of understanding
  10088. in empirical conceptions, but to the unity of reason in pure ideas. The
  10089. conditions of this doctrine are--inasmuch as it must, as a synthesis
  10090. according to rules, be conformable to the understanding, and at the same
  10091. time as the absolute unity of the synthesis, to the reason--that, if
  10092. it is adequate to the unity of reason, it is too great for the
  10093. understanding, if according with the understanding, it is too small for
  10094. the reason. Hence arises a mutual opposition, which cannot be avoided,
  10095. do what we will.
  10096. These sophistical assertions of dialectic open, as it were, a
  10097. battle-field, where that side obtains the victory which has been
  10098. permitted to make the attack, and he is compelled to yield who has been
  10099. unfortunately obliged to stand on the defensive. And hence, champions of
  10100. ability, whether on the right or on the wrong side, are certain to carry
  10101. away the crown of victory, if they only take care to have the right to
  10102. make the last attack, and are not obliged to sustain another onset from
  10103. their opponent. We can easily believe that this arena has been often
  10104. trampled by the feet of combatants, that many victories have been
  10105. obtained on both sides, but that the last victory, decisive of the
  10106. affair between the contending parties, was won by him who fought for the
  10107. right, only if his adversary was forbidden to continue the tourney. As
  10108. impartial umpires, we must lay aside entirely the consideration whether
  10109. the combatants are fighting for the right or for the wrong side, for
  10110. the true or for the false, and allow the combat to be first decided.
  10111. Perhaps, after they have wearied more than injured each other, they
  10112. will discover the nothingness of their cause of quarrel and part good
  10113. friends.
  10114. This method of watching, or rather of originating, a conflict of
  10115. assertions, not for the purpose of finally deciding in favour of either
  10116. side, but to discover whether the object of the struggle is not a mere
  10117. illusion, which each strives in vain to reach, but which would be
  10118. no gain even when reached--this procedure, I say, may be termed the
  10119. sceptical method. It is thoroughly distinct from scepticism--the
  10120. principle of a technical and scientific ignorance, which undermines
  10121. the foundations of all knowledge, in order, if possible, to destroy
  10122. our belief and confidence therein. For the sceptical method aims at
  10123. certainty, by endeavouring to discover in a conflict of this kind,
  10124. conducted honestly and intelligently on both sides, the point
  10125. of misunderstanding; just as wise legislators derive, from the
  10126. embarrassment of judges in lawsuits, information in regard to the
  10127. defective and ill-defined parts of their statutes. The antinomy which
  10128. reveals itself in the application of laws, is for our limited wisdom
  10129. the best criterion of legislation. For the attention of reason, which in
  10130. abstract speculation does not easily become conscious of its errors, is
  10131. thus roused to the momenta in the determination of its principles.
  10132. But this sceptical method is essentially peculiar to transcendental
  10133. philosophy, and can perhaps be dispensed with in every other field of
  10134. investigation. In mathematics its use would be absurd; because in it no
  10135. false assertions can long remain hidden, inasmuch as its demonstrations
  10136. must always proceed under the guidance of pure intuition, and by means
  10137. of an always evident synthesis. In experimental philosophy, doubt and
  10138. delay may be very useful; but no misunderstanding is possible, which
  10139. cannot be easily removed; and in experience means of solving the
  10140. difficulty and putting an end to the dissension must at last be found,
  10141. whether sooner or later. Moral philosophy can always exhibit its
  10142. principles, with their practical consequences, in concreto--at least in
  10143. possible experiences, and thus escape the mistakes and ambiguities of
  10144. abstraction. But transcendental propositions, which lay claim to insight
  10145. beyond the region of possible experience, cannot, on the one hand,
  10146. exhibit their abstract synthesis in any a priori intuition, nor, on the
  10147. other, expose a lurking error by the help of experience. Transcendental
  10148. reason, therefore, presents us with no other criterion than that of an
  10149. attempt to reconcile such assertions, and for this purpose to permit a
  10150. free and unrestrained conflict between them. And this we now proceed to
  10151. arrange.*
  10152. [*Footnote: The antinomies stand in the order of the four transcendental
  10153. ideas above detailed.]
  10154. FIRST CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
  10155. THESIS.
  10156. The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited in regard to
  10157. space.
  10158. PROOF.
  10159. Granted that the world has no beginning in time; up to every given
  10160. moment of time, an eternity must have elapsed, and therewith passed away
  10161. an infinite series of successive conditions or states of things in the
  10162. world. Now the infinity of a series consists in the fact that it never
  10163. can be completed by means of a successive synthesis. It follows that an
  10164. infinite series already elapsed is impossible and that, consequently,
  10165. a beginning of the world is a necessary condition of its existence. And
  10166. this was the first thing to be proved.
  10167. As regards the second, let us take the opposite for granted. In this
  10168. case, the world must be an infinite given total of coexistent things.
  10169. Now we cannot cogitate the dimensions of a quantity, which is not given
  10170. within certain limits of an intuition,* in any other way than by means
  10171. of the synthesis of its parts, and the total of such a quantity only
  10172. by means of a completed synthesis, or the repeated addition of unity to
  10173. itself. Accordingly, to cogitate the world, which fills all spaces, as
  10174. a whole, the successive synthesis of the parts of an infinite world must
  10175. be looked upon as completed, that is to say, an infinite time must be
  10176. regarded as having elapsed in the enumeration of all co-existing things;
  10177. which is impossible. For this reason an infinite aggregate of actual
  10178. things cannot be considered as a given whole, consequently, not as a
  10179. contemporaneously given whole. The world is consequently, as regards
  10180. extension in space, not infinite, but enclosed in limits. And this was
  10181. the second thing to be proved.
  10182. [*Footnote: We may consider an undetermined quantity as a whole, when it
  10183. is enclosed within limits, although we cannot construct or ascertain
  10184. its totality by measurement, that is, by the successive synthesis of
  10185. its parts. For its limits of themselves determine its completeness as a
  10186. whole.]
  10187. ANTITHESIS.
  10188. The world has no beginning, and no limits in space, but is, in relation
  10189. both to time and space, infinite.
  10190. PROOF.
  10191. For let it be granted that it has a beginning. A beginning is an
  10192. existence which is preceded by a time in which the thing does not exist.
  10193. On the above supposition, it follows that there must have been a time in
  10194. which the world did not exist, that is, a void time. But in a void time
  10195. the origination of a thing is impossible; because no part of any such
  10196. time contains a distinctive condition of being, in preference to that of
  10197. non-being (whether the supposed thing originate of itself, or by means
  10198. of some other cause). Consequently, many series of things may have a
  10199. beginning in the world, but the world itself cannot have a beginning,
  10200. and is, therefore, in relation to past time, infinite.
  10201. As regards the second statement, let us first take the opposite for
  10202. granted--that the world is finite and limited in space; it follows that
  10203. it must exist in a void space, which is not limited. We should therefore
  10204. meet not only with a relation of things in space, but also a relation
  10205. of things to space. Now, as the world is an absolute whole, out of and
  10206. beyond which no object of intuition, and consequently no correlate to
  10207. which can be discovered, this relation of the world to a void space is
  10208. merely a relation to no object. But such a relation, and consequently
  10209. the limitation of the world by void space, is nothing. Consequently,
  10210. the world, as regards space, is not limited, that is, it is infinite in
  10211. regard to extension.*
  10212. [*Footnote: Space is merely the form of external intuition (formal
  10213. intuition), and not a real object which can be externally perceived.
  10214. Space, prior to all things which determine it (fill or limit it), or,
  10215. rather, which present an empirical intuition conformable to it, is,
  10216. under the title of absolute space, nothing but the mere possibility of
  10217. external phenomena, in so far as they either exist in themselves, or can
  10218. annex themselves to given intuitions. Empirical intuition is therefore
  10219. not a composition of phenomena and space (of perception and empty
  10220. intuition). The one is not the correlate of the other in a synthesis,
  10221. but they are vitally connected in the same empirical intuition, as
  10222. matter and form. If we wish to set one of these two apart from
  10223. the other--space from phenomena--there arise all sorts of empty
  10224. determinations of external intuition, which are very far from being
  10225. possible perceptions. For example, motion or rest of the world in an
  10226. infinite empty space, or a determination of the mutual relation of both,
  10227. cannot possibly be perceived, and is therefore merely the predicate of a
  10228. notional entity.]
  10229. OBSERVATIONS ON THE FIRST ANTINOMY.
  10230. ON THE THESIS.
  10231. In bringing forward these conflicting arguments, I have not been on
  10232. the search for sophisms, for the purpose of availing myself of special
  10233. pleading, which takes advantage of the carelessness of the opposite
  10234. party, appeals to a misunderstood statute, and erects its unrighteous
  10235. claims upon an unfair interpretation. Both proofs originate fairly from
  10236. the nature of the case, and the advantage presented by the mistakes of
  10237. the dogmatists of both parties has been completely set aside.
  10238. The thesis might also have been unfairly demonstrated, by the
  10239. introduction of an erroneous conception of the infinity of a given
  10240. quantity. A quantity is infinite, if a greater than itself cannot
  10241. possibly exist. The quantity is measured by the number of given
  10242. units--which are taken as a standard--contained in it. Now no number can
  10243. be the greatest, because one or more units can always be added. It follows
  10244. that an infinite given quantity, consequently an infinite world (both as
  10245. regards time and extension) is impossible. It is, therefore, limited in
  10246. both respects. In this manner I might have conducted my proof; but the
  10247. conception given in it does not agree with the true conception of an
  10248. infinite whole. In this there is no representation of its quantity,
  10249. it is not said how large it is; consequently its conception is not the
  10250. conception of a maximum. We cogitate in it merely its relation to an
  10251. arbitrarily assumed unit, in relation to which it is greater than any
  10252. number. Now, just as the unit which is taken is greater or smaller, the
  10253. infinite will be greater or smaller; but the infinity, which consists
  10254. merely in the relation to this given unit, must remain always the same,
  10255. although the absolute quantity of the whole is not thereby cognized.
  10256. The true (transcendental) conception of infinity is: that the successive
  10257. synthesis of unity in the measurement of a given quantum can never be
  10258. completed.* Hence it follows, without possibility of mistake, that an
  10259. eternity of actual successive states up to a given (the present) moment
  10260. cannot have elapsed, and that the world must therefore have a beginning.
  10261. [*Footnote: The quantum in this sense contains a congeries of given
  10262. units, which is greater than any number--and this is the mathematical
  10263. conception of the infinite.]
  10264. In regard to the second part of the thesis, the difficulty as to an
  10265. infinite and yet elapsed series disappears; for the manifold of a world
  10266. infinite in extension is contemporaneously given. But, in order to
  10267. cogitate the total of this manifold, as we cannot have the aid of limits
  10268. constituting by themselves this total in intuition, we are obliged to
  10269. give some account of our conception, which in this case cannot proceed
  10270. from the whole to the determined quantity of the parts, but must
  10271. demonstrate the possibility of a whole by means of a successive
  10272. synthesis of the parts. But as this synthesis must constitute a series
  10273. that cannot be completed, it is impossible for us to cogitate prior to
  10274. it, and consequently not by means of it, a totality. For the conception
  10275. of totality itself is in the present case the representation of a
  10276. completed synthesis of the parts; and this completion, and consequently
  10277. its conception, is impossible.
  10278. ON THE ANTITHESIS.
  10279. The proof in favour of the infinity of the cosmical succession and the
  10280. cosmical content is based upon the consideration that, in the opposite
  10281. case, a void time and a void space must constitute the limits of the
  10282. world. Now I am not unaware, that there are some ways of escaping this
  10283. conclusion. It may, for example, be alleged, that a limit to the world,
  10284. as regards both space and time, is quite possible, without at the same
  10285. time holding the existence of an absolute time before the beginning of
  10286. the world, or an absolute space extending beyond the actual world--which
  10287. is impossible. I am quite well satisfied with the latter part of this
  10288. opinion of the philosophers of the Leibnitzian school. Space is merely
  10289. the form of external intuition, but not a real object which can itself
  10290. be externally intuited; it is not a correlate of phenomena, it is
  10291. the form of phenomena itself. Space, therefore, cannot be regarded as
  10292. absolutely and in itself something determinative of the existence
  10293. of things, because it is not itself an object, but only the form of
  10294. possible objects. Consequently, things, as phenomena, determine space;
  10295. that is to say, they render it possible that, of all the possible
  10296. predicates of space (size and relation), certain may belong to
  10297. reality. But we cannot affirm the converse, that space, as something
  10298. self-subsistent, can determine real things in regard to size or shape,
  10299. for it is in itself not a real thing. Space (filled or void)* may
  10300. therefore be limited by phenomena, but phenomena cannot be limited by
  10301. an empty space without them. This is true of time also. All this being
  10302. granted, it is nevertheless indisputable, that we must assume these two
  10303. nonentities, void space without and void time before the world, if we
  10304. assume the existence of cosmical limits, relatively to space or time.
  10305. [*Footnote: It is evident that what is meant here is, that empty space,
  10306. in so far as it is limited by phenomena--space, that is, within the
  10307. world--does not at least contradict transcendental principles, and may
  10308. therefore, as regards them, be admitted, although its possibility cannot
  10309. on that account be affirmed.]
  10310. For, as regards the subterfuge adopted by those who endeavour to evade
  10311. the consequence--that, if the world is limited as to space and time, the
  10312. infinite void must determine the existence of actual things in regard
  10313. to their dimensions--it arises solely from the fact that instead of a
  10314. sensuous world, an intelligible world--of which nothing is known--is
  10315. cogitated; instead of a real beginning (an existence, which is preceded
  10316. by a period in which nothing exists), an existence which presupposes no
  10317. other condition than that of time; and, instead of limits of extension,
  10318. boundaries of the universe. But the question relates to the mundus
  10319. phaenomenon, and its quantity; and in this case we cannot make
  10320. abstraction of the conditions of sensibility, without doing away with
  10321. the essential reality of this world itself. The world of sense, if it is
  10322. limited, must necessarily lie in the infinite void. If this, and with it
  10323. space as the a priori condition of the possibility of phenomena, is left
  10324. out of view, the whole world of sense disappears. In our problem is this
  10325. alone considered as given. The mundus intelligibilis is nothing but the
  10326. general conception of a world, in which abstraction has been made of
  10327. all conditions of intuition, and in relation to which no synthetical
  10328. proposition--either affirmative or negative--is possible.
  10329. SECOND CONFLICT OF TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
  10330. THESIS.
  10331. Every composite substance in the world consists of simple parts; and
  10332. there exists nothing that is not either itself simple, or composed of
  10333. simple parts.
  10334. PROOF.
  10335. For, grant that composite substances do not consist of simple parts;
  10336. in this case, if all combination or composition were annihilated in
  10337. thought, no composite part, and (as, by the supposition, there do
  10338. not exist simple parts) no simple part would exist. Consequently,
  10339. no substance; consequently, nothing would exist. Either, then, it
  10340. is impossible to annihilate composition in thought; or, after such
  10341. annihilation, there must remain something that subsists without
  10342. composition, that is, something that is simple. But in the former case
  10343. the composite could not itself consist of substances, because with
  10344. substances composition is merely a contingent relation, apart from
  10345. which they must still exist as self-subsistent beings. Now, as this case
  10346. contradicts the supposition, the second must contain the truth--that the
  10347. substantial composite in the world consists of simple parts.
  10348. It follows, as an immediate inference, that the things in the world are
  10349. all, without exception, simple beings--that composition is merely an
  10350. external condition pertaining to them--and that, although we never
  10351. can separate and isolate the elementary substances from the state of
  10352. composition, reason must cogitate these as the primary subjects of
  10353. all composition, and consequently, as prior thereto--and as simple
  10354. substances.
  10355. ANTITHESIS.
  10356. No composite thing in the world consists of simple parts; and there does
  10357. not exist in the world any simple substance.
  10358. PROOF.
  10359. Let it be supposed that a composite thing (as substance) consists
  10360. of simple parts. Inasmuch as all external relation, consequently
  10361. all composition of substances, is possible only in space; the space,
  10362. occupied by that which is composite, must consist of the same number of
  10363. parts as is contained in the composite. But space does not consist of
  10364. simple parts, but of spaces. Therefore, every part of the composite must
  10365. occupy a space. But the absolutely primary parts of what is composite
  10366. are simple. It follows that what is simple occupies a space. Now, as
  10367. everything real that occupies a space, contains a manifold the parts of
  10368. which are external to each other, and is consequently composite--and
  10369. a real composite, not of accidents (for these cannot exist external to
  10370. each other apart from substance), but of substances--it follows that the
  10371. simple must be a substantial composite, which is self-contradictory.
  10372. The second proposition of the antithesis--that there exists in the
  10373. world nothing that is simple--is here equivalent to the following:
  10374. The existence of the absolutely simple cannot be demonstrated from any
  10375. experience or perception either external or internal; and the absolutely
  10376. simple is a mere idea, the objective reality of which cannot be
  10377. demonstrated in any possible experience; it is consequently, in the
  10378. exposition of phenomena, without application and object. For, let us
  10379. take for granted that an object may be found in experience for this
  10380. transcendental idea; the empirical intuition of such an object must then
  10381. be recognized to contain absolutely no manifold with its parts external
  10382. to each other, and connected into unity. Now, as we cannot reason from
  10383. the non-consciousness of such a manifold to the impossibility of its
  10384. existence in the intuition of an object, and as the proof of this
  10385. impossibility is necessary for the establishment and proof of absolute
  10386. simplicity; it follows that this simplicity cannot be inferred from any
  10387. perception whatever. As, therefore, an absolutely simple object cannot
  10388. be given in any experience, and the world of sense must be considered as
  10389. the sum total of all possible experiences: nothing simple exists in the
  10390. world.
  10391. This second proposition in the antithesis has a more extended aim than
  10392. the first. The first merely banishes the simple from the intuition of
  10393. the composite; while the second drives it entirely out of nature. Hence
  10394. we were unable to demonstrate it from the conception of a given object
  10395. of external intuition (of the composite), but we were obliged to prove
  10396. it from the relation of a given object to a possible experience in
  10397. general.
  10398. OBSERVATIONS ON THE SECOND ANTINOMY.
  10399. THESIS.
  10400. When I speak of a whole, which necessarily consists of simple parts, I
  10401. understand thereby only a substantial whole, as the true composite; that
  10402. is to say, I understand that contingent unity of the manifold which is
  10403. given as perfectly isolated (at least in thought), placed in reciprocal
  10404. connection, and thus constituted a unity. Space ought not to be called a
  10405. compositum but a totum, for its parts are possible in the whole, and not
  10406. the whole by means of the parts. It might perhaps be called a compositum
  10407. ideale, but not a compositum reale. But this is of no importance. As
  10408. space is not a composite of substances (and not even of real accidents),
  10409. if I abstract all composition therein--nothing, not even a
  10410. point, remains; for a point is possible only as the limit of a
  10411. space--consequently of a composite. Space and time, therefore, do not
  10412. consist of simple parts. That which belongs only to the condition or
  10413. state of a substance, even although it possesses a quantity (motion or
  10414. change, for example), likewise does not consist of simple parts. That is
  10415. to say, a certain degree of change does not originate from the addition
  10416. of many simple changes. Our inference of the simple from the composite
  10417. is valid only of self-subsisting things. But the accidents of a state
  10418. are not self-subsistent. The proof, then, for the necessity of the
  10419. simple, as the component part of all that is substantial and composite,
  10420. may prove a failure, and the whole case of this thesis be lost, if we
  10421. carry the proposition too far, and wish to make it valid of everything
  10422. that is composite without distinction--as indeed has really now and then
  10423. happened. Besides, I am here speaking only of the simple, in so far as
  10424. it is necessarily given in the composite--the latter being capable
  10425. of solution into the former as its component parts. The proper
  10426. signification of the word monas (as employed by Leibnitz) ought to
  10427. relate to the simple, given immediately as simple substance (for
  10428. example, in consciousness), and not as an element of the composite. As
  10429. an clement, the term atomus would be more appropriate. And as I wish to
  10430. prove the existence of simple substances, only in relation to, and
  10431. as the elements of, the composite, I might term the antithesis of the
  10432. second Antinomy, transcendental Atomistic. But as this word has long
  10433. been employed to designate a particular theory of corporeal phenomena
  10434. (moleculae), and thus presupposes a basis of empirical conceptions, I
  10435. prefer calling it the dialectical principle of Monadology.
  10436. ANTITHESIS.
  10437. Against the assertion of the infinite subdivisibility of matter whose
  10438. ground of proof is purely mathematical, objections have been alleged by
  10439. the Monadists. These objections lay themselves open, at first sight,
  10440. to suspicion, from the fact that they do not recognize the clearest
  10441. mathematical proofs as propositions relating to the constitution of
  10442. space, in so far as it is really the formal condition of the possibility
  10443. of all matter, but regard them merely as inferences from abstract but
  10444. arbitrary conceptions, which cannot have any application to real things.
  10445. Just as if it were possible to imagine another mode of intuition than
  10446. that given in the primitive intuition of space; and just as if its a
  10447. priori determinations did not apply to everything, the existence of
  10448. which is possible, from the fact alone of its filling space. If we
  10449. listen to them, we shall find ourselves required to cogitate, in
  10450. addition to the mathematical point, which is simple--not, however,
  10451. a part, but a mere limit of space--physical points, which are indeed
  10452. likewise simple, but possess the peculiar property, as parts of space,
  10453. of filling it merely by their aggregation. I shall not repeat here the
  10454. common and clear refutations of this absurdity, which are to be
  10455. found everywhere in numbers: every one knows that it is impossible to
  10456. undermine the evidence of mathematics by mere discursive conceptions; I
  10457. shall only remark that, if in this case philosophy endeavours to gain
  10458. an advantage over mathematics by sophistical artifices, it is because
  10459. it forgets that the discussion relates solely to Phenomena and their
  10460. conditions. It is not sufficient to find the conception of the simple
  10461. for the pure conception of the composite, but we must discover for the
  10462. intuition of the composite (matter), the intuition of the simple. Now
  10463. this, according to the laws of sensibility, and consequently in the
  10464. case of objects of sense, is utterly impossible. In the case of a
  10465. whole composed of substances, which is cogitated solely by the pure
  10466. understanding, it may be necessary to be in possession of the simple
  10467. before composition is possible. But this does not hold good of the Totum
  10468. substantiale phaenomenon, which, as an empirical intuition in space,
  10469. possesses the necessary property of containing no simple part, for the
  10470. very reason that no part of space is simple. Meanwhile, the Monadists
  10471. have been subtle enough to escape from this difficulty, by presupposing
  10472. intuition and the dynamical relation of substances as the condition of
  10473. the possibility of space, instead of regarding space as the condition
  10474. of the possibility of the objects of external intuition, that is, of
  10475. bodies. Now we have a conception of bodies only as phenomena, and, as
  10476. such, they necessarily presuppose space as the condition of all external
  10477. phenomena. The evasion is therefore in vain; as, indeed, we have
  10478. sufficiently shown in our Aesthetic. If bodies were things in
  10479. themselves, the proof of the Monadists would be unexceptionable.
  10480. The second dialectical assertion possesses the peculiarity of
  10481. having opposed to it a dogmatical proposition, which, among all such
  10482. sophistical statements, is the only one that undertakes to prove in the
  10483. case of an object of experience, that which is properly a transcendental
  10484. idea--the absolute simplicity of substance. The proposition is that the
  10485. object of the internal sense, the thinking Ego, is an absolute simple
  10486. substance. Without at present entering upon this subject--as it has been
  10487. considered at length in a former chapter--I shall merely remark that, if
  10488. something is cogitated merely as an object, without the addition of any
  10489. synthetical determination of its intuition--as happens in the case
  10490. of the bare representation, I--it is certain that no manifold and no
  10491. composition can be perceived in such a representation. As, moreover, the
  10492. predicates whereby I cogitate this object are merely intuitions of the
  10493. internal sense, there cannot be discovered in them anything to prove
  10494. the existence of a manifold whose parts are external to each other,
  10495. and, consequently, nothing to prove the existence of real composition.
  10496. Consciousness, therefore, is so constituted that, inasmuch as the
  10497. thinking subject is at the same time its own object, it cannot divide
  10498. itself--although it can divide its inhering determinations. For every
  10499. object in relation to itself is absolute unity. Nevertheless, if the
  10500. subject is regarded externally, as an object of intuition, it must, in
  10501. its character of phenomenon, possess the property of composition. And it
  10502. must always be regarded in this manner, if we wish to know whether there
  10503. is or is not contained in it a manifold whose parts are external to each
  10504. other.
  10505. THIRD CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
  10506. THESIS.
  10507. Causality according to the laws of nature, is not the only causality
  10508. operating to originate the phenomena of the world. A causality of
  10509. freedom is also necessary to account fully for these phenomena.
  10510. PROOF.
  10511. Let it be supposed, that there is no other kind of causality than that
  10512. according to the laws of nature. Consequently, everything that happens
  10513. presupposes a previous condition, which it follows with absolute
  10514. certainty, in conformity with a rule. But this previous condition must
  10515. itself be something that has happened (that has arisen in time, as it
  10516. did not exist before), for, if it has always been in existence, its
  10517. consequence or effect would not thus originate for the first time,
  10518. but would likewise have always existed. The causality, therefore, of a
  10519. cause, whereby something happens, is itself a thing that has happened.
  10520. Now this again presupposes, in conformity with the law of nature, a
  10521. previous condition and its causality, and this another anterior to the
  10522. former, and so on. If, then, everything happens solely in accordance
  10523. with the laws of nature, there cannot be any real first beginning of
  10524. things, but only a subaltern or comparative beginning. There cannot,
  10525. therefore, be a completeness of series on the side of the causes which
  10526. originate the one from the other. But the law of nature is that
  10527. nothing can happen without a sufficient a priori determined cause. The
  10528. proposition therefore--if all causality is possible only in accordance
  10529. with the laws of nature--is, when stated in this unlimited and general
  10530. manner, self-contradictory. It follows that this cannot be the only kind
  10531. of causality.
  10532. From what has been said, it follows that a causality must be admitted,
  10533. by means of which something happens, without its cause being determined
  10534. according to necessary laws by some other cause preceding. That is to
  10535. say, there must exist an absolute spontaneity of cause, which of itself
  10536. originates a series of phenomena which proceeds according to natural
  10537. laws--consequently transcendental freedom, without which even in the
  10538. course of nature the succession of phenomena on the side of causes is
  10539. never complete.
  10540. ANTITHESIS.
  10541. There is no such thing as freedom, but everything in the world happens
  10542. solely according to the laws of nature.
  10543. PROOF.
  10544. Granted, that there does exist freedom in the transcendental sense, as a
  10545. peculiar kind of causality, operating to produce events in the world--a
  10546. faculty, that is to say, of originating a state, and consequently a
  10547. series of consequences from that state. In this case, not only the
  10548. series originated by this spontaneity, but the determination of this
  10549. spontaneity itself to the production of the series, that is to say, the
  10550. causality itself must have an absolute commencement, such that nothing
  10551. can precede to determine this action according to unvarying laws. But
  10552. every beginning of action presupposes in the acting cause a state of
  10553. inaction; and a dynamically primal beginning of action presupposes a
  10554. state, which has no connection--as regards causality--with the preceding
  10555. state of the cause--which does not, that is, in any wise result from it.
  10556. Transcendental freedom is therefore opposed to the natural law of cause
  10557. and effect, and such a conjunction of successive states in effective
  10558. causes is destructive of the possibility of unity in experience and
  10559. for that reason not to be found in experience--is consequently a mere
  10560. fiction of thought.
  10561. We have, therefore, nothing but nature to which we must look for
  10562. connection and order in cosmical events. Freedom--independence of the
  10563. laws of nature--is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is
  10564. also a relinquishing of the guidance of law and rule. For it cannot
  10565. be alleged that, instead of the laws of nature, laws of freedom may be
  10566. introduced into the causality of the course of nature. For, if freedom
  10567. were determined according to laws, it would be no longer freedom,
  10568. but merely nature. Nature, therefore, and transcendental freedom are
  10569. distinguishable as conformity to law and lawlessness. The former imposes
  10570. upon understanding the difficulty of seeking the origin of events ever
  10571. higher and higher in the series of causes, inasmuch as causality is
  10572. always conditioned thereby; while it compensates this labour by the
  10573. guarantee of a unity complete and in conformity with law. The latter, on
  10574. the contrary, holds out to the understanding the promise of a point
  10575. of rest in the chain of causes, by conducting it to an unconditioned
  10576. causality, which professes to have the power of spontaneous origination,
  10577. but which, in its own utter blindness, deprives it of the guidance of
  10578. rules, by which alone a completely connected experience is possible.
  10579. OBSERVATIONS ON THE THIRD ANTINOMY.
  10580. ON THE THESIS.
  10581. The transcendental idea of freedom is far from constituting the entire
  10582. content of the psychological conception so termed, which is for the most
  10583. part empirical. It merely presents us with the conception of spontaneity
  10584. of action, as the proper ground for imputing freedom to the cause of a
  10585. certain class of objects. It is, however, the true stumbling-stone to
  10586. philosophy, which meets with unconquerable difficulties in the way of
  10587. its admitting this kind of unconditioned causality. That element in the
  10588. question of the freedom of the will, which has for so long a time placed
  10589. speculative reason in such perplexity, is properly only transcendental,
  10590. and concerns the question, whether there must be held to exist a faculty
  10591. of spontaneous origination of a series of successive things or states.
  10592. How such a faculty is possible is not a necessary inquiry; for in the
  10593. case of natural causality itself, we are obliged to content ourselves
  10594. with the a priori knowledge that such a causality must be presupposed,
  10595. although we are quite incapable of comprehending how the being of
  10596. one thing is possible through the being of another, but must for this
  10597. information look entirely to experience. Now we have demonstrated this
  10598. necessity of a free first beginning of a series of phenomena, only in so
  10599. far as it is required for the comprehension of an origin of the world,
  10600. all following states being regarded as a succession according to laws
  10601. of nature alone. But, as there has thus been proved the existence of a
  10602. faculty which can of itself originate a series in time--although we
  10603. are unable to explain how it can exist--we feel ourselves authorized to
  10604. admit, even in the midst of the natural course of events, a beginning,
  10605. as regards causality, of different successions of phenomena, and at the
  10606. same time to attribute to all substances a faculty of free action.
  10607. But we ought in this case not to allow ourselves to fall into a common
  10608. misunderstanding, and to suppose that, because a successive series in
  10609. the world can only have a comparatively first beginning--another state
  10610. or condition of things always preceding--an absolutely first beginning
  10611. of a series in the course of nature is impossible. For we are not
  10612. speaking here of an absolutely first beginning in relation to time, but
  10613. as regards causality alone. When, for example, I, completely of my own
  10614. free will, and independently of the necessarily determinative influence
  10615. of natural causes, rise from my chair, there commences with this event,
  10616. including its material consequences in infinitum, an absolutely
  10617. new series; although, in relation to time, this event is merely the
  10618. continuation of a preceding series. For this resolution and act of mine
  10619. do not form part of the succession of effects in nature, and are not
  10620. mere continuations of it; on the contrary, the determining causes of
  10621. nature cease to operate in reference to this event, which certainly
  10622. succeeds the acts of nature, but does not proceed from them. For
  10623. these reasons, the action of a free agent must be termed, in regard to
  10624. causality, if not in relation to time, an absolutely primal beginning of
  10625. a series of phenomena.
  10626. The justification of this need of reason to rest upon a free act as
  10627. the first beginning of the series of natural causes is evident from
  10628. the fact, that all philosophers of antiquity (with the exception of the
  10629. Epicurean school) felt themselves obliged, when constructing a theory of
  10630. the motions of the universe, to accept a prime mover, that is, a freely
  10631. acting cause, which spontaneously and prior to all other causes evolved
  10632. this series of states. They always felt the need of going beyond mere
  10633. nature, for the purpose of making a first beginning comprehensible.
  10634. ON THE ANTITHESIS.
  10635. The assertor of the all-sufficiency of nature in regard to causality
  10636. (transcendental Physiocracy), in opposition to the doctrine of freedom,
  10637. would defend his view of the question somewhat in the following manner.
  10638. He would say, in answer to the sophistical arguments of the opposite
  10639. party: If you do not accept a mathematical first, in relation to time,
  10640. you have no need to seek a dynamical first, in regard to causality. Who
  10641. compelled you to imagine an absolutely primal condition of the world,
  10642. and therewith an absolute beginning of the gradually progressing
  10643. successions of phenomena--and, as some foundation for this fancy of
  10644. yours, to set bounds to unlimited nature? Inasmuch as the substances in
  10645. the world have always existed--at least the unity of experience renders
  10646. such a supposition quite necessary--there is no difficulty in believing
  10647. also, that the changes in the conditions of these substances have always
  10648. existed; and, consequently, that a first beginning, mathematical or
  10649. dynamical, is by no means required. The possibility of such an infinite
  10650. derivation, without any initial member from which all the others result,
  10651. is certainly quite incomprehensible. But, if you are rash enough to
  10652. deny the enigmatical secrets of nature for this reason, you will find
  10653. yourselves obliged to deny also the existence of many fundamental
  10654. properties of natural objects (such as fundamental forces), which you
  10655. can just as little comprehend; and even the possibility of so simple
  10656. a conception as that of change must present to you insuperable
  10657. difficulties. For if experience did not teach you that it was real, you
  10658. never could conceive a priori the possibility of this ceaseless sequence
  10659. of being and non-being.
  10660. But if the existence of a transcendental faculty of freedom is
  10661. granted--a faculty of originating changes in the world--this faculty
  10662. must at least exist out of and apart from the world; although it is
  10663. certainly a bold assumption, that, over and above the complete content
  10664. of all possible intuitions, there still exists an object which cannot be
  10665. presented in any possible perception. But, to attribute to substances
  10666. in the world itself such a faculty, is quite inadmissible; for, in
  10667. this case; the connection of phenomena reciprocally determining and
  10668. determined according to general laws, which is termed nature, and along
  10669. with it the criteria of empirical truth, which enable us to distinguish
  10670. experience from mere visionary dreaming, would almost entirely
  10671. disappear. In proximity with such a lawless faculty of freedom, a system
  10672. of nature is hardly cogitable; for the laws of the latter would be
  10673. continually subject to the intrusive influences of the former, and
  10674. the course of phenomena, which would otherwise proceed regularly and
  10675. uniformly, would become thereby confused and disconnected.
  10676. FOURTH CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
  10677. THESIS.
  10678. There exists either in, or in connection with the world--either as a
  10679. part of it, or as the cause of it--an absolutely necessary being.
  10680. PROOF.
  10681. The world of sense, as the sum total of all phenomena, contains a series
  10682. of changes. For, without such a series, the mental representation of
  10683. the series of time itself, as the condition of the possibility of the
  10684. sensuous world, could not be presented to us.* But every change stands
  10685. under its condition, which precedes it in time and renders it necessary.
  10686. Now the existence of a given condition presupposes a complete series of
  10687. conditions up to the absolutely unconditioned, which alone is absolutely
  10688. necessary. It follows that something that is absolutely necessary must
  10689. exist, if change exists as its consequence. But this necessary thing
  10690. itself belongs to the sensuous world. For suppose it to exist out of and
  10691. apart from it, the series of cosmical changes would receive from it a
  10692. beginning, and yet this necessary cause would not itself belong to
  10693. the world of sense. But this is impossible. For, as the beginning of a
  10694. series in time is determined only by that which precedes it in time, the
  10695. supreme condition of the beginning of a series of changes must exist
  10696. in the time in which this series itself did not exist; for a beginning
  10697. supposes a time preceding, in which the thing that begins to be was
  10698. not in existence. The causality of the necessary cause of changes,
  10699. and consequently the cause itself, must for these reasons belong
  10700. to time--and to phenomena, time being possible only as the form of
  10701. phenomena. Consequently, it cannot be cogitated as separated from the
  10702. world of sense--the sum total of all phenomena. There is, therefore,
  10703. contained in the world, something that is absolutely necessary--whether
  10704. it be the whole cosmical series itself, or only a part of it.
  10705. [*Footnote: Objectively, time, as the formal condition of the
  10706. possibility of change, precedes all changes; but subjectively, and in
  10707. consciousness, the representation of time, like every other, is given
  10708. solely by occasion of perception.]
  10709. ANTITHESIS.
  10710. An absolutely necessary being does not exist, either in the world, or
  10711. out of it--as its cause.
  10712. PROOF.
  10713. Grant that either the world itself is necessary, or that there is
  10714. contained in it a necessary existence. Two cases are possible. First,
  10715. there must either be in the series of cosmical changes a beginning,
  10716. which is unconditionally necessary, and therefore uncaused--which is at
  10717. variance with the dynamical law of the determination of all phenomena
  10718. in time; or, secondly, the series itself is without beginning, and,
  10719. although contingent and conditioned in all its parts, is nevertheless
  10720. absolutely necessary and unconditioned as a whole--which is
  10721. self-contradictory. For the existence of an aggregate cannot be
  10722. necessary, if no single part of it possesses necessary existence.
  10723. Grant, on the other band, that an absolutely necessary cause exists out
  10724. of and apart from the world. This cause, as the highest member in the
  10725. series of the causes of cosmical changes, must originate or begin* the
  10726. existence of the latter and their series. In this case it must also
  10727. begin to act, and its causality would therefore belong to time, and
  10728. consequently to the sum total of phenomena, that is, to the world.
  10729. It follows that the cause cannot be out of the world; which is
  10730. contradictory to the hypothesis. Therefore, neither in the world, nor
  10731. out of it (but in causal connection with it), does there exist any
  10732. absolutely necessary being.
  10733. [*Footnote: The word begin is taken in two senses. The first is
  10734. active--the cause being regarded as beginning a series of conditions as
  10735. its effect (infit). The second is passive--the causality in the cause
  10736. itself beginning to operate (fit). I reason here from the first to the
  10737. second.]
  10738. OBSERVATIONS ON THE FOURTH ANTINOMY.
  10739. ON THE THESIS.
  10740. To demonstrate the existence of a necessary being, I cannot be permitted
  10741. in this place to employ any other than the cosmological argument,
  10742. which ascends from the conditioned in phenomena to the unconditioned in
  10743. conception--the unconditioned being considered the necessary condition
  10744. of the absolute totality of the series. The proof, from the mere idea
  10745. of a supreme being, belongs to another principle of reason and requires
  10746. separate discussion.
  10747. The pure cosmological proof demonstrates the existence of a necessary
  10748. being, but at the same time leaves it quite unsettled, whether this
  10749. being is the world itself, or quite distinct from it. To establish
  10750. the truth of the latter view, principles are requisite, which are not
  10751. cosmological and do not proceed in the series of phenomena. We
  10752. should require to introduce into our proof conceptions of contingent
  10753. beings--regarded merely as objects of the understanding, and also
  10754. a principle which enables us to connect these, by means of mere
  10755. conceptions, with a necessary being. But the proper place for all such
  10756. arguments is a transcendent philosophy, which has unhappily not yet been
  10757. established.
  10758. But, if we begin our proof cosmologically, by laying at the foundation
  10759. of it the series of phenomena, and the regress in it according to
  10760. empirical laws of causality, we are not at liberty to break off from
  10761. this mode of demonstration and to pass over to something which is not
  10762. itself a member of the series. The condition must be taken in exactly
  10763. the same signification as the relation of the conditioned to its
  10764. condition in the series has been taken, for the series must conduct us
  10765. in an unbroken regress to this supreme condition. But if this relation
  10766. is sensuous, and belongs to the possible empirical employment of
  10767. understanding, the supreme condition or cause must close the regressive
  10768. series according to the laws of sensibility and consequently, must
  10769. belong to the series of time. It follows that this necessary existence
  10770. must be regarded as the highest member of the cosmical series.
  10771. Certain philosophers have, nevertheless, allowed themselves the liberty
  10772. of making such a saltus (metabasis eis allo gonos). From the changes
  10773. in the world they have concluded their empirical contingency, that
  10774. is, their dependence on empirically-determined causes, and they thus
  10775. admitted an ascending series of empirical conditions: and in this they
  10776. are quite right. But as they could not find in this series any primal
  10777. beginning or any highest member, they passed suddenly from the empirical
  10778. conception of contingency to the pure category, which presents us with
  10779. a series--not sensuous, but intellectual--whose completeness does
  10780. certainly rest upon the existence of an absolutely necessary cause. Nay,
  10781. more, this intellectual series is not tied to any sensuous conditions;
  10782. and is therefore free from the condition of time, which requires it
  10783. spontaneously to begin its causality in time. But such a procedure is
  10784. perfectly inadmissible, as will be made plain from what follows.
  10785. In the pure sense of the categories, that is contingent the
  10786. contradictory opposite of which is possible. Now we cannot reason from
  10787. empirical contingency to intellectual. The opposite of that which is
  10788. changed--the opposite of its state--is actual at another time, and is
  10789. therefore possible. Consequently, it is not the contradictory opposite
  10790. of the former state. To be that, it is necessary that, in the same time
  10791. in which the preceding state existed, its opposite could have existed in
  10792. its place; but such a cognition is not given us in the mere phenomenon
  10793. of change. A body that was in motion = A, comes into a state of rest =
  10794. non-A. Now it cannot be concluded from the fact that a state opposite
  10795. to the state A follows it, that the contradictory opposite of A is
  10796. possible; and that A is therefore contingent. To prove this, we should
  10797. require to know that the state of rest could have existed in the very
  10798. same time in which the motion took place. Now we know nothing more than
  10799. that the state of rest was actual in the time that followed the state of
  10800. motion; consequently, that it was also possible. But motion at one time,
  10801. and rest at another time, are not contradictorily opposed to each other.
  10802. It follows from what has been said that the succession of opposite
  10803. determinations, that is, change, does not demonstrate the fact of
  10804. contingency as represented in the conceptions of the pure understanding;
  10805. and that it cannot, therefore, conduct us to the fact of the existence
  10806. of a necessary being. Change proves merely empirical contingency, that
  10807. is to say, that the new state could not have existed without a cause,
  10808. which belongs to the preceding time. This cause--even although it is
  10809. regarded as absolutely necessary--must be presented to us in time, and
  10810. must belong to the series of phenomena.
  10811. ON THE ANTITHESIS.
  10812. The difficulties which meet us, in our attempt to rise through the
  10813. series of phenomena to the existence of an absolutely necessary supreme
  10814. cause, must not originate from our inability to establish the truth of
  10815. our mere conceptions of the necessary existence of a thing. That is to
  10816. say, our objections not be ontological, but must be directed against
  10817. the causal connection with a series of phenomena of a condition which is
  10818. itself unconditioned. In one word, they must be cosmological and relate
  10819. to empirical laws. We must show that the regress in the series of
  10820. causes (in the world of sense) cannot conclude with an empirically
  10821. unconditioned condition, and that the cosmological argument from the
  10822. contingency of the cosmical state--a contingency alleged to arise from
  10823. change--does not justify us in accepting a first cause, that is, a prime
  10824. originator of the cosmical series.
  10825. The reader will observe in this antinomy a very remarkable contrast. The
  10826. very same grounds of proof which established in the thesis the existence
  10827. of a supreme being, demonstrated in the antithesis--and with equal
  10828. strictness--the non-existence of such a being. We found, first, that a
  10829. necessary being exists, because the whole time past contains the series
  10830. of all conditions, and with it, therefore, the unconditioned (the
  10831. necessary); secondly, that there does not exist any necessary being,
  10832. for the same reason, that the whole time past contains the series of
  10833. all conditions--which are themselves, therefore, in the aggregate,
  10834. conditioned. The cause of this seeming incongruity is as follows. We
  10835. attend, in the first argument, solely to the absolute totality of the
  10836. series of conditions, the one of which determines the other in time, and
  10837. thus arrive at a necessary unconditioned. In the second, we consider,
  10838. on the contrary, the contingency of everything that is determined in
  10839. the series of time--for every event is preceded by a time, in which the
  10840. condition itself must be determined as conditioned--and thus everything
  10841. that is unconditioned or absolutely necessary disappears. In both, the
  10842. mode of proof is quite in accordance with the common procedure of human
  10843. reason, which often falls into discord with itself, from considering an
  10844. object from two different points of view. Herr von Mairan regarded
  10845. the controversy between two celebrated astronomers, which arose from
  10846. a similar difficulty as to the choice of a proper standpoint, as a
  10847. phenomenon of sufficient importance to warrant a separate treatise
  10848. on the subject. The one concluded: the moon revolves on its own axis,
  10849. because it constantly presents the same side to the earth; the other
  10850. declared that the moon does not revolve on its own axis, for the same
  10851. reason. Both conclusions were perfectly correct, according to the point
  10852. of view from which the motions of the moon were considered.
  10853. SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Self-contradictions.
  10854. We have thus completely before us the dialectical procedure of the
  10855. cosmological ideas. No possible experience can present us with an object
  10856. adequate to them in extent. Nay, more, reason itself cannot cogitate
  10857. them as according with the general laws of experience. And yet they
  10858. are not arbitrary fictions of thought. On the contrary, reason, in
  10859. its uninterrupted progress in the empirical synthesis, is necessarily
  10860. conducted to them, when it endeavours to free from all conditions and
  10861. to comprehend in its unconditioned totality that which can only be
  10862. determined conditionally in accordance with the laws of experience.
  10863. These dialectical propositions are so many attempts to solve four
  10864. natural and unavoidable problems of reason. There are neither more, nor
  10865. can there be less, than this number, because there are no other series
  10866. of synthetical hypotheses, limiting a priori the empirical synthesis.
  10867. The brilliant claims of reason striving to extend its dominion beyond
  10868. the limits of experience, have been represented above only in dry
  10869. formulae, which contain merely the grounds of its pretensions. They
  10870. have, besides, in conformity with the character of a transcendental
  10871. philosophy, been freed from every empirical element; although the full
  10872. splendour of the promises they hold out, and the anticipations they
  10873. excite, manifests itself only when in connection with empirical
  10874. cognitions. In the application of them, however, and in the advancing
  10875. enlargement of the employment of reason, while struggling to rise from
  10876. the region of experience and to soar to those sublime ideas, philosophy
  10877. discovers a value and a dignity, which, if it could but make good its
  10878. assertions, would raise it far above all other departments of human
  10879. knowledge--professing, as it does, to present a sure foundation for our
  10880. highest hopes and the ultimate aims of all the exertions of reason.
  10881. The questions: whether the world has a beginning and a limit to its
  10882. extension in space; whether there exists anywhere, or perhaps, in my
  10883. own thinking Self, an indivisible and indestructible unity--or whether
  10884. nothing but what is divisible and transitory exists; whether I am a free
  10885. agent, or, like other beings, am bound in the chains of nature and fate;
  10886. whether, finally, there is a supreme cause of the world, or all our
  10887. thought and speculation must end with nature and the order of external
  10888. things--are questions for the solution of which the mathematician would
  10889. willingly exchange his whole science; for in it there is no satisfaction
  10890. for the highest aspirations and most ardent desires of humanity. Nay, it
  10891. may even be said that the true value of mathematics--that pride of human
  10892. reason--consists in this: that she guides reason to the knowledge of
  10893. nature--in her greater as well as in her less manifestations--in her
  10894. beautiful order and regularity--guides her, moreover, to an insight into
  10895. the wonderful unity of the moving forces in the operations of nature,
  10896. far beyond the expectations of a philosophy building only on experience;
  10897. and that she thus encourages philosophy to extend the province of reason
  10898. beyond all experience, and at the same time provides it with the most
  10899. excellent materials for supporting its investigations, in so far as
  10900. their nature admits, by adequate and accordant intuitions.
  10901. Unfortunately for speculation--but perhaps fortunately for the
  10902. practical interests of humanity--reason, in the midst of her highest
  10903. anticipations, finds herself hemmed in by a press of opposite and
  10904. contradictory conclusions, from which neither her honour nor her safety
  10905. will permit her to draw back. Nor can she regard these conflicting
  10906. trains of reasoning with indifference as mere passages at arms, still
  10907. less can she command peace; for in the subject of the conflict she has a
  10908. deep interest. There is no other course left open to her than to reflect
  10909. with herself upon the origin of this disunion in reason--whether it may
  10910. not arise from a mere misunderstanding. After such an inquiry, arrogant
  10911. claims would have to be given up on both sides; but the sovereignty
  10912. of reason over understanding and sense would be based upon a sure
  10913. foundation.
  10914. We shall at present defer this radical inquiry and, in the meantime,
  10915. consider for a little what side in the controversy we should most
  10916. willingly take, if we were obliged to become partisans at all. As, in
  10917. this case, we leave out of sight altogether the logical criterion of
  10918. truth, and merely consult our own interest in reference to the question,
  10919. these considerations, although inadequate to settle the question of
  10920. right in either party, will enable us to comprehend how those who have
  10921. taken part in the struggle, adopt the one view rather than the other--no
  10922. special insight into the subject, however, having influenced their
  10923. choice. They will, at the same time, explain to us many other things
  10924. by the way--for example, the fiery zeal on the one side and the cold
  10925. maintenance of their cause on the other; why the one party has met with
  10926. the warmest approbations, and the other has always been repulsed by
  10927. irreconcilable prejudices.
  10928. There is one thing, however, that determines the proper point of view,
  10929. from which alone this preliminary inquiry can be instituted and carried
  10930. on with the proper completeness--and that is the comparison of the
  10931. principles from which both sides, thesis and antithesis, proceed. My
  10932. readers would remark in the propositions of the antithesis a complete
  10933. uniformity in the mode of thought and a perfect unity of principle. Its
  10934. principle was that of pure empiricism, not only in the explication
  10935. of the phenomena in the world, but also in the solution of the
  10936. transcendental ideas, even of that of the universe itself. The
  10937. affirmations of the thesis, on the contrary, were based, in addition to
  10938. the empirical mode of explanation employed in the series of phenomena,
  10939. on intellectual propositions; and its principles were in so far
  10940. not simple. I shall term the thesis, in view of its essential
  10941. characteristic, the dogmatism of pure reason.
  10942. On the side of Dogmatism, or of the thesis, therefore, in the
  10943. determination of the cosmological ideas, we find:
  10944. 1. A practical interest, which must be very dear to every right-thinking
  10945. man. That the word has a beginning--that the nature of my thinking self
  10946. is simple, and therefore indestructible--that I am a free agent, and
  10947. raised above the compulsion of nature and her laws--and, finally, that
  10948. the entire order of things, which form the world, is dependent upon a
  10949. Supreme Being, from whom the whole receives unity and connection--these
  10950. are so many foundation-stones of morality and religion. The antithesis
  10951. deprives us of all these supports--or, at least, seems so to deprive us.
  10952. 2. A speculative interest of reason manifests itself on this side. For,
  10953. if we take the transcendental ideas and employ them in the manner which
  10954. the thesis directs, we can exhibit completely a priori the entire
  10955. chain of conditions, and understand the derivation of the
  10956. conditioned--beginning from the unconditioned. This the antithesis does
  10957. not do; and for this reason does not meet with so welcome a reception.
  10958. For it can give no answer to our question respecting the conditions of
  10959. its synthesis--except such as must be supplemented by another question,
  10960. and so on to infinity. According to it, we must rise from a given
  10961. beginning to one still higher; every part conducts us to a still smaller
  10962. one; every event is preceded by another event which is its cause; and
  10963. the conditions of existence rest always upon other and still higher
  10964. conditions, and find neither end nor basis in some self-subsistent thing
  10965. as the primal being.
  10966. 3. This side has also the advantage of popularity; and this constitutes
  10967. no small part of its claim to favour. The common understanding does not
  10968. find the least difficulty in the idea of the unconditioned beginning of
  10969. all synthesis--accustomed, as it is, rather to follow our consequences
  10970. than to seek for a proper basis for cognition. In the conception of an
  10971. absolute first, moreover--the possibility of which it does not inquire
  10972. into--it is highly gratified to find a firmly-established point
  10973. of departure for its attempts at theory; while in the restless and
  10974. continuous ascent from the conditioned to the condition, always with one
  10975. foot in the air, it can find no satisfaction.
  10976. On the side of the antithesis, or Empiricism, in the determination of
  10977. the cosmological ideas:
  10978. 1. We cannot discover any such practical interest arising from pure
  10979. principles of reason as morality and religion present. On the contrary,
  10980. pure empiricism seems to empty them of all their power and influence.
  10981. If there does not exist a Supreme Being distinct from the world--if the
  10982. world is without beginning, consequently without a Creator--if our wills
  10983. are not free, and the soul is divisible and subject to corruption just
  10984. like matter--the ideas and principles of morality lose all validity and
  10985. fall with the transcendental ideas which constituted their theoretical
  10986. support.
  10987. 2. But empiricism, in compensation, holds out to reason, in its
  10988. speculative interests, certain important advantages, far exceeding any
  10989. that the dogmatist can promise us. For, when employed by the empiricist,
  10990. understanding is always upon its proper ground of investigation--the
  10991. field of possible experience, the laws of which it can explore, and thus
  10992. extend its cognition securely and with clear intelligence without being
  10993. stopped by limits in any direction. Here can it and ought it to find and
  10994. present to intuition its proper object--not only in itself, but in all
  10995. its relations; or, if it employ conceptions, upon this ground it can
  10996. always present the corresponding images in clear and unmistakable
  10997. intuitions. It is quite unnecessary for it to renounce the guidance of
  10998. nature, to attach itself to ideas, the objects of which it cannot know;
  10999. because, as mere intellectual entities, they cannot be presented in
  11000. any intuition. On the contrary, it is not even permitted to abandon
  11001. its proper occupation, under the pretence that it has been brought to
  11002. a conclusion (for it never can be), and to pass into the region of
  11003. idealizing reason and transcendent conceptions, which it is not required
  11004. to observe and explore the laws of nature, but merely to think and to
  11005. imagine--secure from being contradicted by facts, because they have not
  11006. been called as witnesses, but passed by, or perhaps subordinated to the
  11007. so-called higher interests and considerations of pure reason.
  11008. Hence the empiricist will never allow himself to accept any epoch of
  11009. nature for the first--the absolutely primal state; he will not believe
  11010. that there can be limits to his outlook into her wide domains, nor pass
  11011. from the objects of nature, which he can satisfactorily explain by
  11012. means of observation and mathematical thought--which he can determine
  11013. synthetically in intuition, to those which neither sense nor imagination
  11014. can ever present in concreto; he will not concede the existence of a
  11015. faculty in nature, operating independently of the laws of nature--a
  11016. concession which would introduce uncertainty into the procedure of the
  11017. understanding, which is guided by necessary laws to the observation of
  11018. phenomena; nor, finally, will he permit himself to seek a cause beyond
  11019. nature, inasmuch as we know nothing but it, and from it alone receive an
  11020. objective basis for all our conceptions and instruction in the unvarying
  11021. laws of things.
  11022. In truth, if the empirical philosopher had no other purpose in the
  11023. establishment of his antithesis than to check the presumption of a
  11024. reason which mistakes its true destination, which boasts of its insight
  11025. and its knowledge, just where all insight and knowledge cease to
  11026. exist, and regards that which is valid only in relation to a practical
  11027. interest, as an advancement of the speculative interests of the mind
  11028. (in order, when it is convenient for itself, to break the thread of our
  11029. physical investigations, and, under pretence of extending our cognition,
  11030. connect them with transcendental ideas, by means of which we really know
  11031. only that we know nothing)--if, I say, the empiricist rested satisfied
  11032. with this benefit, the principle advanced by him would be a maxim
  11033. recommending moderation in the pretensions of reason and modesty in its
  11034. affirmations, and at the same time would direct us to the right mode
  11035. of extending the province of the understanding, by the help of the only
  11036. true teacher, experience. In obedience to this advice, intellectual
  11037. hypotheses and faith would not be called in aid of our practical
  11038. interests; nor should we introduce them under the pompous titles of
  11039. science and insight. For speculative cognition cannot find an objective
  11040. basis any other where than in experience; and, when we overstep its
  11041. limits our synthesis, which requires ever new cognitions independent of
  11042. experience, has no substratum of intuition upon which to build.
  11043. But if--as often happens--empiricism, in relation to ideas, becomes
  11044. itself dogmatic and boldly denies that which is above the sphere of its
  11045. phenomenal cognition, it falls itself into the error of intemperance--an
  11046. error which is here all the more reprehensible, as thereby the practical
  11047. interest of reason receives an irreparable injury.
  11048. And this constitutes the opposition between Epicureanism* and Platonism.
  11049. [*Footnote: It is, however, still a matter of doubt whether Epicurus
  11050. ever propounded these principles as directions for the objective
  11051. employment of the understanding. If, indeed, they were nothing more than
  11052. maxims for the speculative exercise of reason, he gives evidence therein
  11053. a more genuine philosophic spirit than any of the philosophers of
  11054. antiquity. That, in the explanation of phenomena, we must proceed as
  11055. if the field of inquiry had neither limits in space nor commencement
  11056. in time; that we must be satisfied with the teaching of experience in
  11057. reference to the material of which the world is posed; that we must not
  11058. look for any other mode of the origination of events than that which is
  11059. determined by the unalterable laws of nature; and finally, that we not
  11060. employ the hypothesis of a cause distinct from the world to account for
  11061. a phenomenon or for the world itself--are principles for the extension
  11062. of speculative philosophy, and the discovery of the true sources of the
  11063. principles of morals, which, however little conformed to in the present
  11064. day, are undoubtedly correct. At the same time, any one desirous of
  11065. ignoring, in mere speculation, these dogmatical propositions, need not
  11066. for that reason be accused of denying them.]
  11067. Both Epicurus and Plato assert more in their systems than they know. The
  11068. former encourages and advances science--although to the prejudice of
  11069. the practical; the latter presents us with excellent principles for the
  11070. investigation of the practical, but, in relation to everything regarding
  11071. which we can attain to speculative cognition, permits reason to append
  11072. idealistic explanations of natural phenomena, to the great injury of
  11073. physical investigation.
  11074. 3. In regard to the third motive for the preliminary choice of a party
  11075. in this war of assertions, it seems very extraordinary that empiricism
  11076. should be utterly unpopular. We should be inclined to believe that the
  11077. common understanding would receive it with pleasure--promising as it
  11078. does to satisfy it without passing the bounds of experience and its
  11079. connected order; while transcendental dogmatism obliges it to rise to
  11080. conceptions which far surpass the intelligence and ability of the most
  11081. practised thinkers. But in this, in truth, is to be found its real
  11082. motive. For the common understanding thus finds itself in a situation
  11083. where not even the most learned can have the advantage of it. If it
  11084. understands little or nothing about these transcendental conceptions, no
  11085. one can boast of understanding any more; and although it may not express
  11086. itself in so scholastically correct a manner as others, it can busy
  11087. itself with reasoning and arguments without end, wandering among mere
  11088. ideas, about which one can always be very eloquent, because we know
  11089. nothing about them; while, in the observation and investigation of
  11090. nature, it would be forced to remain dumb and to confess its utter
  11091. ignorance. Thus indolence and vanity form of themselves strong
  11092. recommendations of these principles. Besides, although it is a hard
  11093. thing for a philosopher to assume a principle, of which he can give to
  11094. himself no reasonable account, and still more to employ conceptions, the
  11095. objective reality of which cannot be established, nothing is more usual
  11096. with the common understanding. It wants something which will allow it
  11097. to go to work with confidence. The difficulty of even comprehending
  11098. a supposition does not disquiet it, because--not knowing what
  11099. comprehending means--it never even thinks of the supposition it may be
  11100. adopting as a principle; and regards as known that with which it
  11101. has become familiar from constant use. And, at last, all speculative
  11102. interests disappear before the practical interests which it holds dear;
  11103. and it fancies that it understands and knows what its necessities
  11104. and hopes incite it to assume or to believe. Thus the empiricism of
  11105. transcendentally idealizing reason is robbed of all popularity; and,
  11106. however prejudicial it may be to the highest practical principles, there
  11107. is no fear that it will ever pass the limits of the schools, or acquire
  11108. any favour or influence in society or with the multitude.
  11109. Human reason is by nature architectonic. That is to say, it regards all
  11110. cognitions as parts of a possible system, and hence accepts only such
  11111. principles as at least do not incapacitate a cognition to which we may
  11112. have attained from being placed along with others in a general system.
  11113. But the propositions of the antithesis are of a character which renders
  11114. the completion of an edifice of cognitions impossible. According to
  11115. these, beyond one state or epoch of the world there is always to be
  11116. found one more ancient; in every part always other parts themselves
  11117. divisible; preceding every event another, the origin of which
  11118. must itself be sought still higher; and everything in existence is
  11119. conditioned, and still not dependent on an unconditioned and primal
  11120. existence. As, therefore, the antithesis will not concede the existence
  11121. of a first beginning which might be available as a foundation, a
  11122. complete edifice of cognition, in the presence of such hypothesis, is
  11123. utterly impossible. Thus the architectonic interest of reason, which
  11124. requires a unity--not empirical, but a priori and rational--forms a
  11125. natural recommendation for the assertions of the thesis in our antinomy.
  11126. But if any one could free himself entirely from all considerations
  11127. of interest, and weigh without partiality the assertions of reason,
  11128. attending only to their content, irrespective of the consequences which
  11129. follow from them; such a person, on the supposition that he knew no
  11130. other way out of the confusion than to settle the truth of one or
  11131. other of the conflicting doctrines, would live in a state of continual
  11132. hesitation. Today, he would feel convinced that the human will is free;
  11133. to-morrow, considering the indissoluble chain of nature, he would look
  11134. on freedom as a mere illusion and declare nature to be all-in-all. But,
  11135. if he were called to action, the play of the merely speculative reason
  11136. would disappear like the shapes of a dream, and practical interest would
  11137. dictate his choice of principles. But, as it well befits a reflective
  11138. and inquiring being to devote certain periods of time to the examination
  11139. of its own reason--to divest itself of all partiality, and frankly to
  11140. communicate its observations for the judgement and opinion of others; so
  11141. no one can be blamed for, much less prevented from, placing both
  11142. parties on their trial, with permission to end themselves, free
  11143. from intimidation, before intimidation, before a sworn jury of equal
  11144. condition with themselves--the condition of weak and fallible men.
  11145. SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of
  11146. presenting a Solution of its Transcendental Problems.
  11147. To avow an ability to solve all problems and to answer all questions
  11148. would be a profession certain to convict any philosopher of extravagant
  11149. boasting and self-conceit, and at once to destroy the confidence that
  11150. might otherwise have been reposed in him. There are, however, sciences
  11151. so constituted that every question arising within their sphere must
  11152. necessarily be capable of receiving an answer from the knowledge already
  11153. possessed, for the answer must be received from the same sources whence
  11154. the question arose. In such sciences it is not allowable to excuse
  11155. ourselves on the plea of necessary and unavoidable ignorance; a solution
  11156. is absolutely requisite. The rule of right and wrong must help us to the
  11157. knowledge of what is right or wrong in all possible cases; otherwise,
  11158. the idea of obligation or duty would be utterly null, for we cannot have
  11159. any obligation to that which we cannot know. On the other hand, in our
  11160. investigations of the phenomena of nature, much must remain uncertain,
  11161. and many questions continue insoluble; because what we know of nature
  11162. is far from being sufficient to explain all the phenomena that are
  11163. presented to our observation. Now the question is: Whether there is in
  11164. transcendental philosophy any question, relating to an object presented
  11165. to pure reason, which is unanswerable by this reason; and whether we
  11166. must regard the subject of the question as quite uncertain, so far as
  11167. our knowledge extends, and must give it a place among those subjects, of
  11168. which we have just so much conception as is sufficient to enable us
  11169. to raise a question--faculty or materials failing us, however, when we
  11170. attempt an answer.
  11171. Now I maintain that, among all speculative cognition, the peculiarity of
  11172. transcendental philosophy is that there is no question, relating to an
  11173. object presented to pure reason, which is insoluble by this reason; and
  11174. that the profession of unavoidable ignorance--the problem being alleged
  11175. to be beyond the reach of our faculties--cannot free us from the
  11176. obligation to present a complete and satisfactory answer. For the very
  11177. conception which enables us to raise the question must give us the power
  11178. of answering it; inasmuch as the object, as in the case of right and
  11179. wrong, is not to be discovered out of the conception.
  11180. But, in transcendental philosophy, it is only the cosmological questions
  11181. to which we can demand a satisfactory answer in relation to the
  11182. constitution of their object; and the philosopher is not permitted to
  11183. avail himself of the pretext of necessary ignorance and impenetrable
  11184. obscurity. These questions relate solely to the cosmological ideas. For
  11185. the object must be given in experience, and the question relates to the
  11186. adequateness of the object to an idea. If the object is transcendental
  11187. and therefore itself unknown; if the question, for example, is whether
  11188. the object--the something, the phenomenon of which (internal--in
  11189. ourselves) is thought--that is to say, the soul, is in itself a simple
  11190. being; or whether there is a cause of all things, which is absolutely
  11191. necessary--in such cases we are seeking for our idea an object, of which
  11192. we may confess that it is unknown to us, though we must not on that
  11193. account assert that it is impossible.* The cosmological ideas alone
  11194. posses the peculiarity that we can presuppose the object of them and the
  11195. empirical synthesis requisite for the conception of that object to be
  11196. given; and the question, which arises from these ideas, relates merely
  11197. to the progress of this synthesis, in so far as it must contain absolute
  11198. totality--which, however, is not empirical, as it cannot be given in any
  11199. experience. Now, as the question here is solely in regard to a thing as
  11200. the object of a possible experience and not as a thing in itself, the
  11201. answer to the transcendental cosmological question need not be sought
  11202. out of the idea, for the question does not regard an object in itself.
  11203. The question in relation to a possible experience is not, "What can be
  11204. given in an experience in concreto" but "what is contained in the idea,
  11205. to which the empirical synthesis must approximate." The question must
  11206. therefore be capable of solution from the idea alone. For the idea is
  11207. a creation of reason itself, which therefore cannot disclaim the
  11208. obligation to answer or refer us to the unknown object.
  11209. [*Footnote: The question, "What is the constitution of a transcendental
  11210. object?" is unanswerable--we are unable to say what it is; but we can
  11211. perceive that the question itself is nothing; because it does not relate
  11212. to any object that can be presented to us. For this reason, we must
  11213. consider all the questions raised in transcendental psychology as
  11214. answerable and as really answered; for they relate to the transcendental
  11215. subject of all internal phenomena, which is not itself phenomenon and
  11216. consequently not given as an object, in which, moreover, none of
  11217. the categories--and it is to them that the question is properly
  11218. directed--find any conditions of its application. Here, therefore, is a
  11219. case where no answer is the only proper answer. For a question regarding
  11220. the constitution of a something which cannot be cogitated by any
  11221. determined predicate, being completely beyond the sphere of objects and
  11222. experience, is perfectly null and void.]
  11223. It is not so extraordinary, as it at first sight appears, that a science
  11224. should demand and expect satisfactory answers to all the questions that
  11225. may arise within its own sphere (questiones domesticae), although, up to
  11226. a certain time, these answers may not have been discovered. There are,
  11227. in addition to transcendental philosophy, only two pure sciences
  11228. of reason; the one with a speculative, the other with a practical
  11229. content--pure mathematics and pure ethics. Has any one ever heard
  11230. it alleged that, from our complete and necessary ignorance of the
  11231. conditions, it is uncertain what exact relation the diameter of a circle
  11232. bears to the circle in rational or irrational numbers? By the former
  11233. the sum cannot be given exactly, by the latter only approximately; and
  11234. therefore we decide that the impossibility of a solution of the question
  11235. is evident. Lambert presented us with a demonstration of this. In the
  11236. general principles of morals there can be nothing uncertain, for the
  11237. propositions are either utterly without meaning, or must originate
  11238. solely in our rational conceptions. On the other hand, there must be
  11239. in physical science an infinite number of conjectures, which can never
  11240. become certainties; because the phenomena of nature are not given as
  11241. objects dependent on our conceptions. The key to the solution of such
  11242. questions cannot, therefore, be found in our conceptions, or in pure
  11243. thought, but must lie without us and for that reason is in many cases
  11244. not to be discovered; and consequently a satisfactory explanation cannot
  11245. be expected. The questions of transcendental analytic, which relate to
  11246. the deduction of our pure cognition, are not to be regarded as of the
  11247. same kind as those mentioned above; for we are not at present treating
  11248. of the certainty of judgements in relation to the origin of our
  11249. conceptions, but only of that certainty in relation to objects.
  11250. We cannot, therefore, escape the responsibility of at least a critical
  11251. solution of the questions of reason, by complaints of the limited nature
  11252. of our faculties, and the seemingly humble confession that it is beyond
  11253. the power of our reason to decide, whether the world has existed from
  11254. all eternity or had a beginning--whether it is infinitely extended, or
  11255. enclosed within certain limits--whether anything in the world is simple,
  11256. or whether everything must be capable of infinite divisibility--whether
  11257. freedom can originate phenomena, or whether everything is absolutely
  11258. dependent on the laws and order of nature--and, finally, whether there
  11259. exists a being that is completely unconditioned and necessary, or
  11260. whether the existence of everything is conditioned and consequently
  11261. dependent on something external to itself, and therefore in its own
  11262. nature contingent. For all these questions relate to an object, which
  11263. can be given nowhere else than in thought. This object is the absolutely
  11264. unconditioned totality of the synthesis of phenomena. If the conceptions
  11265. in our minds do not assist us to some certain result in regard to these
  11266. problems, we must not defend ourselves on the plea that the object
  11267. itself remains hidden from and unknown to us. For no such thing or
  11268. object can be given--it is not to be found out of the idea in our minds.
  11269. We must seek the cause of our failure in our idea itself, which is an
  11270. insoluble problem and in regard to which we obstinately assume that
  11271. there exists a real object corresponding and adequate to it. A clear
  11272. explanation of the dialectic which lies in our conception, will very
  11273. soon enable us to come to a satisfactory decision in regard to such a
  11274. question.
  11275. The pretext that we are unable to arrive at certainty in regard to these
  11276. problems may be met with this question, which requires at least a plain
  11277. answer: "From what source do the ideas originate, the solution of which
  11278. involves you in such difficulties? Are you seeking for an explanation
  11279. of certain phenomena; and do you expect these ideas to give you the
  11280. principles or the rules of this explanation?" Let it be granted, that
  11281. all nature was laid open before you; that nothing was hid from your
  11282. senses and your consciousness. Still, you could not cognize in concreto
  11283. the object of your ideas in any experience. For what is demanded is not
  11284. only this full and complete intuition, but also a complete synthesis and
  11285. the consciousness of its absolute totality; and this is not possible by
  11286. means of any empirical cognition. It follows that your question--your
  11287. idea--is by no means necessary for the explanation of any phenomenon;
  11288. and the idea cannot have been in any sense given by the object itself.
  11289. For such an object can never be presented to us, because it cannot be
  11290. given by any possible experience. Whatever perceptions you may attain
  11291. to, you are still surrounded by conditions--in space, or in time--and
  11292. you cannot discover anything unconditioned; nor can you decide whether
  11293. this unconditioned is to be placed in an absolute beginning of the
  11294. synthesis, or in an absolute totality of the series without beginning.
  11295. A whole, in the empirical signification of the term, is always merely
  11296. comparative. The absolute whole of quantity (the universe), of division,
  11297. of derivation, of the condition of existence, with the question--whether
  11298. it is to be produced by finite or infinite synthesis, no possible
  11299. experience can instruct us concerning. You will not, for example, be
  11300. able to explain the phenomena of a body in the least degree better,
  11301. whether you believe it to consist of simple, or of composite parts;
  11302. for a simple phenomenon--and just as little an infinite series of
  11303. composition--can never be presented to your perception. Phenomena
  11304. require and admit of explanation, only in so far as the conditions of
  11305. that explanation are given in perception; but the sum total of that
  11306. which is given in phenomena, considered as an absolute whole, is itself
  11307. a perception--and we cannot therefore seek for explanations of this
  11308. whole beyond itself, in other perceptions. The explanation of this whole
  11309. is the proper object of the transcendental problems of pure reason.
  11310. Although, therefore, the solution of these problems is unattainable
  11311. through experience, we must not permit ourselves to say that it is
  11312. uncertain how the object of our inquiries is constituted. For the object
  11313. is in our own mind and cannot be discovered in experience; and we have
  11314. only to take care that our thoughts are consistent with each other,
  11315. and to avoid falling into the amphiboly of regarding our idea as a
  11316. representation of an object empirically given, and therefore to be
  11317. cognized according to the laws of experience. A dogmatical solution is
  11318. therefore not only unsatisfactory but impossible. The critical solution,
  11319. which may be a perfectly certain one, does not consider the question
  11320. objectively, but proceeds by inquiring into the basis of the cognition
  11321. upon which the question rests.
  11322. SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems
  11323. presented in the four Transcendental Ideas.
  11324. We should be quite willing to desist from the demand of a dogmatical
  11325. answer to our questions, if we understood beforehand that, be the answer
  11326. what it may, it would only serve to increase our ignorance, to throw
  11327. us from one incomprehensibility into another, from one obscurity
  11328. into another still greater, and perhaps lead us into irreconcilable
  11329. contradictions. If a dogmatical affirmative or negative answer is
  11330. demanded, is it at all prudent to set aside the probable grounds of
  11331. a solution which lie before us and to take into consideration what
  11332. advantage we shall gain, if the answer is to favour the one side or the
  11333. other? If it happens that in both cases the answer is mere nonsense,
  11334. we have in this an irresistible summons to institute a critical
  11335. investigation of the question, for the purpose of discovering whether
  11336. it is based on a groundless presupposition and relates to an idea, the
  11337. falsity of which would be more easily exposed in its application and
  11338. consequences than in the mere representation of its content. This is the
  11339. great utility of the sceptical mode of treating the questions addressed
  11340. by pure reason to itself. By this method we easily rid ourselves of
  11341. the confusions of dogmatism, and establish in its place a temperate
  11342. criticism, which, as a genuine cathartic, will successfully remove
  11343. the presumptuous notions of philosophy and their consequence--the vain
  11344. pretension to universal science.
  11345. If, then, I could understand the nature of a cosmological idea and
  11346. perceive, before I entered on the discussion of the subject at all,
  11347. that, whatever side of the question regarding the unconditioned of the
  11348. regressive synthesis of phenomena it favoured--it must either be too
  11349. great or too small for every conception of the understanding--I would
  11350. be able to comprehend how the idea, which relates to an object of
  11351. experience--an experience which must be adequate to and in accordance
  11352. with a possible conception of the understanding--must be completely void
  11353. and without significance, inasmuch as its object is inadequate, consider
  11354. it as we may. And this is actually the case with all cosmological
  11355. conceptions, which, for the reason above mentioned, involve reason, so
  11356. long as it remains attached to them, in an unavoidable antinomy. For
  11357. suppose:
  11358. First, that the world has no beginning--in this case it is too large
  11359. for our conception; for this conception, which consists in a successive
  11360. regress, cannot overtake the whole eternity that has elapsed. Grant
  11361. that it has a beginning, it is then too small for the conception of
  11362. the understanding. For, as a beginning presupposes a time preceding, it
  11363. cannot be unconditioned; and the law of the empirical employment of the
  11364. understanding imposes the necessity of looking for a higher condition of
  11365. time; and the world is, therefore, evidently too small for this law.
  11366. The same is the case with the double answer to the question regarding
  11367. the extent, in space, of the world. For, if it is infinite and
  11368. unlimited, it must be too large for every possible empirical conception.
  11369. If it is finite and limited, we have a right to ask: "What determines
  11370. these limits?" Void space is not a self-subsistent correlate of things,
  11371. and cannot be a final condition--and still less an empirical condition,
  11372. forming a part of a possible experience. For how can we have any
  11373. experience or perception of an absolute void? But the absolute totality
  11374. of the empirical synthesis requires that the unconditioned be an
  11375. empirical conception. Consequently, a finite world is too small for our
  11376. conception.
  11377. Secondly, if every phenomenon (matter) in space consists of an infinite
  11378. number of parts, the regress of the division is always too great for our
  11379. conception; and if the division of space must cease with some member
  11380. of the division (the simple), it is too small for the idea of the
  11381. unconditioned. For the member at which we have discontinued our division
  11382. still admits a regress to many more parts contained in the object.
  11383. Thirdly, suppose that every event in the world happens in accordance
  11384. with the laws of nature; the causality of a cause must itself be
  11385. an event and necessitates a regress to a still higher cause, and
  11386. consequently the unceasing prolongation of the series of conditions
  11387. a parte priori. Operative nature is therefore too large for every
  11388. conception we can form in the synthesis of cosmical events.
  11389. If we admit the existence of spontaneously produced events, that is, of
  11390. free agency, we are driven, in our search for sufficient reasons, on an
  11391. unavoidable law of nature and are compelled to appeal to the empirical
  11392. law of causality, and we find that any such totality of connection in
  11393. our synthesis is too small for our necessary empirical conception.
  11394. Fourthly, if we assume the existence of an absolutely necessary
  11395. being--whether it be the world or something in the world, or the cause
  11396. of the world--we must place it in a time at an infinite distance from
  11397. any given moment; for, otherwise, it must be dependent on some other and
  11398. higher existence. Such an existence is, in this case, too large for our
  11399. empirical conception, and unattainable by the continued regress of any
  11400. synthesis.
  11401. But if we believe that everything in the world--be it condition or
  11402. conditioned--is contingent; every given existence is too small for our
  11403. conception. For in this case we are compelled to seek for some other
  11404. existence upon which the former depends.
  11405. We have said that in all these cases the cosmological idea is either
  11406. too great or too small for the empirical regress in a synthesis, and
  11407. consequently for every possible conception of the understanding. Why did
  11408. we not express ourselves in a manner exactly the reverse of this and,
  11409. instead of accusing the cosmological idea of over stepping or of falling
  11410. short of its true aim, possible experience, say that, in the first case,
  11411. the empirical conception is always too small for the idea, and in the
  11412. second too great, and thus attach the blame of these contradictions to
  11413. the empirical regress? The reason is this. Possible experience can alone
  11414. give reality to our conceptions; without it a conception is merely an
  11415. idea, without truth or relation to an object. Hence a possible empirical
  11416. conception must be the standard by which we are to judge whether an
  11417. idea is anything more than an idea and fiction of thought, or whether it
  11418. relates to an object in the world. If we say of a thing that in
  11419. relation to some other thing it is too large or too small, the former is
  11420. considered as existing for the sake of the latter, and requiring to
  11421. be adapted to it. Among the trivial subjects of discussion in the old
  11422. schools of dialectics was this question: "If a ball cannot pass through
  11423. a hole, shall we say that the ball is too large or the hole too small?"
  11424. In this case it is indifferent what expression we employ; for we do
  11425. not know which exists for the sake of the other. On the other hand, we
  11426. cannot say: "The man is too long for his coat"; but: "The coat is too
  11427. short for the man."
  11428. We are thus led to the well-founded suspicion that the cosmological
  11429. ideas, and all the conflicting sophistical assertions connected with
  11430. them, are based upon a false and fictitious conception of the mode in
  11431. which the object of these ideas is presented to us; and this suspicion
  11432. will probably direct us how to expose the illusion that has so long led
  11433. us astray from the truth.
  11434. SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to theSolution
  11435. of Pure Cosmological Dialectic.
  11436. In the transcendental aesthetic we proved that everything intuited in
  11437. space and time, all objects of a possible experience, are nothing but
  11438. phenomena, that is, mere representations; and that these, as
  11439. presented to us--as extended bodies, or as series of changes--have no
  11440. self-subsistent existence apart from human thought. This doctrine I
  11441. call Transcendental Idealism.* The realist in the transcendental
  11442. sense regards these modifications of our sensibility, these mere
  11443. representations, as things subsisting in themselves.
  11444. [*Footnote: I have elsewhere termed this theory formal idealism, to
  11445. distinguish it from material idealism, which doubts or denies the
  11446. existence of external things. To avoid ambiguity, it seems advisable in
  11447. many cases to employ this term instead of that mentioned in the text.]
  11448. It would be unjust to accuse us of holding the long-decried theory of
  11449. empirical idealism, which, while admitting the reality of space, denies,
  11450. or at least doubts, the existence of bodies extended in it, and thus
  11451. leaves us without a sufficient criterion of reality and illusion. The
  11452. supporters of this theory find no difficulty in admitting the reality of
  11453. the phenomena of the internal sense in time; nay, they go the length
  11454. of maintaining that this internal experience is of itself a sufficient
  11455. proof of the real existence of its object as a thing in itself.
  11456. Transcendental idealism allows that the objects of external
  11457. intuition--as intuited in space, and all changes in time--as represented
  11458. by the internal sense, are real. For, as space is the form of that
  11459. intuition which we call external, and, without objects in space, no
  11460. empirical representation could be given us, we can and ought to regard
  11461. extended bodies in it as real. The case is the same with representations
  11462. in time. But time and space, with all phenomena therein, are not in
  11463. themselves things. They are nothing but representations and cannot exist
  11464. out of and apart from the mind. Nay, the sensuous internal intuition of
  11465. the mind (as the object of consciousness), the determination of which
  11466. is represented by the succession of different states in time, is not
  11467. the real, proper self, as it exists in itself--not the transcendental
  11468. subject--but only a phenomenon, which is presented to the sensibility of
  11469. this, to us, unknown being. This internal phenomenon cannot be admitted
  11470. to be a self-subsisting thing; for its condition is time, and time
  11471. cannot be the condition of a thing in itself. But the empirical truth
  11472. of phenomena in space and time is guaranteed beyond the possibility of
  11473. doubt, and sufficiently distinguished from the illusion of dreams
  11474. or fancy--although both have a proper and thorough connection in an
  11475. experience according to empirical laws. The objects of experience then
  11476. are not things in themselves, but are given only in experience, and have
  11477. no existence apart from and independently of experience. That there may
  11478. be inhabitants in the moon, although no one has ever observed them, must
  11479. certainly be admitted; but this assertion means only, that we may in the
  11480. possible progress of experience discover them at some future time. For
  11481. that which stands in connection with a perception according to the
  11482. laws of the progress of experience is real. They are therefore really
  11483. existent, if they stand in empirical connection with my actual or real
  11484. consciousness, although they are not in themselves real, that is, apart
  11485. from the progress of experience.
  11486. There is nothing actually given--we can be conscious of nothing as
  11487. real, except a perception and the empirical progression from it to other
  11488. possible perceptions. For phenomena, as mere representations, are real
  11489. only in perception; and perception is, in fact, nothing but the reality
  11490. of an empirical representation, that is, a phenomenon. To call a
  11491. phenomenon a real thing prior to perception means either that we must
  11492. meet with this phenomenon in the progress of experience, or it means
  11493. nothing at all. For I can say only of a thing in itself that it exists
  11494. without relation to the senses and experience. But we are speaking here
  11495. merely of phenomena in space and time, both of which are determinations
  11496. of sensibility, and not of things in themselves. It follows that
  11497. phenomena are not things in themselves, but are mere representations,
  11498. which if not given in us--in perception--are non-existent.
  11499. The faculty of sensuous intuition is properly a receptivity--a capacity
  11500. of being affected in a certain manner by representations, the relation
  11501. of which to each other is a pure intuition of space and time--the pure
  11502. forms of sensibility. These representations, in so far as they are
  11503. connected and determinable in this relation (in space and time)
  11504. according to laws of the unity of experience, are called objects. The
  11505. non-sensuous cause of these representations is completely unknown to us
  11506. and hence cannot be intuited as an object. For such an object could not
  11507. be represented either in space or in time; and without these conditions
  11508. intuition or representation is impossible. We may, at the same time,
  11509. term the non-sensuous cause of phenomena the transcendental object--but
  11510. merely as a mental correlate to sensibility, considered as a
  11511. receptivity. To this transcendental object we may attribute the whole
  11512. connection and extent of our possible perceptions, and say that it is
  11513. given and exists in itself prior to all experience. But the phenomena,
  11514. corresponding to it, are not given as things in themselves, but in
  11515. experience alone. For they are mere representations, receiving from
  11516. perceptions alone significance and relation to a real object, under
  11517. the condition that this or that perception--indicating an object--is in
  11518. complete connection with all others in accordance with the rules of the
  11519. unity of experience. Thus we can say: "The things that really existed
  11520. in past time are given in the transcendental object of experience." But
  11521. these are to me real objects, only in so far as I can represent to my
  11522. own mind, that a regressive series of possible perceptions--following
  11523. the indications of history, or the footsteps of cause and effect--in
  11524. accordance with empirical laws--that, in one word, the course of the
  11525. world conducts us to an elapsed series of time as the condition of the
  11526. present time. This series in past time is represented as real, not in
  11527. itself, but only in connection with a possible experience. Thus, when
  11528. I say that certain events occurred in past time, I merely assert the
  11529. possibility of prolonging the chain of experience, from the present
  11530. perception, upwards to the conditions that determine it according to
  11531. time.
  11532. If I represent to myself all objects existing in all space and time, I
  11533. do not thereby place these in space and time prior to all experience; on
  11534. the contrary, such a representation is nothing more than the notion of
  11535. a possible experience, in its absolute completeness. In experience alone
  11536. are those objects, which are nothing but representations, given. But,
  11537. when I say they existed prior to my experience, this means only that
  11538. I must begin with the perception present to me and follow the track
  11539. indicated until I discover them in some part or region of experience.
  11540. The cause of the empirical condition of this progression--and
  11541. consequently at what member therein I must stop, and at what point
  11542. in the regress I am to find this member--is transcendental, and hence
  11543. necessarily incognizable. But with this we have not to do; our concern
  11544. is only with the law of progression in experience, in which objects,
  11545. that is, phenomena, are given. It is a matter of indifference, whether
  11546. I say, "I may in the progress of experience discover stars, at a hundred
  11547. times greater distance than the most distant of those now visible," or,
  11548. "Stars at this distance may be met in space, although no one has,
  11549. or ever will discover them." For, if they are given as things in
  11550. themselves, without any relation to possible experience, they are for me
  11551. non-existent, consequently, are not objects, for they are not contained
  11552. in the regressive series of experience. But, if these phenomena must be
  11553. employed in the construction or support of the cosmological idea of an
  11554. absolute whole, and when we are discussing a question that oversteps the
  11555. limits of possible experience, the proper distinction of the different
  11556. theories of the reality of sensuous objects is of great importance,
  11557. in order to avoid the illusion which must necessarily arise from the
  11558. misinterpretation of our empirical conceptions.
  11559. SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem.
  11560. The antinomy of pure reason is based upon the following dialectical
  11561. argument: "If that which is conditioned is given, the whole series
  11562. of its conditions is also given; but sensuous objects are given as
  11563. conditioned; consequently..." This syllogism, the major of which seems
  11564. so natural and evident, introduces as many cosmological ideas as there
  11565. are different kinds of conditions in the synthesis of phenomena, in
  11566. so far as these conditions constitute a series. These ideas require
  11567. absolute totality in the series, and thus place reason in inextricable
  11568. embarrassment. Before proceeding to expose the fallacy in this
  11569. dialectical argument, it will be necessary to have a correct
  11570. understanding of certain conceptions that appear in it.
  11571. In the first place, the following proposition is evident, and
  11572. indubitably certain: "If the conditioned is given, a regress in the
  11573. series of all its conditions is thereby imperatively required." For the
  11574. very conception of a conditioned is a conception of something related
  11575. to a condition, and, if this condition is itself conditioned, to
  11576. another condition--and so on through all the members of the series.
  11577. This proposition is, therefore, analytical and has nothing to fear
  11578. from transcendental criticism. It is a logical postulate of reason:
  11579. to pursue, as far as possible, the connection of a conception with its
  11580. conditions.
  11581. If, in the second place, both the conditioned and the condition are
  11582. things in themselves, and if the former is given, not only is the
  11583. regress to the latter requisite, but the latter is really given with
  11584. the former. Now, as this is true of all the members of the series, the
  11585. entire series of conditions, and with them the unconditioned, is at the
  11586. same time given in the very fact of the conditioned, the existence of
  11587. which is possible only in and through that series, being given. In
  11588. this case, the synthesis of the conditioned with its condition, is a
  11589. synthesis of the understanding merely, which represents things as they
  11590. are, without regarding whether and how we can cognize them. But if
  11591. I have to do with phenomena, which, in their character of mere
  11592. representations, are not given, if I do not attain to a cognition of
  11593. them (in other words, to themselves, for they are nothing more than
  11594. empirical cognitions), I am not entitled to say: "If the conditioned
  11595. is given, all its conditions (as phenomena) are also given." I cannot,
  11596. therefore, from the fact of a conditioned being given, infer the
  11597. absolute totality of the series of its conditions. For phenomena are
  11598. nothing but an empirical synthesis in apprehension or perception, and
  11599. are therefore given only in it. Now, in speaking of phenomena it does
  11600. not follow that, if the conditioned is given, the synthesis which
  11601. constitutes its empirical condition is also thereby given and
  11602. presupposed; such a synthesis can be established only by an actual
  11603. regress in the series of conditions. But we are entitled to say in this
  11604. case that a regress to the conditions of a conditioned, in other
  11605. words, that a continuous empirical synthesis is enjoined; that, if the
  11606. conditions are not given, they are at least required; and that we are
  11607. certain to discover the conditions in this regress.
  11608. We can now see that the major, in the above cosmological syllogism,
  11609. takes the conditioned in the transcendental signification which it has
  11610. in the pure category, while the minor speaks of it in the empirical
  11611. signification which it has in the category as applied to phenomena.
  11612. There is, therefore, a dialectical fallacy in the syllogism--a sophisma
  11613. figurae dictionis. But this fallacy is not a consciously devised one,
  11614. but a perfectly natural illusion of the common reason of man. For,
  11615. when a thing is given as conditioned, we presuppose in the major its
  11616. conditions and their series, unperceived, as it were, and unseen;
  11617. because this is nothing more than the logical requirement of complete
  11618. and satisfactory premisses for a given conclusion. In this case, time
  11619. is altogether left out in the connection of the conditioned with
  11620. the condition; they are supposed to be given in themselves, and
  11621. contemporaneously. It is, moreover, just as natural to regard phenomena
  11622. (in the minor) as things in themselves and as objects presented to the
  11623. pure understanding, as in the major, in which complete abstraction was
  11624. made of all conditions of intuition. But it is under these conditions
  11625. alone that objects are given. Now we overlooked a remarkable distinction
  11626. between the conceptions. The synthesis of the conditioned with its
  11627. condition, and the complete series of the latter (in the major) are not
  11628. limited by time, and do not contain the conception of succession. On the
  11629. contrary, the empirical synthesis and the series of conditions in the
  11630. phenomenal world--subsumed in the minor--are necessarily successive and
  11631. given in time alone. It follows that I cannot presuppose in the minor,
  11632. as I did in the major, the absolute totality of the synthesis and of
  11633. the series therein represented; for in the major all the members of the
  11634. series are given as things in themselves--without any limitations or
  11635. conditions of time, while in the minor they are possible only in and
  11636. through a successive regress, which cannot exist, except it be actually
  11637. carried into execution in the world of phenomena.
  11638. After this proof of the viciousness of the argument commonly employed
  11639. in maintaining cosmological assertions, both parties may now be justly
  11640. dismissed, as advancing claims without grounds or title. But the process
  11641. has not been ended by convincing them that one or both were in the
  11642. wrong and had maintained an assertion which was without valid grounds
  11643. of proof. Nothing seems to be clearer than that, if one maintains: "The
  11644. world has a beginning," and another: "The world has no beginning," one
  11645. of the two must be right. But it is likewise clear that, if the evidence
  11646. on both sides is equal, it is impossible to discover on what side the
  11647. truth lies; and the controversy continues, although the parties have
  11648. been recommended to peace before the tribunal of reason. There remains,
  11649. then, no other means of settling the question than to convince the
  11650. parties, who refute each other with such conclusiveness and ability,
  11651. that they are disputing about nothing, and that a transcendental
  11652. illusion has been mocking them with visions of reality where there is
  11653. none. The mode of adjusting a dispute which cannot be decided upon its
  11654. own merits, we shall now proceed to lay before our readers.
  11655. Zeno of Elea, a subtle dialectician, was severely reprimanded by Plato
  11656. as a sophist, who, merely from the base motive of exhibiting his
  11657. skill in discussion, maintained and subverted the same proposition by
  11658. arguments as powerful and convincing on the one side as on the other. He
  11659. maintained, for example, that God (who was probably nothing more, in his
  11660. view, than the world) is neither finite nor infinite, neither in motion
  11661. nor in rest, neither similar nor dissimilar to any other thing. It
  11662. seemed to those philosophers who criticized his mode of discussion
  11663. that his purpose was to deny completely both of two self-contradictory
  11664. propositions--which is absurd. But I cannot believe that there is any
  11665. justice in this accusation. The first of these propositions I shall
  11666. presently consider in a more detailed manner. With regard to the others,
  11667. if by the word of God he understood merely the Universe, his meaning
  11668. must have been--that it cannot be permanently present in one place--that
  11669. is, at rest--nor be capable of changing its place--that is, of
  11670. moving--because all places are in the universe, and the universe itself
  11671. is, therefore, in no place. Again, if the universe contains in itself
  11672. everything that exists, it cannot be similar or dissimilar to any other
  11673. thing, because there is, in fact, no other thing with which it can be
  11674. compared. If two opposite judgements presuppose a contingent impossible,
  11675. or arbitrary condition, both--in spite of their opposition (which is,
  11676. however, not properly or really a contradiction)--fall away; because the
  11677. condition, which ensured the validity of both, has itself disappeared.
  11678. If we say: "Everybody has either a good or a bad smell," we have omitted
  11679. a third possible judgement--it has no smell at all; and thus both
  11680. conflicting statements may be false. If we say: "It is either
  11681. good-smelling or not good-smelling (vel suaveolens vel non-suaveolens),"
  11682. both judgements are contradictorily opposed; and the contradictory
  11683. opposite of the former judgement--some bodies are not
  11684. good-smelling--embraces also those bodies which have no smell at all. In
  11685. the preceding pair of opposed judgements (per disparata), the contingent
  11686. condition of the conception of body (smell) attached to both conflicting
  11687. statements, instead of having been omitted in the latter, which is
  11688. consequently not the contradictory opposite of the former.
  11689. If, accordingly, we say: "The world is either infinite in extension, or
  11690. it is not infinite (non est infinitus)"; and if the former proposition
  11691. is false, its contradictory opposite--the world is not infinite--must
  11692. be true. And thus I should deny the existence of an infinite, without,
  11693. however affirming the existence of a finite world. But if we construct
  11694. our proposition thus: "The world is either infinite or finite
  11695. (non-infinite)," both statements may be false. For, in this case, we
  11696. consider the world as per se determined in regard to quantity, and
  11697. while, in the one judgement, we deny its infinite and consequently,
  11698. perhaps, its independent existence; in the other, we append to the
  11699. world, regarded as a thing in itself, a certain determination--that
  11700. of finitude; and the latter may be false as well as the former, if the
  11701. world is not given as a thing in itself, and thus neither as finite nor
  11702. as infinite in quantity. This kind of opposition I may be allowed to
  11703. term dialectical; that of contradictories may be called analytical
  11704. opposition. Thus then, of two dialectically opposed judgements both may
  11705. be false, from the fact, that the one is not a mere contradictory of
  11706. the other, but actually enounces more than is requisite for a full and
  11707. complete contradiction.
  11708. When we regard the two propositions--"The world is infinite in
  11709. quantity," and, "The world is finite in quantity," as contradictory
  11710. opposites, we are assuming that the world--the complete series of
  11711. phenomena--is a thing in itself. For it remains as a permanent quantity,
  11712. whether I deny the infinite or the finite regress in the series of
  11713. its phenomena. But if we dismiss this assumption--this transcendental
  11714. illusion--and deny that it is a thing in itself, the contradictory
  11715. opposition is metamorphosed into a merely dialectical one; and the
  11716. world, as not existing in itself--independently of the regressive series
  11717. of my representations--exists in like manner neither as a whole which is
  11718. infinite nor as a whole which is finite in itself. The universe exists
  11719. for me only in the empirical regress of the series of phenomena and not
  11720. per se. If, then, it is always conditioned, it is never completely or as
  11721. a whole; and it is, therefore, not an unconditioned whole and does not
  11722. exist as such, either with an infinite, or with a finite quantity.
  11723. What we have here said of the first cosmological idea--that of the
  11724. absolute totality of quantity in phenomena--applies also to the
  11725. others. The series of conditions is discoverable only in the regressive
  11726. synthesis itself, and not in the phenomenon considered as a thing in
  11727. itself--given prior to all regress. Hence I am compelled to say: "The
  11728. aggregate of parts in a given phenomenon is in itself neither finite nor
  11729. infinite; and these parts are given only in the regressive synthesis
  11730. of decomposition--a synthesis which is never given in absolute
  11731. completeness, either as finite, or as infinite." The same is the case
  11732. with the series of subordinated causes, or of the conditioned up to the
  11733. unconditioned and necessary existence, which can never be regarded as in
  11734. itself, ind in its totality, either as finite or as infinite; because,
  11735. as a series of subordinate representations, it subsists only in the
  11736. dynamical regress and cannot be regarded as existing previously to this
  11737. regress, or as a self-subsistent series of things.
  11738. Thus the antinomy of pure reason in its cosmological ideas disappears.
  11739. For the above demonstration has established the fact that it is merely
  11740. the product of a dialectical and illusory opposition, which arises from
  11741. the application of the idea of absolute totality--admissible only as a
  11742. condition of things in themselves--to phenomena, which exist only in
  11743. our representations, and--when constituting a series--in a successive
  11744. regress. This antinomy of reason may, however, be really profitable to
  11745. our speculative interests, not in the way of contributing any dogmatical
  11746. addition, but as presenting to us another material support in our
  11747. critical investigations. For it furnishes us with an indirect proof
  11748. of the transcendental ideality of phenomena, if our minds were
  11749. not completely satisfied with the direct proof set forth in the
  11750. Trancendental Aesthetic. The proof would proceed in the following
  11751. dilemma. If the world is a whole existing in itself, it must be either
  11752. finite or infinite. But it is neither finite nor infinite--as has been
  11753. shown, on the one side, by the thesis, on the other, by the antithesis.
  11754. Therefore the world--the content of all phenomena--is not a whole
  11755. existing in itself. It follows that phenomena are nothing, apart
  11756. from our representations. And this is what we mean by transcendental
  11757. ideality.
  11758. This remark is of some importance. It enables us to see that the proofs
  11759. of the fourfold antinomy are not mere sophistries--are not fallacious,
  11760. but grounded on the nature of reason, and valid--under the supposition
  11761. that phenomena are things in themselves. The opposition of the
  11762. judgements which follow makes it evident that a fallacy lay in the
  11763. initial supposition, and thus helps us to discover the true constitution
  11764. of objects of sense. This transcendental dialectic does not favour
  11765. scepticism, although it presents us with a triumphant demonstration of
  11766. the advantages of the sceptical method, the great utility of which is
  11767. apparent in the antinomy, where the arguments of reason were allowed to
  11768. confront each other in undiminished force. And although the result of
  11769. these conflicts of reason is not what we expected--although we have
  11770. obtained no positive dogmatical addition to metaphysical science--we
  11771. have still reaped a great advantage in the correction of our judgements
  11772. on these subjects of thought.
  11773. SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the
  11774. Cosmological Ideas.
  11775. The cosmological principle of totality could not give us any certain
  11776. knowledge in regard to the maximum in the series of conditions in the
  11777. world of sense, considered as a thing in itself. The actual regress in
  11778. the series is the only means of approaching this maximum. This principle
  11779. of pure reason, therefore, may still be considered as valid--not as an
  11780. axiom enabling us to cogitate totality in the object as actual, but as
  11781. a problem for the understanding, which requires it to institute and
  11782. to continue, in conformity with the idea of totality in the mind, the
  11783. regress in the series of the conditions of a given conditioned. For in
  11784. the world of sense, that is, in space and time, every condition which
  11785. we discover in our investigation of phenomena is itself conditioned;
  11786. because sensuous objects are not things in themselves (in which case an
  11787. absolutely unconditioned might be reached in the progress of cognition),
  11788. but are merely empirical representations the conditions of which must
  11789. always be found in intuition. The principle of reason is therefore
  11790. properly a mere rule--prescribing a regress in the series of conditions
  11791. for given phenomena, and prohibiting any pause or rest on an absolutely
  11792. unconditioned. It is, therefore, not a principle of the possibility
  11793. of experience or of the empirical cognition of sensuous
  11794. objects--consequently not a principle of the understanding; for every
  11795. experience is confined within certain proper limits determined by the
  11796. given intuition. Still less is it a constitutive principle of reason
  11797. authorizing us to extend our conception of the sensuous world beyond all
  11798. possible experience. It is merely a principle for the enlargement and
  11799. extension of experience as far as is possible for human faculties. It
  11800. forbids us to consider any empirical limits as absolute. It is, hence, a
  11801. principle of reason, which, as a rule, dictates how we ought to proceed
  11802. in our empirical regress, but is unable to anticipate or indicate prior
  11803. to the empirical regress what is given in the object itself. I have
  11804. termed it for this reason a regulative principle of reason; while the
  11805. principle of the absolute totality of the series of conditions,
  11806. as existing in itself and given in the object, is a constitutive
  11807. cosmological principle. This distinction will at once demonstrate the
  11808. falsehood of the constitutive principle, and prevent us from attributing
  11809. (by a transcendental subreptio) objective reality to an idea, which is
  11810. valid only as a rule.
  11811. In order to understand the proper meaning of this rule of pure reason,
  11812. we must notice first that it cannot tell us what the object is, but only
  11813. how the empirical regress is to be proceeded with in order to attain to
  11814. the complete conception of the object. If it gave us any information in
  11815. respect to the former statement, it would be a constitutive principle--a
  11816. principle impossible from the nature of pure reason. It will not
  11817. therefore enable us to establish any such conclusions as: "The series
  11818. of conditions for a given conditioned is in itself finite," or, "It is
  11819. infinite." For, in this case, we should be cogitating in the mere idea
  11820. of absolute totality, an object which is not and cannot be given in
  11821. experience; inasmuch as we should be attributing a reality objective and
  11822. independent of the empirical synthesis, to a series of phenomena. This
  11823. idea of reason cannot then be regarded as valid--except as a rule for
  11824. the regressive synthesis in the series of conditions, according to
  11825. which we must proceed from the conditioned, through all intermediate and
  11826. subordinate conditions, up to the unconditioned; although this goal is
  11827. unattained and unattainable. For the absolutely unconditioned cannot be
  11828. discovered in the sphere of experience.
  11829. We now proceed to determine clearly our notion of a synthesis which
  11830. can never be complete. There are two terms commonly employed for this
  11831. purpose. These terms are regarded as expressions of different and
  11832. distinguishable notions, although the ground of the distinction has
  11833. never been clearly exposed. The term employed by the mathematicians
  11834. is progressus in infinitum. The philosophers prefer the expression
  11835. progressus in indefinitum. Without detaining the reader with an
  11836. examination of the reasons for such a distinction, or with remarks
  11837. on the right or wrong use of the terms, I shall endeavour clearly to
  11838. determine these conceptions, so far as is necessary for the purpose in
  11839. this Critique.
  11840. We may, with propriety, say of a straight line, that it may be produced
  11841. to infinity. In this case the distinction between a progressus in
  11842. infinitum and a progressus in indefinitum is a mere piece of subtlety.
  11843. For, although when we say, "Produce a straight line," it is more correct
  11844. to say in indefinitum than in infinitum; because the former means,
  11845. "Produce it as far as you please," the second, "You must not cease to
  11846. produce it"; the expression in infinitum is, when we are speaking of the
  11847. power to do it, perfectly correct, for we can always make it longer if
  11848. we please--on to infinity. And this remark holds good in all cases, when
  11849. we speak of a progressus, that is, an advancement from the condition to
  11850. the conditioned; this possible advancement always proceeds to infinity.
  11851. We may proceed from a given pair in the descending line of generation
  11852. from father to son, and cogitate a never-ending line of descendants from
  11853. it. For in such a case reason does not demand absolute totality in the
  11854. series, because it does not presuppose it as a condition and as given
  11855. (datum), but merely as conditioned, and as capable of being given
  11856. (dabile).
  11857. Very different is the case with the problem: "How far the regress, which
  11858. ascends from the given conditioned to the conditions, must extend";
  11859. whether I can say: "It is a regress in infinitum," or only "in
  11860. indefinitum"; and whether, for example, setting out from the human
  11861. beings at present alive in the world, I may ascend in the series of
  11862. their ancestors, in infinitum--mr whether all that can be said is, that
  11863. so far as I have proceeded, I have discovered no empirical ground for
  11864. considering the series limited, so that I am justified, and indeed,
  11865. compelled to search for ancestors still further back, although I am not
  11866. obliged by the idea of reason to presuppose them.
  11867. My answer to this question is: "If the series is given in empirical
  11868. intuition as a whole, the regress in the series of its internal
  11869. conditions proceeds in infinitum; but, if only one member of the series
  11870. is given, from which the regress is to proceed to absolute totality, the
  11871. regress is possible only in indefinitum." For example, the division of
  11872. a portion of matter given within certain limits--of a body, that
  11873. is--proceeds in infinitum. For, as the condition of this whole is its
  11874. part, and the condition of the part a part of the part, and so on, and
  11875. as in this regress of decomposition an unconditioned indivisible member
  11876. of the series of conditions is not to be found; there are no reasons
  11877. or grounds in experience for stopping in the division, but, on the
  11878. contrary, the more remote members of the division are actually and
  11879. empirically given prior to this division. That is to say, the division
  11880. proceeds to infinity. On the other hand, the series of ancestors of
  11881. any given human being is not given, in its absolute totality, in any
  11882. experience, and yet the regress proceeds from every genealogical member
  11883. of this series to one still higher, and does not meet with any empirical
  11884. limit presenting an absolutely unconditioned member of the series.
  11885. But as the members of such a series are not contained in the empirical
  11886. intuition of the whole, prior to the regress, this regress does not
  11887. proceed to infinity, but only in indefinitum, that is, we are called
  11888. upon to discover other and higher members, which are themselves always
  11889. conditioned.
  11890. In neither case--the regressus in infinitum, nor the regressus in
  11891. indefinitum, is the series of conditions to be considered as actually
  11892. infinite in the object itself. This might be true of things in
  11893. themselves, but it cannot be asserted of phenomena, which, as conditions
  11894. of each other, are only given in the empirical regress itself. Hence,
  11895. the question no longer is, "What is the quantity of this series of
  11896. conditions in itself--is it finite or infinite?" for it is nothing in
  11897. itself; but, "How is the empirical regress to be commenced, and how
  11898. far ought we to proceed with it?" And here a signal distinction in
  11899. the application of this rule becomes apparent. If the whole is given
  11900. empirically, it is possible to recede in the series of its internal
  11901. conditions to infinity. But if the whole is not given, and can only
  11902. be given by and through the empirical regress, I can only say: "It
  11903. is possible to infinity, to proceed to still higher conditions in
  11904. the series." In the first case, I am justified in asserting that more
  11905. members are empirically given in the object than I attain to in the
  11906. regress (of decomposition). In the second case, I am justified only in
  11907. saying, that I can always proceed further in the regress, because no
  11908. member of the series is given as absolutely conditioned, and thus
  11909. a higher member is possible, and an inquiry with regard to it is
  11910. necessary. In the one case it is necessary to find other members of the
  11911. series, in the other it is necessary to inquire for others, inasmuch as
  11912. experience presents no absolute limitation of the regress. For, either
  11913. you do not possess a perception which absolutely limits your empirical
  11914. regress, and in this case the regress cannot be regarded as complete;
  11915. or, you do possess such a limitative perception, in which case it is not
  11916. a part of your series (for that which limits must be distinct from
  11917. that which is limited by it), and it is incumbent you to continue your
  11918. regress up to this condition, and so on.
  11919. These remarks will be placed in their proper light by their application
  11920. in the following section.
  11921. SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of
  11922. Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas.
  11923. We have shown that no transcendental use can be made either of the
  11924. conceptions of reason or of understanding. We have shown, likewise, that
  11925. the demand of absolute totality in the series of conditions in the world
  11926. of sense arises from a transcendental employment of reason, resting on
  11927. the opinion that phenomena are to be regarded as things in themselves.
  11928. It follows that we are not required to answer the question respecting
  11929. the absolute quantity of a series--whether it is in itself limited or
  11930. unlimited. We are only called upon to determine how far we must proceed
  11931. in the empirical regress from condition to condition, in order to
  11932. discover, in conformity with the rule of reason, a full and correct
  11933. answer to the questions proposed by reason itself.
  11934. This principle of reason is hence valid only as a rule for the extension
  11935. of a possible experience--its invalidity as a principle constitutive of
  11936. phenomena in themselves having been sufficiently demonstrated. And thus,
  11937. too, the antinomial conflict of reason with itself is completely put an
  11938. end to; inasmuch as we have not only presented a critical solution of
  11939. the fallacy lurking in the opposite statements of reason, but have shown
  11940. the true meaning of the ideas which gave rise to these statements. The
  11941. dialectical principle of reason has, therefore, been changed into a
  11942. doctrinal principle. But in fact, if this principle, in the subjective
  11943. signification which we have shown to be its only true sense, may be
  11944. guaranteed as a principle of the unceasing extension of the employment
  11945. of our understanding, its influence and value are just as great as if
  11946. it were an axiom for the a priori determination of objects. For such
  11947. an axiom could not exert a stronger influence on the extension and
  11948. rectification of our knowledge, otherwise than by procuring for the
  11949. principles of the understanding the most widely expanded employment in
  11950. the field of experience.
  11951. I. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the
  11952. Composition of Phenomena in the Universe.
  11953. Here, as well as in the case of the other cosmological problems, the
  11954. ground of the regulative principle of reason is the proposition that
  11955. in our empirical regress no experience of an absolute limit, and
  11956. consequently no experience of a condition, which is itself absolutely
  11957. unconditioned, is discoverable. And the truth of this proposition itself
  11958. rests upon the consideration that such an experience must represent
  11959. to us phenomena as limited by nothing or the mere void, on which our
  11960. continued regress by means of perception must abut--which is impossible.
  11961. Now this proposition, which declares that every condition attained in
  11962. the empirical regress must itself be considered empirically conditioned,
  11963. contains the rule in terminis, which requires me, to whatever extent
  11964. I may have proceeded in the ascending series, always to look for some
  11965. higher member in the series--whether this member is to become known to
  11966. me through experience, or not.
  11967. Nothing further is necessary, then, for the solution of the first
  11968. cosmological problem, than to decide, whether, in the regress to the
  11969. unconditioned quantity of the universe (as regards space and time),
  11970. this never limited ascent ought to be called a regressus in infinitum or
  11971. indefinitum.
  11972. The general representation which we form in our minds of the series of
  11973. all past states or conditions of the world, or of all the things which
  11974. at present exist in it, is itself nothing more than a possible empirical
  11975. regress, which is cogitated--although in an undetermined manner--in the
  11976. mind, and which gives rise to the conception of a series of conditions
  11977. for a given object.* Now I have a conception of the universe, but not
  11978. an intuition--that is, not an intuition of it as a whole. Thus I cannot
  11979. infer the magnitude of the regress from the quantity or magnitude of the
  11980. world, and determine the former by means of the latter; on the contrary,
  11981. I must first of all form a conception of the quantity or magnitude
  11982. of the world from the magnitude of the empirical regress. But of this
  11983. regress I know nothing more than that I ought to proceed from every
  11984. given member of the series of conditions to one still higher. But the
  11985. quantity of the universe is not thereby determined, and we cannot affirm
  11986. that this regress proceeds in infinitum. Such an affirmation would
  11987. anticipate the members of the series which have not yet been reached,
  11988. and represent the number of them as beyond the grasp of any empirical
  11989. synthesis; it would consequently determine the cosmical quantity
  11990. prior to the regress (although only in a negative manner)--which is
  11991. impossible. For the world is not given in its totality in any intuition:
  11992. consequently, its quantity cannot be given prior to the regress. It
  11993. follows that we are unable to make any declaration respecting the
  11994. cosmical quantity in itself--not even that the regress in it is a
  11995. regress in infinitum; we must only endeavour to attain to a conception
  11996. of the quantity of the universe, in conformity with the rule which
  11997. determines the empirical regress in it. But this rule merely requires
  11998. us never to admit an absolute limit to our series--how far soever we may
  11999. have proceeded in it, but always, on the contrary, to subordinate every
  12000. phenomenon to some other as its condition, and consequently to proceed
  12001. to this higher phenomenon. Such a regress is, therefore, the regressus
  12002. in indefinitum, which, as not determining a quantity in the object, is
  12003. clearly distinguishable from the regressus in infinitum.
  12004. [*Footnote: The cosmical series can neither be greater nor smaller than
  12005. the possible empirical regress, upon which its conception is based. And
  12006. as this regress cannot be a determinate infinite regress, still less a
  12007. determinate finite (absolutely limited), it is evident that we cannot
  12008. regard the world as either finite or infinite, because the regress,
  12009. which gives us the representation of the world, is neither finite nor
  12010. infinite.]
  12011. It follows from what we have said that we are not justified in declaring
  12012. the world to be infinite in space, or as regards past time. For this
  12013. conception of an infinite given quantity is empirical; but we cannot
  12014. apply the conception of an infinite quantity to the world as an object
  12015. of the senses. I cannot say, "The regress from a given perception to
  12016. everything limited either in space or time, proceeds in infinitum," for
  12017. this presupposes an infinite cosmical quantity; neither can I say, "It
  12018. is finite," for an absolute limit is likewise impossible in experience.
  12019. It follows that I am not entitled to make any assertion at all
  12020. respecting the whole object of experience--the world of sense; I must
  12021. limit my declarations to the rule according to which experience or
  12022. empirical knowledge is to be attained.
  12023. To the question, therefore, respecting the cosmical quantity, the first
  12024. and negative answer is: "The world has no beginning in time, and no
  12025. absolute limit in space."
  12026. For, in the contrary case, it would be limited by a void time on the
  12027. one hand, and by a void space on the other. Now, since the world, as a
  12028. phenomenon, cannot be thus limited in itself for a phenomenon is not a
  12029. thing in itself; it must be possible for us to have a perception of this
  12030. limitation by a void time and a void space. But such a perception--such
  12031. an experience is impossible; because it has no content. Consequently,
  12032. an absolute cosmical limit is empirically, and therefore absolutely,
  12033. impossible.*
  12034. [*Footnote: The reader will remark that the proof presented above is
  12035. very different from the dogmatical demonstration given in the antithesis
  12036. of the first antinomy. In that demonstration, it was taken for granted
  12037. that the world is a thing in itself--given in its totality prior to
  12038. all regress, and a determined position in space and time was denied to
  12039. it--if it was not considered as occupying all time and all space. Hence
  12040. our conclusion differed from that given above; for we inferred in the
  12041. antithesis the actual infinity of the world.]
  12042. From this follows the affirmative answer: "The regress in the series
  12043. of phenomena--as a determination of the cosmical quantity, proceeds in
  12044. indefinitum." This is equivalent to saying: "The world of sense has no
  12045. absolute quantity, but the empirical regress (through which alone the
  12046. world of sense is presented to us on the side of its conditions) rests
  12047. upon a rule, which requires it to proceed from every member of the
  12048. series, as conditioned, to one still more remote (whether through
  12049. personal experience, or by means of history, or the chain of cause and
  12050. effect), and not to cease at any point in this extension of the possible
  12051. empirical employment of the understanding." And this is the proper and
  12052. only use which reason can make of its principles.
  12053. The above rule does not prescribe an unceasing regress in one kind of
  12054. phenomena. It does not, for example, forbid us, in our ascent from an
  12055. individual human being through the line of his ancestors, to expect that
  12056. we shall discover at some point of the regress a primeval pair, or to
  12057. admit, in the series of heavenly bodies, a sun at the farthest possible
  12058. distance from some centre. All that it demands is a perpetual progress
  12059. from phenomena to phenomena, even although an actual perception is not
  12060. presented by them (as in the case of our perceptions being so weak
  12061. as that we are unable to become conscious of them), since they,
  12062. nevertheless, belong to possible experience.
  12063. Every beginning is in time, and all limits to extension are in space.
  12064. But space and time are in the world of sense. Consequently phenomena
  12065. in the world are conditionally limited, but the world itself is not
  12066. limited, either conditionally or unconditionally.
  12067. For this reason, and because neither the world nor the cosmical series
  12068. of conditions to a given conditioned can be completely given, our
  12069. conception of the cosmical quantity is given only in and through the
  12070. regress and not prior to it--in a collective intuition. But the regress
  12071. itself is really nothing more than the determining of the cosmical
  12072. quantity, and cannot therefore give us any determined conception of
  12073. it--still less a conception of a quantity which is, in relation to a
  12074. certain standard, infinite. The regress does not, therefore, proceed to
  12075. infinity (an infinity given), but only to an indefinite extent, for or
  12076. the of presenting to us a quantity--realized only in and through the
  12077. regress itself.
  12078. II. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the Division
  12079. of a Whole given in Intuition.
  12080. When I divide a whole which is given in intuition, I proceed from a
  12081. conditioned to its conditions. The division of the parts of the whole
  12082. (subdivisio or decompositio) is a regress in the series of these
  12083. conditions. The absolute totality of this series would be actually
  12084. attained and given to the mind, if the regress could arrive at simple
  12085. parts. But if all the parts in a continuous decomposition are themselves
  12086. divisible, the division, that is to say, the regress, proceeds from the
  12087. conditioned to its conditions in infinitum; because the conditions (the
  12088. parts) are themselves contained in the conditioned, and, as the latter
  12089. is given in a limited intuition, the former are all given along with it.
  12090. This regress cannot, therefore, be called a regressus in indefinitum, as
  12091. happened in the case of the preceding cosmological idea, the regress
  12092. in which proceeded from the conditioned to the conditions not given
  12093. contemporaneously and along with it, but discoverable only through the
  12094. empirical regress. We are not, however, entitled to affirm of a whole
  12095. of this kind, which is divisible in infinitum, that it consists of an
  12096. infinite number of parts. For, although all the parts are contained in
  12097. the intuition of the whole, the whole division is not contained therein.
  12098. The division is contained only in the progressing decomposition--in the
  12099. regress itself, which is the condition of the possibility and actuality
  12100. of the series. Now, as this regress is infinite, all the members
  12101. (parts) to which it attains must be contained in the given whole as an
  12102. aggregate. But the complete series of division is not contained therein.
  12103. For this series, being infinite in succession and always incomplete,
  12104. cannot represent an infinite number of members, and still less a
  12105. composition of these members into a whole.
  12106. To apply this remark to space. Every limited part of space presented to
  12107. intuition is a whole, the parts of which are always spaces--to whatever
  12108. extent subdivided. Every limited space is hence divisible to infinity.
  12109. Let us again apply the remark to an external phenomenon enclosed in
  12110. limits, that is, a body. The divisibility of a body rests upon the
  12111. divisibility of space, which is the condition of the possibility of the
  12112. body as an extended whole. A body is consequently divisible to infinity,
  12113. though it does not, for that reason, consist of an infinite number of
  12114. parts.
  12115. It certainly seems that, as a body must be cogitated as substance
  12116. in space, the law of divisibility would not be applicable to it as
  12117. substance. For we may and ought to grant, in the case of space, that
  12118. division or decomposition, to any extent, never can utterly annihilate
  12119. composition (that is to say, the smallest part of space must still
  12120. consist of spaces); otherwise space would entirely cease to
  12121. exist--which is impossible. But, the assertion on the other band that
  12122. when all composition in matter is annihilated in thought, nothing
  12123. remains, does not seem to harmonize with the conception of substance,
  12124. which must be properly the subject of all composition and must remain,
  12125. even after the conjunction of its attributes in space--which constituted
  12126. a body--is annihilated in thought. But this is not the case with
  12127. substance in the phenomenal world, which is not a thing in itself
  12128. cogitated by the pure category. Phenomenal substance is not an absolute
  12129. subject; it is merely a permanent sensuous image, and nothing more than
  12130. an intuition, in which the unconditioned is not to be found.
  12131. But, although this rule of progress to infinity is legitimate and
  12132. applicable to the subdivision of a phenomenon, as a mere occupation or
  12133. filling of space, it is not applicable to a whole consisting of a number
  12134. of distinct parts and constituting a quantum discretum--that is to say,
  12135. an organized body. It cannot be admitted that every part in an organized
  12136. whole is itself organized, and that, in analysing it to infinity, we
  12137. must always meet with organized parts; although we may allow that the
  12138. parts of the matter which we decompose in infinitum, may be organized.
  12139. For the infinity of the division of a phenomenon in space rests
  12140. altogether on the fact that the divisibility of a phenomenon is given
  12141. only in and through this infinity, that is, an undetermined number of
  12142. parts is given, while the parts themselves are given and determined only
  12143. in and through the subdivision; in a word, the infinity of the division
  12144. necessarily presupposes that the whole is not already divided in se.
  12145. Hence our division determines a number of parts in the whole--a number
  12146. which extends just as far as the actual regress in the division; while,
  12147. on the other hand, the very notion of a body organized to infinity
  12148. represents the whole as already and in itself divided. We expect,
  12149. therefore, to find in it a determinate, but at the same time, infinite,
  12150. number of parts--which is self-contradictory. For we should thus have a
  12151. whole containing a series of members which could not be completed in
  12152. any regress--which is infinite, and at the same time complete in an
  12153. organized composite. Infinite divisibility is applicable only to a
  12154. quantum continuum, and is based entirely on the infinite divisibility
  12155. of space, But in a quantum discretum the multitude of parts or units is
  12156. always determined, and hence always equal to some number. To what extent
  12157. a body may be organized, experience alone can inform us; and although,
  12158. so far as our experience of this or that body has extended, we may not
  12159. have discovered any inorganic part, such parts must exist in possible
  12160. experience. But how far the transcendental division of a phenomenon
  12161. must extend, we cannot know from experience--it is a question which
  12162. experience cannot answer; it is answered only by the principle of reason
  12163. which forbids us to consider the empirical regress, in the analysis of
  12164. extended body, as ever absolutely complete.
  12165. Concluding Remark on the Solution of the Transcendental Mathematical
  12166. Ideas--and Introductory to the Solution of the Dynamical Ideas.
  12167. We presented the antinomy of pure reason in a tabular form, and we
  12168. endeavoured to show the ground of this self-contradiction on the part
  12169. of reason, and the only means of bringing it to a conclusion--namely, by
  12170. declaring both contradictory statements to be false. We represented
  12171. in these antinomies the conditions of phenomena as belonging to the
  12172. conditioned according to relations of space and time--which is the
  12173. usual supposition of the common understanding. In this respect, all
  12174. dialectical representations of totality, in the series of conditions
  12175. to a given conditioned, were perfectly homogeneous. The condition was
  12176. always a member of the series along with the conditioned, and thus the
  12177. homogeneity of the whole series was assured. In this case the regress
  12178. could never be cogitated as complete; or, if this was the case, a member
  12179. really conditioned was falsely regarded as a primal member, consequently
  12180. as unconditioned. In such an antinomy, therefore, we did not consider
  12181. the object, that is, the conditioned, but the series of conditions
  12182. belonging to the object, and the magnitude of that series. And thus
  12183. arose the difficulty--a difficulty not to be settled by any decision
  12184. regarding the claims of the two parties, but simply by cutting the
  12185. knot--by declaring the series proposed by reason to be either too long
  12186. or too short for the understanding, which could in neither case make its
  12187. conceptions adequate with the ideas.
  12188. But we have overlooked, up to this point, an essential difference
  12189. existing between the conceptions of the understanding which reason
  12190. endeavours to raise to the rank of ideas--two of these indicating a
  12191. mathematical, and two a dynamical synthesis of phenomena. Hitherto, it
  12192. was necessary to signalize this distinction; for, just as in our general
  12193. representation of all transcendental ideas, we considered them under
  12194. phenomenal conditions, so, in the two mathematical ideas, our discussion
  12195. is concerned solely with an object in the world of phenomena. But as
  12196. we are now about to proceed to the consideration of the dynamical
  12197. conceptions of the understanding, and their adequateness with ideas, we
  12198. must not lose sight of this distinction. We shall find that it opens up
  12199. to us an entirely new view of the conflict in which reason is involved.
  12200. For, while in the first two antinomies, both parties were dismissed, on
  12201. the ground of having advanced statements based upon false hypothesis; in
  12202. the present case the hope appears of discovering a hypothesis which may
  12203. be consistent with the demands of reason, and, the judge completing the
  12204. statement of the grounds of claim, which both parties had left in an
  12205. unsatisfactory state, the question may be settled on its own merits,
  12206. not by dismissing the claimants, but by a comparison of the arguments on
  12207. both sides. If we consider merely their extension, and whether they are
  12208. adequate with ideas, the series of conditions may be regarded as all
  12209. homogeneous. But the conception of the understanding which lies at the
  12210. basis of these ideas, contains either a synthesis of the homogeneous
  12211. (presupposed in every quantity--in its composition as well as in its
  12212. division) or of the heterogeneous, which is the case in the dynamical
  12213. synthesis of cause and effect, as well as of the necessary and the
  12214. contingent.
  12215. Thus it happens that in the mathematical series of phenomena no other
  12216. than a sensuous condition is admissible--a condition which is itself a
  12217. member of the series; while the dynamical series of sensuous conditions
  12218. admits a heterogeneous condition, which is not a member of the series,
  12219. but, as purely intelligible, lies out of and beyond it. And thus reason
  12220. is satisfied, and an unconditioned placed at the head of the series
  12221. of phenomena, without introducing confusion into or discontinuing it,
  12222. contrary to the principles of the understanding.
  12223. Now, from the fact that the dynamical ideas admit a condition of
  12224. phenomena which does not form a part of the series of phenomena, arises
  12225. a result which we should not have expected from an antinomy. In former
  12226. cases, the result was that both contradictory dialectical statements
  12227. were declared to be false. In the present case, we find the conditioned
  12228. in the dynamical series connected with an empirically unconditioned,
  12229. but non-sensuous condition; and thus satisfaction is done to the
  12230. understanding on the one hand and to the reason on the other.* While,
  12231. moreover, the dialectical arguments for unconditioned totality in mere
  12232. phenomena fall to the ground, both propositions of reason may be shown
  12233. to be true in their proper signification. This could not happen in
  12234. the case of the cosmological ideas which demanded a mathematically
  12235. unconditioned unity; for no condition could be placed at the head of
  12236. the series of phenomena, except one which was itself a phenomenon and
  12237. consequently a member of the series.
  12238. [*Footnote: For the understanding cannot admit among phenomena a
  12239. condition which is itself empirically unconditioned. But if it is
  12240. possible to cogitate an intelligible condition--one which is not a
  12241. member of the series of phenomena--for a conditioned phenomenon, without
  12242. breaking the series of empirical conditions, such a condition may be
  12243. admissible as empirically unconditioned, and the empirical regress
  12244. continue regular, unceasing, and intact.]
  12245. III. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the
  12246. Deduction of Cosmical Events from their Causes.
  12247. There are only two modes of causality cogitable--the causality of nature
  12248. or of freedom. The first is the conjunction of a particular state with
  12249. another preceding it in the world of sense, the former following the
  12250. latter by virtue of a law. Now, as the causality of phenomena is
  12251. subject to conditions of time, and the preceding state, if it had always
  12252. existed, could not have produced an effect which would make its first
  12253. appearance at a particular time, the causality of a cause must itself be
  12254. an effect--must itself have begun to be, and therefore, according to the
  12255. principle of the understanding, itself requires a cause.
  12256. We must understand, on the contrary, by the term freedom, in the
  12257. cosmological sense, a faculty of the spontaneous origination of a state;
  12258. the causality of which, therefore, is not subordinated to another cause
  12259. determining it in time. Freedom is in this sense a pure transcendental
  12260. idea, which, in the first place, contains no empirical element; the
  12261. object of which, in the second place, cannot be given or determined in
  12262. any experience, because it is a universal law of the very possibility
  12263. of experience, that everything which happens must have a cause, that
  12264. consequently the causality of a cause, being itself something that has
  12265. happened, must also have a cause. In this view of the case, the whole
  12266. field of experience, how far soever it may extend, contains nothing that
  12267. is not subject to the laws of nature. But, as we cannot by this means
  12268. attain to an absolute totality of conditions in reference to the series
  12269. of causes and effects, reason creates the idea of a spontaneity, which
  12270. can begin to act of itself, and without any external cause determining
  12271. it to action, according to the natural law of causality.
  12272. It is especially remarkable that the practical conception of freedom
  12273. is based upon the transcendental idea, and that the question of
  12274. the possibility of the former is difficult only as it involves the
  12275. consideration of the truth of the latter. Freedom, in the practical
  12276. sense, is the independence of the will of coercion by sensuous impulses.
  12277. A will is sensuous, in so far as it is pathologically affected (by
  12278. sensuous impulses); it is termed animal (arbitrium brutum), when it is
  12279. pathologically necessitated. The human will is certainly an arbitrium
  12280. sensitivum, not brutum, but liberum; because sensuousness does not
  12281. necessitate its action, a faculty existing in man of self-determination,
  12282. independently of all sensuous coercion.
  12283. It is plain that, if all causality in the world of sense were
  12284. natural--and natural only--every event would be determined by another
  12285. according to necessary laws, and that, consequently, phenomena, in
  12286. so far as they determine the will, must necessitate every action as a
  12287. natural effect from themselves; and thus all practical freedom would
  12288. fall to the ground with the transcendental idea. For the latter
  12289. presupposes that although a certain thing has not happened, it ought to
  12290. have happened, and that, consequently, its phenomenal cause was not so
  12291. powerful and determinative as to exclude the causality of our will--a
  12292. causality capable of producing effects independently of and even in
  12293. opposition to the power of natural causes, and capable, consequently, of
  12294. spontaneously originating a series of events.
  12295. Here, too, we find it to be the case, as we generally found in the
  12296. self-contradictions and perplexities of a reason which strives to pass
  12297. the bounds of possible experience, that the problem is properly not
  12298. physiological, but transcendental. The question of the possibility
  12299. of freedom does indeed concern psychology; but, as it rests upon
  12300. dialectical arguments of pure reason, its solution must engage the
  12301. attention of transcendental philosophy. Before attempting this solution,
  12302. a task which transcendental philosophy cannot decline, it will
  12303. be advisable to make a remark with regard to its procedure in the
  12304. settlement of the question.
  12305. If phenomena were things in themselves, and time and space forms of the
  12306. existence of things, condition and conditioned would always be members
  12307. of the same series; and thus would arise in the present case the
  12308. antinomy common to all transcendental ideas--that their series is either
  12309. too great or too small for the understanding. The dynamical ideas, which
  12310. we are about to discuss in this and the following section, possess the
  12311. peculiarity of relating to an object, not considered as a quantity, but
  12312. as an existence; and thus, in the discussion of the present question,
  12313. we may make abstraction of the quantity of the series of conditions,
  12314. and consider merely the dynamical relation of the condition to the
  12315. conditioned. The question, then, suggests itself, whether freedom is
  12316. possible; and, if it is, whether it can consist with the universality
  12317. of the natural law of causality; and, consequently, whether we enounce a
  12318. proper disjunctive proposition when we say: "Every effect must have its
  12319. origin either in nature or in freedom," or whether both cannot exist
  12320. together in the same event in different relations. The principle of
  12321. an unbroken connection between all events in the phenomenal world, in
  12322. accordance with the unchangeable laws of nature, is a well-established
  12323. principle of transcendental analytic which admits of no exception. The
  12324. question, therefore, is: "Whether an effect, determined according to
  12325. the laws of nature, can at the same time be produced by a free agent, or
  12326. whether freedom and nature mutually exclude each other?" And here, the
  12327. common but fallacious hypothesis of the absolute reality of phenomena
  12328. manifests its injurious influence in embarrassing the procedure
  12329. of reason. For if phenomena are things in themselves, freedom is
  12330. impossible. In this case, nature is the complete and all-sufficient
  12331. cause of every event; and condition and conditioned, cause and effect
  12332. are contained in the same series, and necessitated by the same law. If,
  12333. on the contrary, phenomena are held to be, as they are in fact, nothing
  12334. more than mere representations, connected with each other in accordance
  12335. with empirical laws, they must have a ground which is not phenomenal.
  12336. But the causality of such an intelligible cause is not determined or
  12337. determinable by phenomena; although its effects, as phenomena, must be
  12338. determined by other phenomenal existences. This cause and its causality
  12339. exist therefore out of and apart from the series of phenomena; while
  12340. its effects do exist and are discoverable in the series of empirical
  12341. conditions. Such an effect may therefore be considered to be free in
  12342. relation to its intelligible cause, and necessary in relation to the
  12343. phenomena from which it is a necessary consequence--a distinction which,
  12344. stated in this perfectly general and abstract manner, must appear in
  12345. the highest degree subtle and obscure. The sequel will explain. It is
  12346. sufficient, at present, to remark that, as the complete and unbroken
  12347. connection of phenomena is an unalterable law of nature, freedom is
  12348. impossible--on the supposition that phenomena are absolutely real. Hence
  12349. those philosophers who adhere to the common opinion on this subject can
  12350. never succeed in reconciling the ideas of nature and freedom.
  12351. Possibility of Freedom in Harmony with the Universal Law of Natural
  12352. Necessity.
  12353. That element in a sensuous object which is not itself sensuous, I may be
  12354. allowed to term intelligible. If, accordingly, an object which must be
  12355. regarded as a sensuous phenomenon possesses a faculty which is not an
  12356. object of sensuous intuition, but by means of which it is capable of
  12357. being the cause of phenomena, the causality of an object or existence of
  12358. this kind may be regarded from two different points of view. It may be
  12359. considered to be intelligible, as regards its action--the action of
  12360. a thing which is a thing in itself, and sensuous, as regards its
  12361. effects--the effects of a phenomenon belonging to the sensuous world. We
  12362. should accordingly, have to form both an empirical and an intellectual
  12363. conception of the causality of such a faculty or power--both, however,
  12364. having reference to the same effect. This twofold manner of cogitating
  12365. a power residing in a sensuous object does not run counter to any of
  12366. the conceptions which we ought to form of the world of phenomena or of
  12367. a possible experience. Phenomena--not being things in themselves--must
  12368. have a transcendental object as a foundation, which determines them as
  12369. mere representations; and there seems to be no reason why we should not
  12370. ascribe to this transcendental object, in addition to the property of
  12371. self-phenomenization, a causality whose effects are to be met with in
  12372. the world of phenomena, although it is not itself a phenomenon. But
  12373. every effective cause must possess a character, that is to say, a law of
  12374. its causality, without which it would cease to be a cause. In the above
  12375. case, then, every sensuous object would possess an empirical character,
  12376. which guaranteed that its actions, as phenomena, stand in complete and
  12377. harmonious connection, conformably to unvarying natural laws, with all
  12378. other phenomena, and can be deduced from these, as conditions, and that
  12379. they do thus, in connection with these, constitute a series in the order
  12380. of nature. This sensuous object must, in the second place, possess an
  12381. intelligible character, which guarantees it to be the cause of those
  12382. actions, as phenomena, although it is not itself a phenomenon nor
  12383. subordinate to the conditions of the world of sense. The former may
  12384. be termed the character of the thing as a phenomenon, the latter the
  12385. character of the thing as a thing in itself.
  12386. Now this active subject would, in its character of intelligible subject,
  12387. be subordinate to no conditions of time, for time is only a condition
  12388. of phenomena, and not of things in themselves. No action would begin or
  12389. cease to be in this subject; it would consequently be free from the law
  12390. of all determination of time--the law of change, namely, that everything
  12391. which happens must have a cause in the phenomena of a preceding
  12392. state. In one word, the causality of the subject, in so far as it is
  12393. intelligible, would not form part of the series of empirical conditions
  12394. which determine and necessitate an event in the world of sense. Again,
  12395. this intelligible character of a thing cannot be immediately cognized,
  12396. because we can perceive nothing but phenomena, but it must be capable of
  12397. being cogitated in harmony with the empirical character; for we always
  12398. find ourselves compelled to place, in thought, a transcendental object
  12399. at the basis of phenomena although we can never know what this object is
  12400. in itself.
  12401. In virtue of its empirical character, this subject would at the same
  12402. time be subordinate to all the empirical laws of causality, and, as a
  12403. phenomenon and member of the sensuous world, its effects would have
  12404. to be accounted for by a reference to preceding phenomena. Eternal
  12405. phenomena must be capable of influencing it; and its actions, in
  12406. accordance with natural laws, must explain to us how its empirical
  12407. character, that is, the law of its causality, is to be cognized in and
  12408. by means of experience. In a word, all requisites for a complete and
  12409. necessary determination of these actions must be presented to us by
  12410. experience.
  12411. In virtue of its intelligible character, on the other hand (although we
  12412. possess only a general conception of this character), the subject
  12413. must be regarded as free from all sensuous influences, and from
  12414. all phenomenal determination. Moreover, as nothing happens in this
  12415. subject--for it is a noumenon, and there does not consequently exist in
  12416. it any change, demanding the dynamical determination of time, and for
  12417. the same reason no connection with phenomena as causes--this active
  12418. existence must in its actions be free from and independent of natural
  12419. necessity, for or necessity exists only in the world of phenomena. It
  12420. would be quite correct to say that it originates or begins its effects
  12421. in the world of sense from itself, although the action productive of
  12422. these effects does not begin in itself. We should not be in this case
  12423. affirming that these sensuous effects began to exist of themselves,
  12424. because they are always determined by prior empirical conditions--by
  12425. virtue of the empirical character, which is the phenomenon of the
  12426. intelligible character--and are possible only as constituting a
  12427. continuation of the series of natural causes. And thus nature and
  12428. freedom, each in the complete and absolute signification of these terms,
  12429. can exist, without contradiction or disagreement, in the same action.
  12430. Exposition of the Cosmological Idea of Freedom in Harmony with the
  12431. Universal Law of Natural Necessity.
  12432. I have thought it advisable to lay before the reader at first merely
  12433. a sketch of the solution of this transcendental problem, in order to
  12434. enable him to form with greater ease a clear conception of the course
  12435. which reason must adopt in the solution. I shall now proceed to exhibit
  12436. the several momenta of this solution, and to consider them in their
  12437. order.
  12438. The natural law that everything which happens must have a cause, that
  12439. the causality of this cause, that is, the action of the cause (which
  12440. cannot always have existed, but must be itself an event, for it precedes
  12441. in time some effect which it has originated), must have itself a
  12442. phenomenal cause, by which it is determined and, and, consequently, all
  12443. events are empirically determined in an order of nature--this law, I
  12444. say, which lies at the foundation of the possibility of experience,
  12445. and of a connected system of phenomena or nature is a law of the
  12446. understanding, from which no departure, and to which no exception, can
  12447. be admitted. For to except even a single phenomenon from its operation
  12448. is to exclude it from the sphere of possible experience and thus to
  12449. admit it to be a mere fiction of thought or phantom of the brain.
  12450. Thus we are obliged to acknowledge the existence of a chain of causes,
  12451. in which, however, absolute totality cannot be found. But we need
  12452. not detain ourselves with this question, for it has already been
  12453. sufficiently answered in our discussion of the antinomies into which
  12454. reason falls, when it attempts to reach the unconditioned in the series
  12455. of phenomena. If we permit ourselves to be deceived by the illusion of
  12456. transcendental idealism, we shall find that neither nature nor freedom
  12457. exists. Now the question is: "Whether, admitting the existence of
  12458. natural necessity in the world of phenomena, it is possible to consider
  12459. an effect as at the same time an effect of nature and an effect of
  12460. freedom--or, whether these two modes of causality are contradictory and
  12461. incompatible?"
  12462. No phenomenal cause can absolutely and of itself begin a series. Every
  12463. action, in so far as it is productive of an event, is itself an event or
  12464. occurrence, and presupposes another preceding state, in which its cause
  12465. existed. Thus everything that happens is but a continuation of a series,
  12466. and an absolute beginning is impossible in the sensuous world. The
  12467. actions of natural causes are, accordingly, themselves effects, and
  12468. presuppose causes preceding them in time. A primal action which forms an
  12469. absolute beginning, is beyond the causal power of phenomena.
  12470. Now, is it absolutely necessary that, granting that all effects are
  12471. phenomena, the causality of the cause of these effects must also be a
  12472. phenomenon and belong to the empirical world? Is it not rather possible
  12473. that, although every effect in the phenomenal world must be connected
  12474. with an empirical cause, according to the universal law of nature, this
  12475. empirical causality may be itself the effect of a non-empirical and
  12476. intelligible causality--its connection with natural causes remaining
  12477. nevertheless intact? Such a causality would be considered, in reference
  12478. to phenomena, as the primal action of a cause, which is in so far,
  12479. therefore, not phenomenal, but, by reason of this faculty or power,
  12480. intelligible; although it must, at the same time, as a link in the chain
  12481. of nature, be regarded as belonging to the sensuous world.
  12482. A belief in the reciprocal causality of phenomena is necessary, if
  12483. we are required to look for and to present the natural conditions of
  12484. natural events, that is to say, their causes. This being admitted as
  12485. unexceptionably valid, the requirements of the understanding, which
  12486. recognizes nothing but nature in the region of phenomena, are satisfied,
  12487. and our physical explanations of physical phenomena may proceed in their
  12488. regular course, without hindrance and without opposition. But it is no
  12489. stumbling-block in the way, even assuming the idea to be a pure fiction,
  12490. to admit that there are some natural causes in the possession of a
  12491. faculty which is not empirical, but intelligible, inasmuch as it is not
  12492. determined to action by empirical conditions, but purely and solely upon
  12493. grounds brought forward by the understanding--this action being still,
  12494. when the cause is phenomenized, in perfect accordance with the laws of
  12495. empirical causality. Thus the acting subject, as a causal phenomenon,
  12496. would continue to preserve a complete connection with nature and
  12497. natural conditions; and the phenomenon only of the subject (with all
  12498. its phenomenal causality) would contain certain conditions, which, if we
  12499. ascend from the empirical to the transcendental object, must necessarily
  12500. be regarded as intelligible. For, if we attend, in our inquiries with
  12501. regard to causes in the world of phenomena, to the directions of nature
  12502. alone, we need not trouble ourselves about the relation in which the
  12503. transcendental subject, which is completely unknown to us, stands to
  12504. these phenomena and their connection in nature. The intelligible ground
  12505. of phenomena in this subject does not concern empirical questions. It
  12506. has to do only with pure thought; and, although the effects of this
  12507. thought and action of the pure understanding are discoverable in
  12508. phenomena, these phenomena must nevertheless be capable of a full and
  12509. complete explanation, upon purely physical grounds and in accordance
  12510. with natural laws. And in this case we attend solely to their empirical
  12511. and omit all consideration of their intelligible character (which is the
  12512. transcendental cause of the former) as completely unknown, except in so
  12513. far as it is exhibited by the latter as its empirical symbol. Now let us
  12514. apply this to experience. Man is a phenomenon of the sensuous world and,
  12515. at the same time, therefore, a natural cause, the causality of which
  12516. must be regulated by empirical laws. As such, he must possess an
  12517. empirical character, like all other natural phenomena. We remark this
  12518. empirical character in his actions, which reveal the presence of certain
  12519. powers and faculties. If we consider inanimate or merely animal nature,
  12520. we can discover no reason for ascribing to ourselves any other than a
  12521. faculty which is determined in a purely sensuous manner. But man, to
  12522. whom nature reveals herself only through sense, cognizes himself not
  12523. only by his senses, but also through pure apperception; and this in
  12524. actions and internal determinations, which he cannot regard as sensuous
  12525. impressions. He is thus to himself, on the one hand, a phenomenon,
  12526. but on the other hand, in respect of certain faculties, a purely
  12527. intelligible object--intelligible, because its action cannot be ascribed
  12528. to sensuous receptivity. These faculties are understanding and reason.
  12529. The latter, especially, is in a peculiar manner distinct from all
  12530. empirically-conditioned faculties, for it employs ideas alone in the
  12531. consideration of its objects, and by means of these determines the
  12532. understanding, which then proceeds to make an empirical use of its
  12533. own conceptions, which, like the ideas of reason, are pure and
  12534. non-empirical.
  12535. That reason possesses the faculty of causality, or that at least we are
  12536. compelled so to represent it, is evident from the imperatives, which in
  12537. the sphere of the practical we impose on many of our executive powers.
  12538. The words I ought express a species of necessity, and imply a connection
  12539. with grounds which nature does not and cannot present to the mind of
  12540. man. Understanding knows nothing in nature but that which is, or has
  12541. been, or will be. It would be absurd to say that anything in nature
  12542. ought to be other than it is in the relations of time in which it
  12543. stands; indeed, the ought, when we consider merely the course of nature,
  12544. has neither application nor meaning. The question, "What ought to happen
  12545. in the sphere of nature?" is just as absurd as the question, "What ought
  12546. to be the properties of a circle?" All that we are entitled to ask is,
  12547. "What takes place in nature?" or, in the latter case, "What are the
  12548. properties of a circle?"
  12549. But the idea of an ought or of duty indicates a possible action, the
  12550. ground of which is a pure conception; while the ground of a merely
  12551. natural action is, on the contrary, always a phenomenon. This action
  12552. must certainly be possible under physical conditions, if it is
  12553. prescribed by the moral imperative ought; but these physical or natural
  12554. conditions do not concern the determination of the will itself, they
  12555. relate to its effects alone, and the consequences of the effect in the
  12556. world of phenomena. Whatever number of motives nature may present to
  12557. my will, whatever sensuous impulses--the moral ought it is beyond their
  12558. power to produce. They may produce a volition, which, so far from
  12559. being necessary, is always conditioned--a volition to which the ought
  12560. enunciated by reason, sets an aim and a standard, gives permission or
  12561. prohibition. Be the object what it may, purely sensuous--as pleasure,
  12562. or presented by pure reason--as good, reason will not yield to grounds
  12563. which have an empirical origin. Reason will not follow the order
  12564. of things presented by experience, but, with perfect spontaneity,
  12565. rearranges them according to ideas, with which it compels empirical
  12566. conditions to agree. It declares, in the name of these ideas, certain
  12567. actions to be necessary which nevertheless have not taken place and
  12568. which perhaps never will take place; and yet presupposes that it
  12569. possesses the faculty of causality in relation to these actions. For,
  12570. in the absence of this supposition, it could not expect its ideas to
  12571. produce certain effects in the world of experience.
  12572. Now, let us stop here and admit it to be at least possible that reason
  12573. does stand in a really causal relation to phenomena. In this case it
  12574. must--pure reason as it is--exhibit an empirical character. For every
  12575. cause supposes a rule, according to which certain phenomena follow as
  12576. effects from the cause, and every rule requires uniformity in these
  12577. effects; and this is the proper ground of the conception of a cause--as
  12578. a faculty or power. Now this conception (of a cause) may be termed the
  12579. empirical character of reason; and this character is a permanent one,
  12580. while the effects produced appear, in conformity with the various
  12581. conditions which accompany and partly limit them, in various forms.
  12582. Thus the volition of every man has an empirical character, which is
  12583. nothing more than the causality of his reason, in so far as its effects
  12584. in the phenomenal world manifest the presence of a rule, according to
  12585. which we are enabled to examine, in their several kinds and degrees, the
  12586. actions of this causality and the rational grounds for these actions,
  12587. and in this way to decide upon the subjective principles of the
  12588. volition. Now we learn what this empirical character is only from
  12589. phenomenal effects, and from the rule of these which is presented by
  12590. experience; and for this reason all the actions of man in the world
  12591. of phenomena are determined by his empirical character, and the
  12592. co-operative causes of nature. If, then, we could investigate all the
  12593. phenomena of human volition to their lowest foundation in the mind,
  12594. there would be no action which we could not anticipate with certainty,
  12595. and recognize to be absolutely necessary from its preceding conditions.
  12596. So far as relates to this empirical character, therefore, there can be
  12597. no freedom; and it is only in the light of this character that we can
  12598. consider the human will, when we confine ourselves to simple observation
  12599. and, as is the case in anthropology, institute a physiological
  12600. investigation of the motive causes of human actions.
  12601. But when we consider the same actions in relation to reason--not for the
  12602. purpose of explaining their origin, that is, in relation to speculative
  12603. reason, but to practical reason, as the producing cause of these
  12604. actions--we shall discover a rule and an order very different from those
  12605. of nature and experience. For the declaration of this mental faculty may
  12606. be that what has and could not but take place in the course of nature,
  12607. ought not to have taken place. Sometimes, too, we discover, or believe
  12608. that we discover, that the ideas of reason did actually stand in a
  12609. causal relation to certain actions of man; and that these actions have
  12610. taken place because they were determined, not by empirical causes, but
  12611. by the act of the will upon grounds of reason.
  12612. Now, granting that reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena; can
  12613. an action of reason be called free, when we know that, sensuously, in
  12614. its empirical character, it is completely determined and absolutely
  12615. necessary? But this empirical character is itself determined by the
  12616. intelligible character. The latter we cannot cognize; we can only
  12617. indicate it by means of phenomena, which enable us to have an immediate
  12618. cognition only of the empirical character.* An action, then, in so far
  12619. as it is to be ascribed to an intelligible cause, does not result from
  12620. it in accordance with empirical laws. That is to say, not the conditions
  12621. of pure reason, but only their effects in the internal sense, precede
  12622. the act. Pure reason, as a purely intelligible faculty, is not subject
  12623. to the conditions of time. The causality of reason in its intelligible
  12624. character does not begin to be; it does not make its appearance at a
  12625. certain time, for the purpose of producing an effect. If this were not
  12626. the case, the causality of reason would be subservient to the natural
  12627. law of phenomena, which determines them according to time, and as a
  12628. series of causes and effects in time; it would consequently cease to
  12629. be freedom and become a part of nature. We are therefore justified in
  12630. saying: "If reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena, it is a
  12631. faculty which originates the sensuous condition of an empirical
  12632. series of effects." For the condition, which resides in the reason, is
  12633. non-sensuous, and therefore cannot be originated, or begin to be. And
  12634. thus we find--what we could not discover in any empirical series--a
  12635. condition of a successive series of events itself empirically
  12636. unconditioned. For, in the present case, the condition stands out of and
  12637. beyond the series of phenomena--it is intelligible, and it
  12638. consequently cannot be subjected to any sensuous condition, or to any
  12639. time-determination by a preceding cause.
  12640. [*Footnote: The real morality of actions--their merit or demerit, and
  12641. even that of our own conduct, is completely unknown to us. Our estimates
  12642. can relate only to their empirical character. How much is the result
  12643. of the action of free will, how much is to be ascribed to nature and
  12644. to blameless error, or to a happy constitution of temperament (merito
  12645. fortunae), no one can discover, nor, for this reason, determine with
  12646. perfect justice.]
  12647. But, in another respect, the same cause belongs also to the series
  12648. of phenomena. Man is himself a phenomenon. His will has an empirical
  12649. character, which is the empirical cause of all his actions. There is
  12650. no condition--determining man and his volition in conformity with this
  12651. character--which does not itself form part of the series of effects
  12652. in nature, and is subject to their law--the law according to which an
  12653. empirically undetermined cause of an event in time cannot exist.
  12654. For this reason no given action can have an absolute and spontaneous
  12655. origination, all actions being phenomena, and belonging to the world of
  12656. experience. But it cannot be said of reason, that the state in which it
  12657. determines the will is always preceded by some other state determining
  12658. it. For reason is not a phenomenon, and therefore not subject to
  12659. sensuous conditions; and, consequently, even in relation to its
  12660. causality, the sequence or conditions of time do not influence reason,
  12661. nor can the dynamical law of nature, which determines the sequence of
  12662. time according to certain rules, be applied to it.
  12663. Reason is consequently the permanent condition of all actions of the
  12664. human will. Each of these is determined in the empirical character of
  12665. the man, even before it has taken place. The intelligible character, of
  12666. which the former is but the sensuous schema, knows no before or after;
  12667. and every action, irrespective of the time-relation in which it stands
  12668. with other phenomena, is the immediate effect of the intelligible
  12669. character of pure reason, which, consequently, enjoys freedom of
  12670. action, and is not dynamically determined either by internal or external
  12671. preceding conditions. This freedom must not be described, in a merely
  12672. negative manner, as independence of empirical conditions, for in this
  12673. case the faculty of reason would cease to be a cause of phenomena; but
  12674. it must be regarded, positively, as a faculty which can spontaneously
  12675. originate a series of events. At the same time, it must not be supposed
  12676. that any beginning can take place in reason; on the contrary, reason,
  12677. as the unconditioned condition of all action of the will, admits of no
  12678. time-conditions, although its effect does really begin in a series of
  12679. phenomena--a beginning which is not, however, absolutely primal.
  12680. I shall illustrate this regulative principle of reason by an example,
  12681. from its employment in the world of experience; proved it cannot be by
  12682. any amount of experience, or by any number of facts, for such arguments
  12683. cannot establish the truth of transcendental propositions. Let us take a
  12684. voluntary action--for example, a falsehood--by means of which a man
  12685. has introduced a certain degree of confusion into the social life
  12686. of humanity, which is judged according to the motives from which it
  12687. originated, and the blame of which and of the evil consequences arising
  12688. from it, is imputed to the offender. We at first proceed to examine the
  12689. empirical character of the offence, and for this purpose we endeavour
  12690. to penetrate to the sources of that character, such as a defective
  12691. education, bad company, a shameless and wicked disposition, frivolity,
  12692. and want of reflection--not forgetting also the occasioning causes which
  12693. prevailed at the moment of the transgression. In this the procedure is
  12694. exactly the same as that pursued in the investigation of the series of
  12695. causes which determine a given physical effect. Now, although we believe
  12696. the action to have been determined by all these circumstances, we do
  12697. not the less blame the offender. We do not blame him for his unhappy
  12698. disposition, nor for the circumstances which influenced him, nay, not
  12699. even for his former course of life; for we presuppose that all these
  12700. considerations may be set aside, that the series of preceding conditions
  12701. may be regarded as having never existed, and that the action may
  12702. be considered as completely unconditioned in relation to any state
  12703. preceding, just as if the agent commenced with it an entirely new series
  12704. of effects. Our blame of the offender is grounded upon a law of reason,
  12705. which requires us to regard this faculty as a cause, which could have
  12706. and ought to have otherwise determined the behaviour of the culprit,
  12707. independently of all empirical conditions. This causality of reason we
  12708. do not regard as a co-operating agency, but as complete in itself. It
  12709. matters not whether the sensuous impulses favoured or opposed the
  12710. action of this causality, the offence is estimated according to its
  12711. intelligible character--the offender is decidedly worthy of blame, the
  12712. moment he utters a falsehood. It follows that we regard reason, in
  12713. spite of the empirical conditions of the act, as completely free, and
  12714. therefore, therefore, as in the present case, culpable.
  12715. The above judgement is complete evidence that we are accustomed to think
  12716. that reason is not affected by sensuous conditions, that in it no change
  12717. takes place--although its phenomena, in other words, the mode in
  12718. which it appears in its effects, are subject to change--that in it no
  12719. preceding state determines the following, and, consequently, that
  12720. it does not form a member of the series of sensuous conditions which
  12721. necessitate phenomena according to natural laws. Reason is present and
  12722. the same in all human actions and at all times; but it does not itself
  12723. exist in time, and therefore does not enter upon any state in which it
  12724. did not formerly exist. It is, relatively to new states or conditions,
  12725. determining, but not determinable. Hence we cannot ask: "Why did not
  12726. reason determine itself in a different manner?" The question ought to
  12727. be thus stated: "Why did not reason employ its power of causality
  12728. to determine certain phenomena in a different manner?" But this is
  12729. a question which admits of no answer. For a different intelligible
  12730. character would have exhibited a different empirical character; and,
  12731. when we say that, in spite of the course which his whole former life has
  12732. taken, the offender could have refrained from uttering the falsehood,
  12733. this means merely that the act was subject to the power and
  12734. authority--permissive or prohibitive--of reason. Now, reason is not
  12735. subject in its causality to any conditions of phenomena or of time; and
  12736. a difference in time may produce a difference in the relation of
  12737. phenomena to each other--for these are not things and therefore not
  12738. causes in themselves--but it cannot produce any difference in the
  12739. relation in which the action stands to the faculty of reason.
  12740. Thus, then, in our investigation into free actions and the causal power
  12741. which produced them, we arrive at an intelligible cause, beyond which,
  12742. however, we cannot go; although we can recognize that it is free, that
  12743. is, independent of all sensuous conditions, and that, in this way, it
  12744. may be the sensuously unconditioned condition of phenomena. But for what
  12745. reason the intelligible character generates such and such phenomena
  12746. and exhibits such and such an empirical character under certain
  12747. circumstances, it is beyond the power of our reason to decide. The
  12748. question is as much above the power and the sphere of reason as the
  12749. following would be: "Why does the transcendental object of our external
  12750. sensuous intuition allow of no other form than that of intuition in
  12751. space?" But the problem, which we were called upon to solve, does not
  12752. require us to entertain any such questions. The problem was merely
  12753. this--whether freedom and natural necessity can exist without opposition
  12754. in the same action. To this question we have given a sufficient
  12755. answer; for we have shown that, as the former stands in a relation to a
  12756. different kind of condition from those of the latter, the law of the one
  12757. does not affect the law of the other and that, consequently, both can
  12758. exist together in independence of and without interference with each
  12759. other.
  12760. The reader must be careful to remark that my intention in the above
  12761. remarks has not been to prove the actual existence of freedom, as a
  12762. faculty in which resides the cause of certain sensuous phenomena. For,
  12763. not to mention that such an argument would not have a transcendental
  12764. character, nor have been limited to the discussion of pure
  12765. conceptions--all attempts at inferring from experience what cannot be
  12766. cogitated in accordance with its laws, must ever be unsuccessful. Nay,
  12767. more, I have not even aimed at demonstrating the possibility of freedom;
  12768. for this too would have been a vain endeavour, inasmuch as it is beyond
  12769. the power of the mind to cognize the possibility of a reality or of a
  12770. causal power by the aid of mere a priori conceptions. Freedom has been
  12771. considered in the foregoing remarks only as a transcendental idea, by
  12772. means of which reason aims at originating a series of conditions in
  12773. the world of phenomena with the help of that which is sensuously
  12774. unconditioned, involving itself, however, in an antinomy with the laws
  12775. which itself prescribes for the conduct of the understanding. That this
  12776. antinomy is based upon a mere illusion, and that nature and freedom are
  12777. at least not opposed--this was the only thing in our power to prove, and
  12778. the question which it was our task to solve.
  12779. IV. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the
  12780. Dependence of Phenomenal Existences.
  12781. In the preceding remarks, we considered the changes in the world of
  12782. sense as constituting a dynamical series, in which each member is
  12783. subordinated to another--as its cause. Our present purpose is to avail
  12784. ourselves of this series of states or conditions as a guide to
  12785. an existence which may be the highest condition of all changeable
  12786. phenomena, that is, to a necessary being. Our endeavour to reach,
  12787. not the unconditioned causality, but the unconditioned existence, of
  12788. substance. The series before us is therefore a series of conceptions,
  12789. and not of intuitions (in which the one intuition is the condition of
  12790. the other).
  12791. But it is evident that, as all phenomena are subject to change and
  12792. conditioned in their existence, the series of dependent existences
  12793. cannot embrace an unconditioned member, the existence of which would
  12794. be absolutely necessary. It follows that, if phenomena were things
  12795. in themselves, and--as an immediate consequence from this
  12796. supposition--condition and conditioned belonged to the same series of
  12797. phenomena, the existence of a necessary being, as the condition of the
  12798. existence of sensuous phenomena, would be perfectly impossible.
  12799. An important distinction, however, exists between the dynamical and the
  12800. mathematical regress. The latter is engaged solely with the combination
  12801. of parts into a whole, or with the division of a whole into its parts;
  12802. and therefore are the conditions of its series parts of the series,
  12803. and to be consequently regarded as homogeneous, and for this reason, as
  12804. consisting, without exception, of phenomena. If the former regress, on
  12805. the contrary, the aim of which is not to establish the possibility of
  12806. an unconditioned whole consisting of given parts, or of an unconditioned
  12807. part of a given whole, but to demonstrate the possibility of the
  12808. deduction of a certain state from its cause, or of the contingent
  12809. existence of substance from that which exists necessarily, it is not
  12810. requisite that the condition should form part of an empirical series
  12811. along with the conditioned.
  12812. In the case of the apparent antinomy with which we are at present
  12813. dealing, there exists a way of escape from the difficulty; for it is
  12814. not impossible that both of the contradictory statements may be true
  12815. in different relations. All sensuous phenomena may be contingent, and
  12816. consequently possess only an empirically conditioned existence, and yet
  12817. there may also exist a non-empirical condition of the whole series,
  12818. or, in other words, a necessary being. For this necessary being, as an
  12819. intelligible condition, would not form a member--not even the highest
  12820. member--of the series; the whole world of sense would be left in its
  12821. empirically determined existence uninterfered with and uninfluenced.
  12822. This would also form a ground of distinction between the modes of
  12823. solution employed for the third and fourth antinomies. For, while in the
  12824. consideration of freedom in the former antinomy, the thing itself--the
  12825. cause (substantia phaenomenon)--was regarded as belonging to the series
  12826. of conditions, and only its causality to the intelligible world--we are
  12827. obliged in the present case to cogitate this necessary being as purely
  12828. intelligible and as existing entirely apart from the world of sense
  12829. (as an ens extramundanum); for otherwise it would be subject to the
  12830. phenomenal law of contingency and dependence.
  12831. In relation to the present problem, therefore, the regulative principle
  12832. of reason is that everything in the sensuous world possesses an
  12833. empirically conditioned existence--that no property of the sensuous
  12834. world possesses unconditioned necessity--that we are bound to expect,
  12835. and, so far as is possible, to seek for the empirical condition of every
  12836. member in the series of conditions--and that there is no sufficient
  12837. reason to justify us in deducing any existence from a condition which
  12838. lies out of and beyond the empirical series, or in regarding any
  12839. existence as independent and self-subsistent; although this should not
  12840. prevent us from recognizing the possibility of the whole series being
  12841. based upon a being which is intelligible, and for this reason free from
  12842. all empirical conditions.
  12843. But it has been far from my intention, in these remarks, to prove the
  12844. existence of this unconditioned and necessary being, or even to evidence
  12845. the possibility of a purely intelligible condition of the existence or
  12846. all sensuous phenomena. As bounds were set to reason, to prevent it from
  12847. leaving the guiding thread of empirical conditions and losing itself in
  12848. transcendent theories which are incapable of concrete presentation; so
  12849. it was my purpose, on the other band, to set bounds to the law of the
  12850. purely empirical understanding, and to protest against any attempts
  12851. on its part at deciding on the possibility of things, or declaring the
  12852. existence of the intelligible to be impossible, merely on the ground
  12853. that it is not available for the explanation and exposition of
  12854. phenomena. It has been shown, at the same time, that the contingency
  12855. of all the phenomena of nature and their empirical conditions is quite
  12856. consistent with the arbitrary hypothesis of a necessary, although purely
  12857. intelligible condition, that no real contradiction exists between them
  12858. and that, consequently, both may be true. The existence of such an
  12859. absolutely necessary being may be impossible; but this can never be
  12860. demonstrated from the universal contingency and dependence of sensuous
  12861. phenomena, nor from the principle which forbids us to discontinue the
  12862. series at some member of it, or to seek for its cause in some sphere
  12863. of existence beyond the world of nature. Reason goes its way in the
  12864. empirical world, and follows, too, its peculiar path in the sphere of
  12865. the transcendental.
  12866. The sensuous world contains nothing but phenomena, which are mere
  12867. representations, and always sensuously conditioned; things in themselves
  12868. are not, and cannot be, objects to us. It is not to be wondered at,
  12869. therefore, that we are not justified in leaping from some member of
  12870. an empirical series beyond the world of sense, as if empirical
  12871. representations were things in themselves, existing apart from their
  12872. transcendental ground in the human mind, and the cause of whose
  12873. existence may be sought out of the empirical series. This would
  12874. certainly be the case with contingent things; but it cannot be with mere
  12875. representations of things, the contingency of which is itself merely a
  12876. phenomenon and can relate to no other regress than that which determines
  12877. phenomena, that is, the empirical. But to cogitate an intelligible
  12878. ground of phenomena, as free, moreover, from the contingency of the
  12879. latter, conflicts neither with the unlimited nature of the empirical
  12880. regress, nor with the complete contingency of phenomena. And the
  12881. demonstration of this was the only thing necessary for the solution of
  12882. this apparent antinomy. For if the condition of every conditioned--as
  12883. regards its existence--is sensuous, and for this reason a part of
  12884. the same series, it must be itself conditioned, as was shown in the
  12885. antithesis of the fourth antinomy. The embarrassments into which a
  12886. reason, which postulates the unconditioned, necessarily falls, must,
  12887. therefore, continue to exist; or the unconditioned must be placed in the
  12888. sphere of the intelligible. In this way, its necessity does not require,
  12889. nor does it even permit, the presence of an empirical condition: and it
  12890. is, consequently, unconditionally necessary.
  12891. The empirical employment of reason is not affected by the assumption
  12892. of a purely intelligible being; it continues its operations on the
  12893. principle of the contingency of all phenomena, proceeding from empirical
  12894. conditions to still higher and higher conditions, themselves empirical.
  12895. Just as little does this regulative principle exclude the assumption
  12896. of an intelligible cause, when the question regards merely the pure
  12897. employment of reason--in relation to ends or aims. For, in this case, an
  12898. intelligible cause signifies merely the transcendental and to us unknown
  12899. ground of the possibility of sensuous phenomena, and its existence,
  12900. necessary and independent of all sensuous conditions, is not
  12901. inconsistent with the contingency of phenomena, or with the unlimited
  12902. possibility of regress which exists in the series of empirical
  12903. conditions.
  12904. Concluding Remarks on the Antinomy of Pure Reason.
  12905. So long as the object of our rational conceptions is the
  12906. totality of conditions in the world of phenomena, and the
  12907. satisfaction, from this source, of the requirements of reason,
  12908. so long are our ideas transcendental and cosmological.
  12909. But when we set the unconditioned--which is the aim of
  12910. all our inquiries--in a sphere which lies out of the
  12911. world of sense and possible experience, our ideas become transcendent.
  12912. They are then not merely serviceable towards the completion of the
  12913. exercise of reason (which remains an idea, never executed, but always
  12914. to be pursued); they detach themselves completely from experience and
  12915. construct for themselves objects, the material of which has not been
  12916. presented by experience, and the objective reality of which is not based
  12917. upon the completion of the empirical series, but upon pure a priori
  12918. conceptions. The intelligible object of these transcendent ideas may
  12919. be conceded, as a transcendental object. But we cannot cogitate it as
  12920. a thing determinable by certain distinct predicates relating to its
  12921. internal nature, for it has no connection with empirical conceptions;
  12922. nor are we justified in affirming the existence of any such object.
  12923. It is, consequently, a mere product of the mind alone. Of all the
  12924. cosmological ideas, however, it is that occasioning the fourth antinomy
  12925. which compels us to venture upon this step. For the existence of
  12926. phenomena, always conditioned and never self-subsistent, requires us
  12927. to look for an object different from phenomena--an intelligible object,
  12928. with which all contingency must cease. But, as we have allowed ourselves
  12929. to assume the existence of a self-subsistent reality out of the field
  12930. of experience, and are therefore obliged to regard phenomena as merely a
  12931. contingent mode of representing intelligible objects employed by beings
  12932. which are themselves intelligences--no other course remains for us than
  12933. to follow analogy and employ the same mode in forming some conception
  12934. of intelligible things, of which we have not the least knowledge, which
  12935. nature taught us to use in the formation of empirical conceptions.
  12936. Experience made us acquainted with the contingent. But we are at present
  12937. engaged in the discussion of things which are not objects of experience;
  12938. and must, therefore, deduce our knowledge of them from that which is
  12939. necessary absolutely and in itself, that is, from pure conceptions.
  12940. Hence the first step which we take out of the world of sense obliges
  12941. us to begin our system of new cognition with the investigation of
  12942. a necessary being, and to deduce from our conceptions of it all our
  12943. conceptions of intelligible things. This we propose to attempt in the
  12944. following chapter.
  12945. CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason.
  12946. SECTION I. Of the Ideal in General.
  12947. We have seen that pure conceptions do not present objects to the mind,
  12948. except under sensuous conditions; because the conditions of objective
  12949. reality do not exist in these conceptions, which contain, in fact,
  12950. nothing but the mere form of thought. They may, however, when applied to
  12951. phenomena, be presented in concreto; for it is phenomena that present to
  12952. them the materials for the formation of empirical conceptions, which
  12953. are nothing more than concrete forms of the conceptions of the
  12954. understanding. But ideas are still further removed from objective
  12955. reality than categories; for no phenomenon can ever present them to the
  12956. human mind in concreto. They contain a certain perfection, attainable
  12957. by no possible empirical cognition; and they give to reason a systematic
  12958. unity, to which the unity of experience attempts to approximate, but can
  12959. never completely attain.
  12960. But still further removed than the idea from objective reality is the
  12961. Ideal, by which term I understand the idea, not in concreto, but in
  12962. individuo--as an individual thing, determinable or determined by the
  12963. idea alone. The idea of humanity in its complete perfection supposes not
  12964. only the advancement of all the powers and faculties, which constitute
  12965. our conception of human nature, to a complete attainment of their
  12966. final aims, but also everything which is requisite for the complete
  12967. determination of the idea; for of all contradictory predicates, only
  12968. one can conform with the idea of the perfect man. What I have termed
  12969. an ideal was in Plato's philosophy an idea of the divine mind--an
  12970. individual object present to its pure intuition, the most perfect of
  12971. every kind of possible beings, and the archetype of all phenomenal
  12972. existences.
  12973. Without rising to these speculative heights, we are bound to confess
  12974. that human reason contains not only ideas, but ideals, which possess,
  12975. not, like those of Plato, creative, but certainly practical power--as
  12976. regulative principles, and form the basis of the perfectibility of
  12977. certain actions. Moral conceptions are not perfectly pure conceptions of
  12978. reason, because an empirical element--of pleasure or pain--lies at the
  12979. foundation of them. In relation, however, to the principle, whereby
  12980. reason sets bounds to a freedom which is in itself without law, and
  12981. consequently when we attend merely to their form, they may be considered
  12982. as pure conceptions of reason. Virtue and wisdom in their perfect purity
  12983. are ideas. But the wise man of the Stoics is an ideal, that is to say, a
  12984. human being existing only in thought and in complete conformity with the
  12985. idea of wisdom. As the idea provides a rule, so the ideal serves as an
  12986. archetype for the perfect and complete determination of the copy. Thus
  12987. the conduct of this wise and divine man serves us as a standard of
  12988. action, with which we may compare and judge ourselves, which may help
  12989. us to reform ourselves, although the perfection it demands can never be
  12990. attained by us. Although we cannot concede objective reality to these
  12991. ideals, they are not to be considered as chimeras; on the contrary,
  12992. they provide reason with a standard, which enables it to estimate, by
  12993. comparison, the degree of incompleteness in the objects presented to
  12994. it. But to aim at realizing the ideal in an example in the world of
  12995. experience--to describe, for instance, the character of the perfectly
  12996. wise man in a romance--is impracticable. Nay more, there is something
  12997. absurd in the attempt; and the result must be little edifying, as
  12998. the natural limitations, which are continually breaking in upon the
  12999. perfection and completeness of the idea, destroy the illusion in the
  13000. story and throw an air of suspicion even on what is good in the idea,
  13001. which hence appears fictitious and unreal.
  13002. Such is the constitution of the ideal of reason, which is always based
  13003. upon determinate conceptions, and serves as a rule and a model for
  13004. limitation or of criticism. Very different is the nature of the ideals
  13005. of the imagination. Of these it is impossible to present an intelligible
  13006. conception; they are a kind of monogram, drawn according to no
  13007. determinate rule, and forming rather a vague picture--the production of
  13008. many diverse experiences--than a determinate image. Such are the ideals
  13009. which painters and physiognomists profess to have in their minds, and
  13010. which can serve neither as a model for production nor as a standard for
  13011. appreciation. They may be termed, though improperly, sensuous ideals, as
  13012. they are declared to be models of certain possible empirical intuitions.
  13013. They cannot, however, furnish rules or standards for explanation or
  13014. examination.
  13015. In its ideals, reason aims at complete and perfect determination
  13016. according to a priori rules; and hence it cogitates an object, which
  13017. must be completely determinable in conformity with principles, although
  13018. all empirical conditions are absent, and the conception of the object is
  13019. on this account transcendent.
  13020. SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale).
  13021. Every conception is, in relation to that which is not contained in
  13022. it, undetermined and subject to the principle of determinability. This
  13023. principle is that, of every two contradictorily opposed predicates, only
  13024. one can belong to a conception. It is a purely logical principle, itself
  13025. based upon the principle of contradiction; inasmuch as it makes complete
  13026. abstraction of the content and attends merely to the logical form of the
  13027. cognition.
  13028. But again, everything, as regards its possibility, is also subject to
  13029. the principle of complete determination, according to which one of all
  13030. the possible contradictory predicates of things must belong to it.
  13031. This principle is not based merely upon that of contradiction; for,
  13032. in addition to the relation between two contradictory predicates,
  13033. it regards everything as standing in a relation to the sum of
  13034. possibilities, as the sum total of all predicates of things, and, while
  13035. presupposing this sum as an a priori condition, presents to the mind
  13036. everything as receiving the possibility of its individual existence from
  13037. the relation it bears to, and the share it possesses in, the aforesaid
  13038. sum of possibilities.* The principle of complete determination relates
  13039. the content and not to the logical form. It is the principle of the
  13040. synthesis of all the predicates which are required to constitute the
  13041. complete conception of a thing, and not a mere principle analytical
  13042. representation, which enounces that one of two contradictory predicates
  13043. must belong to a conception. It contains, moreover, a transcendental
  13044. presupposition--that, namely, of the material for all possibility, which
  13045. must contain a priori the data for this or that particular possibility.
  13046. [*Footnote: Thus this principle declares everything to possess a
  13047. relation to a common correlate--the sum-total of possibility, which, if
  13048. discovered to exist in the idea of one individual thing, would establish
  13049. the affinity of all possible things, from the identity of the ground of
  13050. their complete determination. The determinability of every conception
  13051. is subordinate to the universality (Allgemeinheit, universalitas) of
  13052. the principle of excluded middle; the determination of a thing to the
  13053. totality (Allheit, universitas) of all possible predicates.]
  13054. The proposition, everything which exists is completely determined, means
  13055. not only that one of every pair of given contradictory attributes, but
  13056. that one of all possible attributes, is always predicable of the thing;
  13057. in it the predicates are not merely compared logically with each other,
  13058. but the thing itself is transcendentally compared with the sum-total of
  13059. all possible predicates. The proposition is equivalent to saying: "To
  13060. attain to a complete knowledge of a thing, it is necessary to possess a
  13061. knowledge of everything that is possible, and to determine it thereby in
  13062. a positive or negative manner." The conception of complete determination
  13063. is consequently a conception which cannot be presented in its totality
  13064. in concreto, and is therefore based upon an idea, which has its seat in
  13065. the reason--the faculty which prescribes to the understanding the laws
  13066. of its harmonious and perfect exercise.
  13067. Now, although this idea of the sum-total of all possibility, in so far
  13068. as it forms the condition of the complete determination of everything,
  13069. is itself undetermined in relation to the predicates which may
  13070. constitute this sum-total, and we cogitate in it merely the sum-total of
  13071. all possible predicates--we nevertheless find, upon closer examination,
  13072. that this idea, as a primitive conception of the mind, excludes a
  13073. large number of predicates--those deduced and those irreconcilable with
  13074. others, and that it is evolved as a conception completely determined a
  13075. priori. Thus it becomes the conception of an individual object, which
  13076. is completely determined by and through the mere idea, and must
  13077. consequently be termed an ideal of pure reason.
  13078. When we consider all possible predicates, not merely logically, but
  13079. transcendentally, that is to say, with reference to the content which
  13080. may be cogitated as existing in them a priori, we shall find that
  13081. some indicate a being, others merely a non-being. The logical negation
  13082. expressed in the word not does not properly belong to a conception, but
  13083. only to the relation of one conception to another in a judgement, and is
  13084. consequently quite insufficient to present to the mind the content of a
  13085. conception. The expression not mortal does not indicate that a non-being
  13086. is cogitated in the object; it does not concern the content at all. A
  13087. transcendental negation, on the contrary, indicates non-being in itself,
  13088. and is opposed to transcendental affirmation, the conception of which
  13089. of itself expresses a being. Hence this affirmation indicates a reality,
  13090. because in and through it objects are considered to be something--to be
  13091. things; while the opposite negation, on the other band, indicates a
  13092. mere want, or privation, or absence, and, where such negations alone
  13093. are attached to a representation, the non-existence of anything
  13094. corresponding to the representation.
  13095. Now a negation cannot be cogitated as determined, without cogitating at
  13096. the same time the opposite affirmation. The man born blind has not the
  13097. least notion of darkness, because he has none of light; the vagabond
  13098. knows nothing of poverty, because he has never known what it is to be in
  13099. comfort;* the ignorant man has no conception of his ignorance, because
  13100. he has no conception of knowledge. All conceptions of negatives are
  13101. accordingly derived or deduced conceptions; and realities contain the
  13102. data, and, so to speak, the material or transcendental content of the
  13103. possibility and complete determination of all things.
  13104. [*Footnote: The investigations and calculations of astronomers have
  13105. taught us much that is wonderful; but the most important lesson we have
  13106. received from them is the discovery of the abyss of our ignorance in
  13107. relation to the universe--an ignorance the magnitude of which reason,
  13108. without the information thus derived, could never have conceived.
  13109. This discovery of our deficiencies must produce a great change in the
  13110. determination of the aims of human reason.]
  13111. If, therefore, a transcendental substratum lies at the foundation of the
  13112. complete determination of things--a substratum which is to form the fund
  13113. from which all possible predicates of things are to be supplied, this
  13114. substratum cannot be anything else than the idea of a sum-total of
  13115. reality (omnitudo realitatis). In this view, negations are nothing but
  13116. limitations--a term which could not, with propriety, be applied to
  13117. them, if the unlimited (the all) did not form the true basis of our
  13118. conception.
  13119. This conception of a sum-total of reality is the conception of a thing
  13120. in itself, regarded as completely determined; and the conception of an
  13121. ens realissimum is the conception of an individual being, inasmuch as
  13122. it is determined by that predicate of all possible contradictory
  13123. predicates, which indicates and belongs to being. It is, therefore, a
  13124. transcendental ideal which forms the basis of the complete determination
  13125. of everything that exists, and is the highest material condition of
  13126. its possibility--a condition on which must rest the cogitation of all
  13127. objects with respect to their content. Nay, more, this ideal is the only
  13128. proper ideal of which the human mind is capable; because in this case
  13129. alone a general conception of a thing is completely determined by and
  13130. through itself, and cognized as the representation of an individuum.
  13131. The logical determination of a conception is based upon a disjunctive
  13132. syllogism, the major of which contains the logical division of the
  13133. extent of a general conception, the minor limits this extent to a
  13134. certain part, while the conclusion determines the conception by this
  13135. part. The general conception of a reality cannot be divided a priori,
  13136. because, without the aid of experience, we cannot know any determinate
  13137. kinds of reality, standing under the former as the genus. The
  13138. transcendental principle of the complete determination of all things is
  13139. therefore merely the representation of the sum-total of all reality; it
  13140. is not a conception which is the genus of all predicates under
  13141. itself, but one which comprehends them all within itself. The complete
  13142. determination of a thing is consequently based upon the limitation of
  13143. this total of reality, so much being predicated of the thing, while all
  13144. that remains over is excluded--a procedure which is in exact agreement
  13145. with that of the disjunctive syllogism and the determination of the
  13146. objects in the conclusion by one of the members of the division.
  13147. It follows that reason, in laying the transcendental ideal at the
  13148. foundation of its determination of all possible things, takes a course
  13149. in exact analogy with that which it pursues in disjunctive syllogisms--a
  13150. proposition which formed the basis of the systematic division of all
  13151. transcendental ideas, according to which they are produced in complete
  13152. parallelism with the three modes of syllogistic reasoning employed by
  13153. the human mind.
  13154. It is self-evident that reason, in cogitating the necessary complete
  13155. determination of things, does not presuppose the existence of a being
  13156. corresponding to its ideal, but merely the idea of the ideal--for
  13157. the purpose of deducing from the unconditional totality of complete
  13158. determination, The ideal is therefore the prototype of all things,
  13159. which, as defective copies (ectypa), receive from it the material of
  13160. their possibility, and approximate to it more or less, though it is
  13161. impossible that they can ever attain to its perfection.
  13162. The possibility of things must therefore be regarded as derived--except
  13163. that of the thing which contains in itself all reality, which must be
  13164. considered to be primitive and original. For all negations--and they
  13165. are the only predicates by means of which all other things can be
  13166. distinguished from the ens realissimum--are mere limitations of a
  13167. greater and a higher--nay, the highest reality; and they consequently
  13168. presuppose this reality, and are, as regards their content, derived from
  13169. it. The manifold nature of things is only an infinitely various mode of
  13170. limiting the conception of the highest reality, which is their common
  13171. substratum; just as all figures are possible only as different modes of
  13172. limiting infinite space. The object of the ideal of reason--an object
  13173. existing only in reason itself--is also termed the primal being (ens
  13174. originarium); as having no existence superior to him, the supreme being
  13175. (ens summum); and as being the condition of all other beings, which rank
  13176. under it, the being of all beings (ens entium). But none of these terms
  13177. indicate the objective relation of an actually existing object to
  13178. other things, but merely that of an idea to conceptions; and all our
  13179. investigations into this subject still leave us in perfect uncertainty
  13180. with regard to the existence of this being.
  13181. A primal being cannot be said to consist of many other beings with an
  13182. existence which is derivative, for the latter presuppose the former, and
  13183. therefore cannot be constitutive parts of it. It follows that the ideal
  13184. of the primal being must be cogitated as simple.
  13185. The deduction of the possibility of all other things from this primal
  13186. being cannot, strictly speaking, be considered as a limitation, or as a
  13187. kind of division of its reality; for this would be regarding the primal
  13188. being as a mere aggregate--which has been shown to be impossible,
  13189. although it was so represented in our first rough sketch. The highest
  13190. reality must be regarded rather as the ground than as the sum-total
  13191. of the possibility of all things, and the manifold nature of things be
  13192. based, not upon the limitation of the primal being itself, but upon the
  13193. complete series of effects which flow from it. And thus all our powers
  13194. of sense, as well as all phenomenal reality, phenomenal reality, may be
  13195. with propriety regarded as belonging to this series of effects,
  13196. while they could not have formed parts of the idea, considered as an
  13197. aggregate. Pursuing this track, and hypostatizing this idea, we shall
  13198. find ourselves authorized to determine our notion of the Supreme Being
  13199. by means of the mere conception of a highest reality, as one, simple,
  13200. all-sufficient, eternal, and so on--in one word, to determine it in its
  13201. unconditioned completeness by the aid of every possible predicate.
  13202. The conception of such a being is the conception of God in its
  13203. transcendental sense, and thus the ideal of pure reason is the
  13204. object-matter of a transcendental theology.
  13205. But, by such an employment of the transcendental idea, we should be over
  13206. stepping the limits of its validity and purpose. For reason placed
  13207. it, as the conception of all reality, at the basis of the complete
  13208. determination of things, without requiring that this conception be
  13209. regarded as the conception of an objective existence. Such an existence
  13210. would be purely fictitious, and the hypostatizing of the content of
  13211. the idea into an ideal, as an individual being, is a step perfectly
  13212. unauthorized. Nay, more, we are not even called upon to assume the
  13213. possibility of such an hypothesis, as none of the deductions drawn
  13214. from such an ideal would affect the complete determination of things in
  13215. general--for the sake of which alone is the idea necessary.
  13216. It is not sufficient to circumscribe the procedure and the dialectic
  13217. of reason; we must also endeavour to discover the sources of this
  13218. dialectic, that we may have it in our power to give a rational
  13219. explanation of this illusion, as a phenomenon of the human mind. For
  13220. the ideal, of which we are at present speaking, is based, not upon an
  13221. arbitrary, but upon a natural, idea. The question hence arises: How
  13222. happens it that reason regards the possibility of all things as deduced
  13223. from a single possibility, that, to wit, of the highest reality, and
  13224. presupposes this as existing in an individual and primal being?
  13225. The answer is ready; it is at once presented by the procedure of
  13226. transcendental analytic. The possibility of sensuous objects is a
  13227. relation of these objects to thought, in which something (the empirical
  13228. form) may be cogitated a priori; while that which constitutes the
  13229. matter--the reality of the phenomenon (that element which corresponds to
  13230. sensation)--must be given from without, as otherwise it could not even
  13231. be cogitated by, nor could its possibility be presentable to the mind.
  13232. Now, a sensuous object is completely determined, when it has been
  13233. compared with all phenomenal predicates, and represented by means of
  13234. these either positively or negatively. But, as that which constitutes
  13235. the thing itself--the real in a phenomenon, must be given, and that, in
  13236. which the real of all phenomena is given, is experience, one, sole, and
  13237. all-embracing--the material of the possibility of all sensuous objects
  13238. must be presupposed as given in a whole, and it is upon the limitation
  13239. of this whole that the possibility of all empirical objects, their
  13240. distinction from each other and their complete determination, are based.
  13241. Now, no other objects are presented to us besides sensuous objects, and
  13242. these can be given only in connection with a possible experience; it
  13243. follows that a thing is not an object to us, unless it presupposes
  13244. the whole or sum-total of empirical reality as the condition of
  13245. its possibility. Now, a natural illusion leads us to consider this
  13246. principle, which is valid only of sensuous objects, as valid with regard
  13247. to things in general. And thus we are induced to hold the empirical
  13248. principle of our conceptions of the possibility of things, as phenomena,
  13249. by leaving out this limitative condition, to be a transcendental
  13250. principle of the possibility of things in general.
  13251. We proceed afterwards to hypostatize this idea of the sum-total of all
  13252. reality, by changing the distributive unity of the empirical exercise
  13253. of the understanding into the collective unity of an empirical whole--a
  13254. dialectical illusion, and by cogitating this whole or sum of experience
  13255. as an individual thing, containing in itself all empirical reality.
  13256. This individual thing or being is then, by means of the above-mentioned
  13257. transcendental subreption, substituted for our notion of a thing which
  13258. stands at the head of the possibility of all things, the real conditions
  13259. of whose complete determination it presents.*
  13260. [*Footnote: This ideal of the ens realissimum--although merely a
  13261. mental representation--is first objectivized, that is, has an objective
  13262. existence attributed to it, then hypostatized, and finally, by the
  13263. natural progress of reason to the completion of unity, personified, as
  13264. we shall show presently. For the regulative unity of experience is not
  13265. based upon phenomena themselves, but upon the connection of the variety
  13266. of phenomena by the understanding in a consciousness, and thus the unity
  13267. of the supreme reality and the complete determinability of all things,
  13268. seem to reside in a supreme understanding, and, consequently, in a
  13269. conscious intelligence.]
  13270. SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in
  13271. Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being.
  13272. Notwithstanding the pressing necessity which reason feels, to form some
  13273. presupposition that shall serve the understanding as a proper basis
  13274. for the complete determination of its conceptions, the idealistic and
  13275. factitious nature of such a presupposition is too evident to allow
  13276. reason for a moment to persuade itself into a belief of the objective
  13277. existence of a mere creation of its own thought. But there are other
  13278. considerations which compel reason to seek out some resting place in the
  13279. regress from the conditioned to the unconditioned, which is not given
  13280. as an actual existence from the mere conception of it, although it
  13281. alone can give completeness to the series of conditions. And this is
  13282. the natural course of every human reason, even of the most uneducated,
  13283. although the path at first entered it does not always continue to
  13284. follow. It does not begin from conceptions, but from common experience,
  13285. and requires a basis in actual existence. But this basis is insecure,
  13286. unless it rests upon the immovable rock of the absolutely necessary. And
  13287. this foundation is itself unworthy of trust, if it leave under and above
  13288. it empty space, if it do not fill all, and leave no room for a why or a
  13289. wherefore, if it be not, in one word, infinite in its reality.
  13290. If we admit the existence of some one thing, whatever it may be, we must
  13291. also admit that there is something which exists necessarily. For what is
  13292. contingent exists only under the condition of some other thing, which
  13293. is its cause; and from this we must go on to conclude the existence of a
  13294. cause which is not contingent, and which consequently exists necessarily
  13295. and unconditionally. Such is the argument by which reason justifies its
  13296. advances towards a primal being.
  13297. Now reason looks round for the conception of a being that may be
  13298. admitted, without inconsistency, to be worthy of the attribute of
  13299. absolute necessity, not for the purpose of inferring a priori, from
  13300. the conception of such a being, its objective existence (for if reason
  13301. allowed itself to take this course, it would not require a basis in
  13302. given and actual existence, but merely the support of pure conceptions),
  13303. but for the purpose of discovering, among all our conceptions of
  13304. possible things, that conception which possesses no element inconsistent
  13305. with the idea of absolute necessity. For that there must be some
  13306. absolutely necessary existence, it regards as a truth already
  13307. established. Now, if it can remove every existence incapable of
  13308. supporting the attribute of absolute necessity, excepting one--this
  13309. must be the absolutely necessary being, whether its necessity is
  13310. comprehensible by us, that is, deducible from the conception of it
  13311. alone, or not.
  13312. Now that, the conception of which contains a therefore to every
  13313. wherefore, which is not defective in any respect whatever, which is
  13314. all-sufficient as a condition, seems to be the being of which we can
  13315. justly predicate absolute necessity--for this reason, that, possessing
  13316. the conditions of all that is possible, it does not and cannot itself
  13317. require any condition. And thus it satisfies, in one respect at least,
  13318. the requirements of the conception of absolute necessity. In this
  13319. view, it is superior to all other conceptions, which, as deficient and
  13320. incomplete, do not possess the characteristic of independence of all
  13321. higher conditions. It is true that we cannot infer from this that what
  13322. does not contain in itself the supreme and complete condition--the
  13323. condition of all other things--must possess only a conditioned
  13324. existence; but as little can we assert the contrary, for this supposed
  13325. being does not possess the only characteristic which can enable reason
  13326. to cognize by means of an a priori conception the unconditioned and
  13327. necessary nature of its existence.
  13328. The conception of an ens realissimum is that which best agrees with
  13329. the conception of an unconditioned and necessary being. The former
  13330. conception does not satisfy all the requirements of the latter; but
  13331. we have no choice, we are obliged to adhere to it, for we find that we
  13332. cannot do without the existence of a necessary being; and even although
  13333. we admit it, we find it out of our power to discover in the whole sphere
  13334. of possibility any being that can advance well-grounded claims to such a
  13335. distinction.
  13336. The following is, therefore, the natural course of human reason. It
  13337. begins by persuading itself of the existence of some necessary being. In
  13338. this being it recognizes the characteristics of unconditioned existence.
  13339. It then seeks the conception of that which is independent of all
  13340. conditions, and finds it in that which is itself the sufficient
  13341. condition of all other things--in other words, in that which contains
  13342. all reality. But the unlimited all is an absolute unity, and is
  13343. conceived by the mind as a being one and supreme; and thus reason
  13344. concludes that the Supreme Being, as the primal basis of all things,
  13345. possesses an existence which is absolutely necessary.
  13346. This conception must be regarded as in some degree satisfactory, if we
  13347. admit the existence of a necessary being, and consider that there exists
  13348. a necessity for a definite and final answer to these questions. In such
  13349. a case, we cannot make a better choice, or rather we have no choice at
  13350. all, but feel ourselves obliged to declare in favour of the absolute
  13351. unity of complete reality, as the highest source of the possibility
  13352. of things. But if there exists no motive for coming to a definite
  13353. conclusion, and we may leave the question unanswered till we have fully
  13354. weighed both sides--in other words, when we are merely called upon to
  13355. decide how much we happen to know about the question, and how much we
  13356. merely flatter ourselves that we know--the above conclusion does not
  13357. appear to be so great advantage, but, on the contrary, seems defective
  13358. in the grounds upon which it is supported.
  13359. For, admitting the truth of all that has been said, that, namely, the
  13360. inference from a given existence (my own, for example) to the existence
  13361. of an unconditioned and necessary being is valid and unassailable;
  13362. that, in the second place, we must consider a being which contains all
  13363. reality, and consequently all the conditions of other things, to
  13364. be absolutely unconditioned; and admitting too, that we have thus
  13365. discovered the conception of a thing to which may be attributed, without
  13366. inconsistency, absolute necessity--it does not follow from all this that
  13367. the conception of a limited being, in which the supreme reality does not
  13368. reside, is therefore incompatible with the idea of absolute necessity.
  13369. For, although I do not discover the element of the unconditioned in the
  13370. conception of such a being--an element which is manifestly existent in
  13371. the sum-total of all conditions--I am not entitled to conclude that its
  13372. existence is therefore conditioned; just as I am not entitled to affirm,
  13373. in a hypothetical syllogism, that where a certain condition does not
  13374. exist (in the present, completeness, as far as pure conceptions are
  13375. concerned), the conditioned does not exist either. On the contrary,
  13376. we are free to consider all limited beings as likewise unconditionally
  13377. necessary, although we are unable to infer this from the general
  13378. conception which we have of them. Thus conducted, this argument is
  13379. incapable of giving us the least notion of the properties of a necessary
  13380. being, and must be in every respect without result.
  13381. This argument continues, however, to possess a weight and an authority,
  13382. which, in spite of its objective insufficiency, it has never been
  13383. divested of. For, granting that certain responsibilities lie upon us,
  13384. which, as based on the ideas of reason, deserve to be respected and
  13385. submitted to, although they are incapable of a real or practical
  13386. application to our nature, or, in other words, would be responsibilities
  13387. without motives, except upon the supposition of a Supreme Being to give
  13388. effect and influence to the practical laws: in such a case we should be
  13389. bound to obey our conceptions, which, although objectively insufficient,
  13390. do, according to the standard of reason, preponderate over and are
  13391. superior to any claims that may be advanced from any other quarter.
  13392. The equilibrium of doubt would in this case be destroyed by a practical
  13393. addition; indeed, Reason would be compelled to condemn herself, if she
  13394. refused to comply with the demands of the judgement, no superior to
  13395. which we know--however defective her understanding of the grounds of
  13396. these demands might be.
  13397. This argument, although in fact transcendental, inasmuch as it rests
  13398. upon the intrinsic insufficiency of the contingent, is so simple and
  13399. natural, that the commonest understanding can appreciate its value.
  13400. We see things around us change, arise, and pass away; they, or their
  13401. condition, must therefore have a cause. The same demand must again be
  13402. made of the cause itself--as a datum of experience. Now it is natural
  13403. that we should place the highest causality just where we place supreme
  13404. causality, in that being, which contains the conditions of all possible
  13405. effects, and the conception of which is so simple as that of an
  13406. all-embracing reality. This highest cause, then, we regard as absolutely
  13407. necessary, because we find it absolutely necessary to rise to it, and
  13408. do not discover any reason for proceeding beyond it. Thus, among all
  13409. nations, through the darkest polytheism glimmer some faint sparks of
  13410. monotheism, to which these idolaters have been led, not from reflection
  13411. and profound thought, but by the study and natural progress of the
  13412. common understanding.
  13413. There are only three modes of proving the existence of a Deity, on the
  13414. grounds of speculative reason.
  13415. All the paths conducting to this end begin either from determinate
  13416. experience and the peculiar constitution of the world of sense, and
  13417. rise, according to the laws of causality, from it to the highest
  13418. cause existing apart from the world--or from a purely indeterminate
  13419. experience, that is, some empirical existence--or abstraction is made of
  13420. all experience, and the existence of a supreme cause is concluded from a
  13421. priori conceptions alone. The first is the physico-theological argument,
  13422. the second the cosmological, the third the ontological. More there are
  13423. not, and more there cannot be.
  13424. I shall show it is as unsuccessful on the one path--the empirical--as on
  13425. the other--the transcendental, and that it stretches its wings in vain,
  13426. to soar beyond the world of sense by the mere might of speculative
  13427. thought. As regards the order in which we must discuss those arguments,
  13428. it will be exactly the reverse of that in which reason, in the progress
  13429. of its development, attains to them--the order in which they are
  13430. placed above. For it will be made manifest to the reader that, although
  13431. experience presents the occasion and the starting-point, it is the
  13432. transcendental idea of reason which guides it in its pilgrimage and
  13433. is the goal of all its struggles. I shall therefore begin with an
  13434. examination of the transcendental argument, and afterwards inquire what
  13435. additional strength has accrued to this mode of proof from the addition
  13436. of the empirical element.
  13437. SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the
  13438. Existence of God.
  13439. It is evident from what has been said that the conception of an
  13440. absolutely necessary being is a mere idea, the objective reality of
  13441. which is far from being established by the mere fact that it is a
  13442. need of reason. On the contrary, this idea serves merely to indicate a
  13443. certain unattainable perfection, and rather limits the operations
  13444. than, by the presentation of new objects, extends the sphere of the
  13445. understanding. But a strange anomaly meets us at the very threshold;
  13446. for the inference from a given existence in general to an absolutely
  13447. necessary existence seems to be correct and unavoidable, while the
  13448. conditions of the understanding refuse to aid us in forming any
  13449. conception of such a being.
  13450. Philosophers have always talked of an absolutely necessary being,
  13451. and have nevertheless declined to take the trouble of conceiving
  13452. whether--and how--a being of this nature is even cogitable, not to
  13453. mention that its existence is actually demonstrable. A verbal definition
  13454. of the conception is certainly easy enough: it is something the
  13455. non-existence of which is impossible. But does this definition throw
  13456. any light upon the conditions which render it impossible to cogitate the
  13457. non-existence of a thing--conditions which we wish to ascertain, that we
  13458. may discover whether we think anything in the conception of such a
  13459. being or not? For the mere fact that I throw away, by means of the word
  13460. unconditioned, all the conditions which the understanding habitually
  13461. requires in order to regard anything as necessary, is very far from
  13462. making clear whether by means of the conception of the unconditionally
  13463. necessary I think of something, or really of nothing at all.
  13464. Nay, more, this chance-conception, now become so current, many have
  13465. endeavoured to explain by examples which seemed to render any inquiries
  13466. regarding its intelligibility quite needless. Every geometrical
  13467. proposition--a triangle has three angles--it was said, is absolutely
  13468. necessary; and thus people talked of an object which lay out of the
  13469. sphere of our understanding as if it were perfectly plain what the
  13470. conception of such a being meant.
  13471. All the examples adduced have been drawn, without exception, from
  13472. judgements, and not from things. But the unconditioned necessity of
  13473. a judgement does not form the absolute necessity of a thing. On the
  13474. contrary, the absolute necessity of a judgement is only a conditioned
  13475. necessity of a thing, or of the predicate in a judgement. The
  13476. proposition above-mentioned does not enounce that three angles
  13477. necessarily exist, but, upon condition that a triangle exists, three
  13478. angles must necessarily exist--in it. And thus this logical necessity
  13479. has been the source of the greatest delusions. Having formed an a
  13480. priori conception of a thing, the content of which was made to embrace
  13481. existence, we believed ourselves safe in concluding that, because
  13482. existence belongs necessarily to the object of the conception (that is,
  13483. under the condition of my positing this thing as given), the existence
  13484. of the thing is also posited necessarily, and that it is therefore
  13485. absolutely necessary--merely because its existence has been cogitated in
  13486. the conception.
  13487. If, in an identical judgement, I annihilate the predicate in thought,
  13488. and retain the subject, a contradiction is the result; and hence I say,
  13489. the former belongs necessarily to the latter. But if I suppress both
  13490. subject and predicate in thought, no contradiction arises; for there is
  13491. nothing at all, and therefore no means of forming a contradiction. To
  13492. suppose the existence of a triangle and not that of its three angles,
  13493. is self-contradictory; but to suppose the non-existence of both triangle
  13494. and angles is perfectly admissible. And so is it with the conception of
  13495. an absolutely necessary being. Annihilate its existence in thought, and
  13496. you annihilate the thing itself with all its predicates; how then can
  13497. there be any room for contradiction? Externally, there is nothing
  13498. to give rise to a contradiction, for a thing cannot be necessary
  13499. externally; nor internally, for, by the annihilation or suppression of
  13500. the thing itself, its internal properties are also annihilated. God is
  13501. omnipotent--that is a necessary judgement. His omnipotence cannot be
  13502. denied, if the existence of a Deity is posited--the existence, that is,
  13503. of an infinite being, the two conceptions being identical. But when you
  13504. say, God does not exist, neither omnipotence nor any other predicate
  13505. is affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject, and in this
  13506. judgement there cannot exist the least self-contradiction.
  13507. You have thus seen that when the predicate of a judgement is annihilated
  13508. in thought along with the subject, no internal contradiction can arise,
  13509. be the predicate what it may. There is no possibility of evading the
  13510. conclusion--you find yourselves compelled to declare: There are certain
  13511. subjects which cannot be annihilated in thought. But this is
  13512. nothing more than saying: There exist subjects which are absolutely
  13513. necessary--the very hypothesis which you are called upon to establish.
  13514. For I find myself unable to form the slightest conception of a thing
  13515. which when annihilated in thought with all its predicates, leaves
  13516. behind a contradiction; and contradiction is the only criterion of
  13517. impossibility in the sphere of pure a priori conceptions.
  13518. Against these general considerations, the justice of which no one can
  13519. dispute, one argument is adduced, which is regarded as furnishing a
  13520. satisfactory demonstration from the fact. It is affirmed that there is
  13521. one and only one conception, in which the non-being or annihilation of
  13522. the object is self-contradictory, and this is the conception of an ens
  13523. realissimum. It possesses, you say, all reality, and you feel yourselves
  13524. justified in admitting the possibility of such a being. (This I am
  13525. willing to grant for the present, although the existence of a conception
  13526. which is not self-contradictory is far from being sufficient to prove
  13527. the possibility of an object.)* Now the notion of all reality embraces
  13528. in it that of existence; the notion of existence lies, therefore, in
  13529. the conception of this possible thing. If this thing is annihilated
  13530. in thought, the internal possibility of the thing is also annihilated,
  13531. which is self-contradictory.
  13532. [*Footnote: A conception is always possible, if it is not
  13533. self-contradictory. This is the logical criterion of possibility,
  13534. distinguishing the object of such a conception from the nihil negativum.
  13535. But it may be, notwithstanding, an empty conception, unless the
  13536. objective reality of this synthesis, but which it is generated, is
  13537. demonstrated; and a proof of this kind must be based upon principles
  13538. of possible experience, and not upon the principle of analysis or
  13539. contradiction. This remark may be serviceable as a warning against
  13540. concluding, from the possibility of a conception--which is logical--the
  13541. possibility of a thing--which is real.]
  13542. I answer: It is absurd to introduce--under whatever term disguised--into
  13543. the conception of a thing, which is to be cogitated solely in reference
  13544. to its possibility, the conception of its existence. If this is
  13545. admitted, you will have apparently gained the day, but in reality have
  13546. enounced nothing but a mere tautology. I ask, is the proposition,
  13547. this or that thing (which I am admitting to be possible) exists, an
  13548. analytical or a synthetical proposition? If the former, there is no
  13549. addition made to the subject of your thought by the affirmation of its
  13550. existence; but then the conception in your minds is identical with
  13551. the thing itself, or you have supposed the existence of a thing to
  13552. be possible, and then inferred its existence from its internal
  13553. possibility--which is but a miserable tautology. The word reality in the
  13554. conception of the thing, and the word existence in the conception of the
  13555. predicate, will not help you out of the difficulty. For, supposing you
  13556. were to term all positing of a thing reality, you have thereby posited
  13557. the thing with all its predicates in the conception of the subject
  13558. and assumed its actual existence, and this you merely repeat in the
  13559. predicate. But if you confess, as every reasonable person must, that
  13560. every existential proposition is synthetical, how can it be
  13561. maintained that the predicate of existence cannot be denied without
  13562. contradiction?--a property which is the characteristic of analytical
  13563. propositions, alone.
  13564. I should have a reasonable hope of putting an end for ever to this
  13565. sophistical mode of argumentation, by a strict definition of the
  13566. conception of existence, did not my own experience teach me that the
  13567. illusion arising from our confounding a logical with a real predicate (a
  13568. predicate which aids in the determination of a thing) resists almost all
  13569. the endeavours of explanation and illustration. A logical predicate may
  13570. be what you please, even the subject may be predicated of itself;
  13571. for logic pays no regard to the content of a judgement. But the
  13572. determination of a conception is a predicate, which adds to and enlarges
  13573. the conception. It must not, therefore, be contained in the conception.
  13574. Being is evidently not a real predicate, that is, a conception of
  13575. something which is added to the conception of some other thing. It is
  13576. merely the positing of a thing, or of certain determinations in it.
  13577. Logically, it is merely the copula of a judgement. The proposition, God
  13578. is omnipotent, contains two conceptions, which have a certain object or
  13579. content; the word is, is no additional predicate--it merely indicates
  13580. the relation of the predicate to the subject. Now, if I take the subject
  13581. (God) with all its predicates (omnipotence being one), and say: God is,
  13582. or, There is a God, I add no new predicate to the conception of God,
  13583. I merely posit or affirm the existence of the subject with all its
  13584. predicates--I posit the object in relation to my conception. The content
  13585. of both is the same; and there is no addition made to the conception,
  13586. which expresses merely the possibility of the object, by my cogitating
  13587. the object--in the expression, it is--as absolutely given or existing.
  13588. Thus the real contains no more than the possible. A hundred real dollars
  13589. contain no more than a hundred possible dollars. For, as the latter
  13590. indicate the conception, and the former the object, on the supposition
  13591. that the content of the former was greater than that of the latter, my
  13592. conception would not be an expression of the whole object, and would
  13593. consequently be an inadequate conception of it. But in reckoning my
  13594. wealth there may be said to be more in a hundred real dollars than in a
  13595. hundred possible dollars--that is, in the mere conception of them.
  13596. For the real object--the dollars--is not analytically contained in my
  13597. conception, but forms a synthetical addition to my conception (which
  13598. is merely a determination of my mental state), although this objective
  13599. reality--this existence--apart from my conceptions, does not in the
  13600. least degree increase the aforesaid hundred dollars.
  13601. By whatever and by whatever number of predicates--even to the complete
  13602. determination of it--I may cogitate a thing, I do not in the least
  13603. augment the object of my conception by the addition of the statement:
  13604. This thing exists. Otherwise, not exactly the same, but something more
  13605. than what was cogitated in my conception, would exist, and I could not
  13606. affirm that the exact object of my conception had real existence. If I
  13607. cogitate a thing as containing all modes of reality except one, the mode
  13608. of reality which is absent is not added to the conception of the thing
  13609. by the affirmation that the thing exists; on the contrary, the thing
  13610. exists--if it exist at all--with the same defect as that cogitated in
  13611. its conception; otherwise not that which was cogitated, but something
  13612. different, exists. Now, if I cogitate a being as the highest reality,
  13613. without defect or imperfection, the question still remains--whether this
  13614. being exists or not? For, although no element is wanting in the possible
  13615. real content of my conception, there is a defect in its relation to my
  13616. mental state, that is, I am ignorant whether the cognition of the object
  13617. indicated by the conception is possible a posteriori. And here the cause
  13618. of the present difficulty becomes apparent. If the question regarded an
  13619. object of sense merely, it would be impossible for me to confound the
  13620. conception with the existence of a thing. For the conception merely
  13621. enables me to cogitate an object as according with the general
  13622. conditions of experience; while the existence of the object permits me
  13623. to cogitate it as contained in the sphere of actual experience. At the
  13624. same time, this connection with the world of experience does not in the
  13625. least augment the conception, although a possible perception has been
  13626. added to the experience of the mind. But if we cogitate existence by the
  13627. pure category alone, it is not to be wondered at, that we should find
  13628. ourselves unable to present any criterion sufficient to distinguish it
  13629. from mere possibility.
  13630. Whatever be the content of our conception of an object, it is necessary
  13631. to go beyond it, if we wish to predicate existence of the object. In the
  13632. case of sensuous objects, this is attained by their connection according
  13633. to empirical laws with some one of my perceptions; but there is no means
  13634. of cognizing the existence of objects of pure thought, because it must
  13635. be cognized completely a priori. But all our knowledge of existence (be
  13636. it immediately by perception, or by inferences connecting some object
  13637. with a perception) belongs entirely to the sphere of experience--which
  13638. is in perfect unity with itself; and although an existence out of
  13639. this sphere cannot be absolutely declared to be impossible, it is a
  13640. hypothesis the truth of which we have no means of ascertaining.
  13641. The notion of a Supreme Being is in many respects a highly useful idea;
  13642. but for the very reason that it is an idea, it is incapable of enlarging
  13643. our cognition with regard to the existence of things. It is not even
  13644. sufficient to instruct us as to the possibility of a being which we
  13645. do not know to exist. The analytical criterion of possibility, which
  13646. consists in the absence of contradiction in propositions, cannot
  13647. be denied it. But the connection of real properties in a thing is a
  13648. synthesis of the possibility of which an a priori judgement cannot be
  13649. formed, because these realities are not presented to us specifically;
  13650. and even if this were to happen, a judgement would still be impossible,
  13651. because the criterion of the possibility of synthetical cognitions must
  13652. be sought for in the world of experience, to which the object of an idea
  13653. cannot belong. And thus the celebrated Leibnitz has utterly failed in
  13654. his attempt to establish upon a priori grounds the possibility of this
  13655. sublime ideal being.
  13656. The celebrated ontological or Cartesian argument for the existence of
  13657. a Supreme Being is therefore insufficient; and we may as well hope
  13658. to increase our stock of knowledge by the aid of mere ideas, as the
  13659. merchant to augment his wealth by the addition of noughts to his cash
  13660. account.
  13661. SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the
  13662. Existence of God.
  13663. It was by no means a natural course of proceeding, but, on the contrary,
  13664. an invention entirely due to the subtlety of the schools, to attempt
  13665. to draw from a mere idea a proof of the existence of an object
  13666. corresponding to it. Such a course would never have been pursued,
  13667. were it not for that need of reason which requires it to suppose the
  13668. existence of a necessary being as a basis for the empirical regress, and
  13669. that, as this necessity must be unconditioned and a priori, reason is
  13670. bound to discover a conception which shall satisfy, if possible, this
  13671. requirement, and enable us to attain to the a priori cognition of such
  13672. a being. This conception was thought to be found in the idea of an ens
  13673. realissimum, and thus this idea was employed for the attainment of a
  13674. better defined knowledge of a necessary being, of the existence of
  13675. which we were convinced, or persuaded, on other grounds. Thus reason was
  13676. seduced from her natural courage; and, instead of concluding with the
  13677. conception of an ens realissimum, an attempt was made to begin with it,
  13678. for the purpose of inferring from it that idea of a necessary existence
  13679. which it was in fact called in to complete. Thus arose that unfortunate
  13680. ontological argument, which neither satisfies the healthy common sense
  13681. of humanity, nor sustains the scientific examination of the philosopher.
  13682. The cosmological proof, which we are about to examine, retains the
  13683. connection between absolute necessity and the highest reality; but,
  13684. instead of reasoning from this highest reality to a necessary existence,
  13685. like the preceding argument, it concludes from the given unconditioned
  13686. necessity of some being its unlimited reality. The track it pursues,
  13687. whether rational or sophistical, is at least natural, and not only goes
  13688. far to persuade the common understanding, but shows itself deserving of
  13689. respect from the speculative intellect; while it contains, at the
  13690. same time, the outlines of all the arguments employed in natural
  13691. theology--arguments which always have been, and still will be, in
  13692. use and authority. These, however adorned, and hid under whatever
  13693. embellishments of rhetoric and sentiment, are at bottom identical
  13694. with the arguments we are at present to discuss. This proof, termed by
  13695. Leibnitz the argumentum a contingentia mundi, I shall now lay before the
  13696. reader, and subject to a strict examination.
  13697. It is framed in the following manner: If something exists, an
  13698. absolutely necessary being must likewise exist. Now I, at least, exist.
  13699. Consequently, there exists an absolutely necessary being. The minor
  13700. contains an experience, the major reasons from a general experience to
  13701. the existence of a necessary being.* Thus this argument really begins at
  13702. experience, and is not completely a priori, or ontological. The
  13703. object of all possible experience being the world, it is called the
  13704. cosmological proof. It contains no reference to any peculiar property
  13705. of sensuous objects, by which this world of sense might be distinguished
  13706. from other possible worlds; and in this respect it differs from the
  13707. physico-theological proof, which is based upon the consideration of the
  13708. peculiar constitution of our sensuous world.
  13709. [*Footnote: This inference is too well known to require more detailed
  13710. discussion. It is based upon the spurious transcendental law of
  13711. causality, that everything which is contingent has a cause, which, if
  13712. itself contingent, must also have a cause; and so on, till the series of
  13713. subordinated causes must end with an absolutely necessary cause, without
  13714. which it would not possess completeness.]
  13715. The proof proceeds thus: A necessary being can be determined only in one
  13716. way, that is, it can be determined by only one of all possible opposed
  13717. predicates; consequently, it must be completely determined in and by its
  13718. conception. But there is only a single conception of a thing possible,
  13719. which completely determines the thing a priori: that is, the conception
  13720. of the ens realissimum. It follows that the conception of the ens
  13721. realissimum is the only conception by and in which we can cogitate a
  13722. necessary being. Consequently, a Supreme Being necessarily exists.
  13723. In this cosmological argument are assembled so many sophistical
  13724. propositions that speculative reason seems to have exerted in it all
  13725. her dialectical skill to produce a transcendental illusion of the most
  13726. extreme character. We shall postpone an investigation of this argument
  13727. for the present, and confine ourselves to exposing the stratagem by
  13728. which it imposes upon us an old argument in a new dress, and appeals
  13729. to the agreement of two witnesses, the one with the credentials of pure
  13730. reason, and the other with those of empiricism; while, in fact, it is
  13731. only the former who has changed his dress and voice, for the purpose
  13732. of passing himself off for an additional witness. That it may possess
  13733. a secure foundation, it bases its conclusions upon experience, and thus
  13734. appears to be completely distinct from the ontological argument, which
  13735. places its confidence entirely in pure a priori conceptions. But this
  13736. experience merely aids reason in making one step--to the existence of a
  13737. necessary being. What the properties of this being are cannot be learned
  13738. from experience; and therefore reason abandons it altogether, and
  13739. pursues its inquiries in the sphere of pure conception, for the purpose
  13740. of discovering what the properties of an absolutely necessary being
  13741. ought to be, that is, what among all possible things contain the
  13742. conditions (requisita) of absolute necessity. Reason believes that
  13743. it has discovered these requisites in the conception of an ens
  13744. realissimum--and in it alone, and hence concludes: The ens realissimum
  13745. is an absolutely necessary being. But it is evident that reason has
  13746. here presupposed that the conception of an ens realissimum is perfectly
  13747. adequate to the conception of a being of absolute necessity, that is,
  13748. that we may infer the existence of the latter from that of the former--a
  13749. proposition which formed the basis of the ontological argument, and
  13750. which is now employed in the support of the cosmological argument,
  13751. contrary to the wish and professions of its inventors. For the existence
  13752. of an absolutely necessary being is given in conceptions alone. But if
  13753. I say: "The conception of the ens realissimum is a conception of this
  13754. kind, and in fact the only conception which is adequate to our idea of a
  13755. necessary being," I am obliged to admit, that the latter may be inferred
  13756. from the former. Thus it is properly the ontological argument which
  13757. figures in the cosmological, and constitutes the whole strength of the
  13758. latter; while the spurious basis of experience has been of no further
  13759. use than to conduct us to the conception of absolute necessity, being
  13760. utterly insufficient to demonstrate the presence of this attribute in
  13761. any determinate existence or thing. For when we propose to ourselves
  13762. an aim of this character, we must abandon the sphere of experience, and
  13763. rise to that of pure conceptions, which we examine with the purpose of
  13764. discovering whether any one contains the conditions of the possibility
  13765. of an absolutely necessary being. But if the possibility of such a being
  13766. is thus demonstrated, its existence is also proved; for we may then
  13767. assert that, of all possible beings there is one which possesses
  13768. the attribute of necessity--in other words, this being possesses an
  13769. absolutely necessary existence.
  13770. All illusions in an argument are more easily detected when they are
  13771. presented in the formal manner employed by the schools, which we now
  13772. proceed to do.
  13773. If the proposition: "Every absolutely necessary being is likewise an ens
  13774. realissimum," is correct (and it is this which constitutes the nervus
  13775. probandi of the cosmological argument), it must, like all affirmative
  13776. judgements, be capable of conversion--the conversio per accidens, at
  13777. least. It follows, then, that some entia realissima are absolutely
  13778. necessary beings. But no ens realissimum is in any respect different
  13779. from another, and what is valid of some is valid of all. In this present
  13780. case, therefore, I may employ simple conversion, and say: "Every ens
  13781. realissimum is a necessary being." But as this proposition is determined
  13782. a priori by the conceptions contained in it, the mere conception of
  13783. an ens realissimum must possess the additional attribute of absolute
  13784. necessity. But this is exactly what was maintained in the ontological
  13785. argument, and not recognized by the cosmological, although it formed the
  13786. real ground of its disguised and illusory reasoning.
  13787. Thus the second mode employed by speculative reason of demonstrating the
  13788. existence of a Supreme Being, is not only, like the first, illusory
  13789. and inadequate, but possesses the additional blemish of an ignoratio
  13790. elenchi--professing to conduct us by a new road to the desired goal, but
  13791. bringing us back, after a short circuit, to the old path which we had
  13792. deserted at its call.
  13793. I mentioned above that this cosmological argument contains a perfect
  13794. nest of dialectical assumptions, which transcendental criticism does not
  13795. find it difficult to expose and to dissipate. I shall merely enumerate
  13796. these, leaving it to the reader, who must by this time be well practised
  13797. in such matters, to investigate the fallacies residing therein.
  13798. The following fallacies, for example, are discoverable in this mode of
  13799. proof: 1. The transcendental principle: "Everything that is contingent
  13800. must have a cause"--a principle without significance, except in the
  13801. sensuous world. For the purely intellectual conception of the contingent
  13802. cannot produce any synthetical proposition, like that of causality,
  13803. which is itself without significance or distinguishing characteristic
  13804. except in the phenomenal world. But in the present case it is employed
  13805. to help us beyond the limits of its sphere. 2. "From the impossibility
  13806. of an infinite ascending series of causes in the world of sense a first
  13807. cause is inferred"; a conclusion which the principles of the employment
  13808. of reason do not justify even in the sphere of experience, and still
  13809. less when an attempt is made to pass the limits of this sphere. 3.
  13810. Reason allows itself to be satisfied upon insufficient grounds, with
  13811. regard to the completion of this series. It removes all conditions
  13812. (without which, however, no conception of Necessity can take place);
  13813. and, as after this it is beyond our power to form any other conceptions,
  13814. it accepts this as a completion of the conception it wishes to form of
  13815. the series. 4. The logical possibility of a conception of the total
  13816. of reality (the criterion of this possibility being the absence of
  13817. contradiction) is confounded with the transcendental, which requires a
  13818. principle of the practicability of such a synthesis--a principle which
  13819. again refers us to the world of experience. And so on.
  13820. The aim of the cosmological argument is to avoid the necessity
  13821. of proving the existence of a necessary being priori from mere
  13822. conceptions--a proof which must be ontological, and of which we feel
  13823. ourselves quite incapable. With this purpose, we reason from an
  13824. actual existence--an experience in general, to an absolutely necessary
  13825. condition of that existence. It is in this case unnecessary to
  13826. demonstrate its possibility. For after having proved that it exists, the
  13827. question regarding its possibility is superfluous. Now, when we wish to
  13828. define more strictly the nature of this necessary being, we do not look
  13829. out for some being the conception of which would enable us to comprehend
  13830. the necessity of its being--for if we could do this, an empirical
  13831. presupposition would be unnecessary; no, we try to discover merely the
  13832. negative condition (conditio sine qua non), without which a being would
  13833. not be absolutely necessary. Now this would be perfectly admissible in
  13834. every sort of reasoning, from a consequence to its principle; but in
  13835. the present case it unfortunately happens that the condition of absolute
  13836. necessity can be discovered in but a single being, the conception of
  13837. which must consequently contain all that is requisite for demonstrating
  13838. the presence of absolute necessity, and thus entitle me to infer this
  13839. absolute necessity a priori. That is, it must be possible to reason
  13840. conversely, and say: The thing, to which the conception of the highest
  13841. reality belongs, is absolutely necessary. But if I cannot reason
  13842. thus--and I cannot, unless I believe in the sufficiency of the
  13843. ontological argument--I find insurmountable obstacles in my new path,
  13844. and am really no farther than the point from which I set out. The
  13845. conception of a Supreme Being satisfies all questions a priori regarding
  13846. the internal determinations of a thing, and is for this reason an ideal
  13847. without equal or parallel, the general conception of it indicating it
  13848. as at the same time an ens individuum among all possible things. But the
  13849. conception does not satisfy the question regarding its existence--which
  13850. was the purpose of all our inquiries; and, although the existence of a
  13851. necessary being were admitted, we should find it impossible to answer
  13852. the question: What of all things in the world must be regarded as such?
  13853. It is certainly allowable to admit the existence of an all-sufficient
  13854. being--a cause of all possible effects--for the purpose of enabling
  13855. reason to introduce unity into its mode and grounds of explanation with
  13856. regard to phenomena. But to assert that such a being necessarily exists,
  13857. is no longer the modest enunciation of an admissible hypothesis, but
  13858. the boldest declaration of an apodeictic certainty; for the cognition of
  13859. that which is absolutely necessary must itself possess that character.
  13860. The aim of the transcendental ideal formed by the mind is either to
  13861. discover a conception which shall harmonize with the idea of absolute
  13862. necessity, or a conception which shall contain that idea. If the one
  13863. is possible, so is the other; for reason recognizes that alone as
  13864. absolutely necessary which is necessary from its conception. But both
  13865. attempts are equally beyond our power--we find it impossible to satisfy
  13866. the understanding upon this point, and as impossible to induce it to
  13867. remain at rest in relation to this incapacity.
  13868. Unconditioned necessity, which, as the ultimate support and stay of
  13869. all existing things, is an indispensable requirement of the mind, is an
  13870. abyss on the verge of which human reason trembles in dismay. Even the
  13871. idea of eternity, terrible and sublime as it is, as depicted by Haller,
  13872. does not produce upon the mental vision such a feeling of awe and
  13873. terror; for, although it measures the duration of things, it does not
  13874. support them. We cannot bear, nor can we rid ourselves of the
  13875. thought that a being, which we regard as the greatest of all possible
  13876. existences, should say to himself: I am from eternity to eternity;
  13877. beside me there is nothing, except that which exists by my will; whence
  13878. then am I? Here all sinks away from under us; and the greatest, as the
  13879. smallest, perfection, hovers without stay or footing in presence of the
  13880. speculative reason, which finds it as easy to part with the one as with
  13881. the other.
  13882. Many physical powers, which evidence their existence by their effects,
  13883. are perfectly inscrutable in their nature; they elude all our powers
  13884. of observation. The transcendental object which forms the basis of
  13885. phenomena, and, in connection with it, the reason why our sensibility
  13886. possesses this rather than that particular kind of conditions, are and
  13887. must ever remain hidden from our mental vision; the fact is there, the
  13888. reason of the fact we cannot see. But an ideal of pure reason cannot
  13889. be termed mysterious or inscrutable, because the only credential of
  13890. its reality is the need of it felt by reason, for the purpose of giving
  13891. completeness to the world of synthetical unity. An ideal is not even
  13892. given as a cogitable object, and therefore cannot be inscrutable; on
  13893. the contrary, it must, as a mere idea, be based on the constitution of
  13894. reason itself, and on this account must be capable of explanation and
  13895. solution. For the very essence of reason consists in its ability to
  13896. give an account, of all our conceptions, opinions, and assertions--upon
  13897. objective, or, when they happen to be illusory and fallacious, upon
  13898. subjective grounds.
  13899. Detection and Explanation of the Dialectical Illusion in all
  13900. Transcendental Arguments for the Existence of a Necessary Being.
  13901. Both of the above arguments are transcendental; in other words, they do
  13902. not proceed upon empirical principles. For, although the cosmological
  13903. argument professed to lay a basis of experience for its edifice
  13904. of reasoning, it did not ground its procedure upon the peculiar
  13905. constitution of experience, but upon pure principles of reason--in
  13906. relation to an existence given by empirical consciousness; utterly
  13907. abandoning its guidance, however, for the purpose of supporting its
  13908. assertions entirely upon pure conceptions. Now what is the cause,
  13909. in these transcendental arguments, of the dialectical, but natural,
  13910. illusion, which connects the conceptions of necessity and supreme
  13911. reality, and hypostatizes that which cannot be anything but an idea?
  13912. What is the cause of this unavoidable step on the part of reason, of
  13913. admitting that some one among all existing things must be necessary,
  13914. while it falls back from the assertion of the existence of such a being
  13915. as from an abyss? And how does reason proceed to explain this anomaly
  13916. to itself, and from the wavering condition of a timid and reluctant
  13917. approbation--always again withdrawn--arrive at a calm and settled
  13918. insight into its cause?
  13919. It is something very remarkable that, on the supposition that something
  13920. exists, I cannot avoid the inference that something exists necessarily.
  13921. Upon this perfectly natural--but not on that account reliable--inference
  13922. does the cosmological argument rest. But, let me form any conception
  13923. whatever of a thing, I find that I cannot cogitate the existence of
  13924. the thing as absolutely necessary, and that nothing prevents me--be the
  13925. thing or being what it may--from cogitating its non-existence. I may
  13926. thus be obliged to admit that all existing things have a necessary
  13927. basis, while I cannot cogitate any single or individual thing as
  13928. necessary. In other words, I can never complete the regress through the
  13929. conditions of existence, without admitting the existence of a necessary
  13930. being; but, on the other hand, I cannot make a commencement from this
  13931. being.
  13932. If I must cogitate something as existing necessarily as the basis of
  13933. existing things, and yet am not permitted to cogitate any individual
  13934. thing as in itself necessary, the inevitable inference is that necessity
  13935. and contingency are not properties of things themselves--otherwise an
  13936. internal contradiction would result; that consequently neither of
  13937. these principles are objective, but merely subjective principles
  13938. of reason--the one requiring us to seek for a necessary ground
  13939. for everything that exists, that is, to be satisfied with no other
  13940. explanation than that which is complete a priori, the other forbidding
  13941. us ever to hope for the attainment of this completeness, that is, to
  13942. regard no member of the empirical world as unconditioned. In this
  13943. mode of viewing them, both principles, in their purely heuristic and
  13944. regulative character, and as concerning merely the formal interest of
  13945. reason, are quite consistent with each other. The one says: "You must
  13946. philosophize upon nature," as if there existed a necessary primal basis
  13947. of all existing things, solely for the purpose of introducing systematic
  13948. unity into your knowledge, by pursuing an idea of this character--a
  13949. foundation which is arbitrarily admitted to be ultimate; while the
  13950. other warns you to consider no individual determination, concerning
  13951. the existence of things, as such an ultimate foundation, that is,
  13952. as absolutely necessary, but to keep the way always open for further
  13953. progress in the deduction, and to treat every determination as
  13954. determined by some other. But if all that we perceive must be regarded
  13955. as conditionally necessary, it is impossible that anything which is
  13956. empirically given should be absolutely necessary.
  13957. It follows from this that you must accept the absolutely necessary
  13958. as out of and beyond the world, inasmuch as it is useful only as a
  13959. principle of the highest possible unity in experience, and you cannot
  13960. discover any such necessary existence in the would, the second rule
  13961. requiring you to regard all empirical causes of unity as themselves
  13962. deduced.
  13963. The philosophers of antiquity regarded all the forms of nature as
  13964. contingent; while matter was considered by them, in accordance with the
  13965. judgement of the common reason of mankind, as primal and necessary.
  13966. But if they had regarded matter, not relatively--as the substratum of
  13967. phenomena, but absolutely and in itself--as an independent existence,
  13968. this idea of absolute necessity would have immediately disappeared. For
  13969. there is nothing absolutely connecting reason with such an existence;
  13970. on the contrary, it can annihilate it in thought, always and without
  13971. self-contradiction. But in thought alone lay the idea of absolute
  13972. necessity. A regulative principle must, therefore, have been at
  13973. the foundation of this opinion. In fact, extension and
  13974. impenetrability--which together constitute our conception of
  13975. matter--form the supreme empirical principle of the unity of phenomena,
  13976. and this principle, in so far as it is empirically unconditioned,
  13977. possesses the property of a regulative principle. But, as every
  13978. determination of matter which constitutes what is real in it--and
  13979. consequently impenetrability--is an effect, which must have a cause, and
  13980. is for this reason always derived, the notion of matter cannot harmonize
  13981. with the idea of a necessary being, in its character of the principle of
  13982. all derived unity. For every one of its real properties, being derived,
  13983. must be only conditionally necessary, and can therefore be annihilated
  13984. in thought; and thus the whole existence of matter can be so annihilated
  13985. or suppressed. If this were not the case, we should have found in the
  13986. world of phenomena the highest ground or condition of unity--which is
  13987. impossible, according to the second regulative principle. It follows
  13988. that matter, and, in general, all that forms part of the world of sense,
  13989. cannot be a necessary primal being, nor even a principle of empirical
  13990. unity, but that this being or principle must have its place assigned
  13991. without the world. And, in this way, we can proceed in perfect
  13992. confidence to deduce the phenomena of the world and their existence from
  13993. other phenomena, just as if there existed no necessary being; and we
  13994. can at the same time, strive without ceasing towards the attainment of
  13995. completeness for our deduction, just as if such a being--the supreme
  13996. condition of all existences--were presupposed by the mind.
  13997. These remarks will have made it evident to the reader that the ideal of
  13998. the Supreme Being, far from being an enouncement of the existence of a
  13999. being in itself necessary, is nothing more than a regulative principle
  14000. of reason, requiring us to regard all connection existing between
  14001. phenomena as if it had its origin from an all-sufficient necessary
  14002. cause, and basing upon this the rule of a systematic and necessary unity
  14003. in the explanation of phenomena. We cannot, at the same time, avoid
  14004. regarding, by a transcendental subreptio, this formal principle as
  14005. constitutive, and hypostatizing this unity. Precisely similar is the
  14006. case with our notion of space. Space is the primal condition of all
  14007. forms, which are properly just so many different limitations of it; and
  14008. thus, although it is merely a principle of sensibility, we cannot help
  14009. regarding it as an absolutely necessary and self-subsistent thing--as
  14010. an object given a priori in itself. In the same way, it is quite natural
  14011. that, as the systematic unity of nature cannot be established as a
  14012. principle for the empirical employment of reason, unless it is based
  14013. upon the idea of an ens realissimum, as the supreme cause, we should
  14014. regard this idea as a real object, and this object, in its character
  14015. of supreme condition, as absolutely necessary, and that in this way a
  14016. regulative should be transformed into a constitutive principle. This
  14017. interchange becomes evident when I regard this supreme being, which,
  14018. relatively to the world, was absolutely (unconditionally) necessary,
  14019. as a thing per se. In this case, I find it impossible to represent this
  14020. necessity in or by any conception, and it exists merely in my own mind,
  14021. as the formal condition of thought, but not as a material and hypostatic
  14022. condition of existence.
  14023. SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a Physico-Theological Proof.
  14024. If, then, neither a pure conception nor the general experience of an
  14025. existing being can provide a sufficient basis for the proof of the
  14026. existence of the Deity, we can make the attempt by the only other
  14027. mode--that of grounding our argument upon a determinate experience of
  14028. the phenomena of the present world, their constitution and disposition,
  14029. and discover whether we can thus attain to a sound conviction of
  14030. the existence of a Supreme Being. This argument we shall term the
  14031. physico-theological argument. If it is shown to be insufficient,
  14032. speculative reason cannot present us with any satisfactory proof of the
  14033. existence of a being corresponding to our transcendental idea.
  14034. It is evident from the remarks that have been made in the preceding
  14035. sections, that an answer to this question will be far from being
  14036. difficult or unconvincing. For how can any experience be adequate
  14037. with an idea? The very essence of an idea consists in the fact that no
  14038. experience can ever be discovered congruent or adequate with it. The
  14039. transcendental idea of a necessary and all-sufficient being is so
  14040. immeasurably great, so high above all that is empirical, which is always
  14041. conditioned, that we hope in vain to find materials in the sphere of
  14042. experience sufficiently ample for our conception, and in vain seek the
  14043. unconditioned among things that are conditioned, while examples, nay,
  14044. even guidance is denied us by the laws of empirical synthesis.
  14045. If the Supreme Being forms a link in the chain of empirical conditions,
  14046. it must be a member of the empirical series, and, like the lower members
  14047. which it precedes, have its origin in some higher member of the series.
  14048. If, on the other hand, we disengage it from the chain, and cogitate it
  14049. as an intelligible being, apart from the series of natural causes--how
  14050. shall reason bridge the abyss that separates the latter from the former?
  14051. All laws respecting the regress from effects to causes, all synthetical
  14052. additions to our knowledge relate solely to possible experience and
  14053. the objects of the sensuous world, and, apart from them, are without
  14054. significance.
  14055. The world around us opens before our view so magnificent a spectacle of
  14056. order, variety, beauty, and conformity to ends, that whether we pursue
  14057. our observations into the infinity of space in the one direction, or
  14058. into its illimitable divisions in the other, whether we regard the world
  14059. in its greatest or its least manifestations--even after we have attained
  14060. to the highest summit of knowledge which our weak minds can reach, we
  14061. find that language in the presence of wonders so inconceivable has lost
  14062. its force, and number its power to reckon, nay, even thought fails to
  14063. conceive adequately, and our conception of the whole dissolves into an
  14064. astonishment without power of expression--all the more eloquent that it
  14065. is dumb. Everywhere around us we observe a chain of causes and effects,
  14066. of means and ends, of death and birth; and, as nothing has entered
  14067. of itself into the condition in which we find it, we are constantly
  14068. referred to some other thing, which itself suggests the same inquiry
  14069. regarding its cause, and thus the universe must sink into the abyss
  14070. of nothingness, unless we admit that, besides this infinite chain
  14071. of contingencies, there exists something that is primal and
  14072. self-subsistent--something which, as the cause of this phenomenal world,
  14073. secures its continuance and preservation.
  14074. This highest cause--what magnitude shall we attribute to it? Of the
  14075. content of the world we are ignorant; still less can we estimate its
  14076. magnitude by comparison with the sphere of the possible. But this
  14077. supreme cause being a necessity of the human mind, what is there to
  14078. prevent us from attributing to it such a degree of perfection as to
  14079. place it above the sphere of all that is possible? This we can easily
  14080. do, although only by the aid of the faint outline of an abstract
  14081. conception, by representing this being to ourselves as containing
  14082. in itself, as an individual substance, all possible perfection--a
  14083. conception which satisfies that requirement of reason which demands
  14084. parsimony in principles, which is free from self-contradiction, which
  14085. even contributes to the extension of the employment of reason in
  14086. experience, by means of the guidance afforded by this idea to order and
  14087. system, and which in no respect conflicts with any law of experience.
  14088. This argument always deserves to be mentioned with respect. It is the
  14089. oldest, the clearest, and that most in conformity with the common reason
  14090. of humanity. It animates the study of nature, as it itself derives its
  14091. existence and draws ever new strength from that source. It introduces
  14092. aims and ends into a sphere in which our observation could not of itself
  14093. have discovered them, and extends our knowledge of nature, by directing
  14094. our attention to a unity, the principle of which lies beyond nature.
  14095. This knowledge of nature again reacts upon this idea--its cause; and
  14096. thus our belief in a divine author of the universe rises to the power of
  14097. an irresistible conviction.
  14098. For these reasons it would be utterly hopeless to attempt to rob this
  14099. argument of the authority it has always enjoyed. The mind, unceasingly
  14100. elevated by these considerations, which, although empirical, are so
  14101. remarkably powerful, and continually adding to their force, will
  14102. not suffer itself to be depressed by the doubts suggested by subtle
  14103. speculation; it tears itself out of this state of uncertainty, the
  14104. moment it casts a look upon the wondrous forms of nature and the majesty
  14105. of the universe, and rises from height to height, from condition to
  14106. condition, till it has elevated itself to the supreme and unconditioned
  14107. author of all.
  14108. But although we have nothing to object to the reasonableness and utility
  14109. of this procedure, but have rather to commend and encourage it,
  14110. we cannot approve of the claims which this argument advances to
  14111. demonstrative certainty and to a reception upon its own merits, apart
  14112. from favour or support by other arguments. Nor can it injure the cause
  14113. of morality to endeavour to lower the tone of the arrogant sophist, and
  14114. to teach him that modesty and moderation which are the properties of a
  14115. belief that brings calm and content into the mind, without
  14116. prescribing to it an unworthy subjection. I maintain, then, that the
  14117. physico-theological argument is insufficient of itself to prove
  14118. the existence of a Supreme Being, that it must entrust this to the
  14119. ontological argument--to which it serves merely as an introduction, and
  14120. that, consequently, this argument contains the only possible ground of
  14121. proof (possessed by speculative reason) for the existence of this being.
  14122. The chief momenta in the physico-theological argument are as follow:
  14123. 1. We observe in the world manifest signs of an arrangement full of
  14124. purpose, executed with great wisdom, and argument in whole of a
  14125. content indescribably various, and of an extent without limits. 2. This
  14126. arrangement of means and ends is entirely foreign to the things existing
  14127. in the world--it belongs to them merely as a contingent attribute;
  14128. in other words, the nature of different things could not of itself,
  14129. whatever means were employed, harmoniously tend towards certain
  14130. purposes, were they not chosen and directed for these purposes by a
  14131. rational and disposing principle, in accordance with certain fundamental
  14132. ideas. 3. There exists, therefore, a sublime and wise cause (or
  14133. several), which is not merely a blind, all-powerful nature, producing
  14134. the beings and events which fill the world in unconscious fecundity, but
  14135. a free and intelligent cause of the world. 4. The unity of this cause
  14136. may be inferred from the unity of the reciprocal relation existing
  14137. between the parts of the world, as portions of an artistic edifice--an
  14138. inference which all our observation favours, and all principles of
  14139. analogy support.
  14140. In the above argument, it is inferred from the analogy of certain
  14141. products of nature with those of human art, when it compels Nature to
  14142. bend herself to its purposes, as in the case of a house, a ship, or
  14143. a watch, that the same kind of causality--namely, understanding
  14144. and will--resides in nature. It is also declared that the internal
  14145. possibility of this freely-acting nature (which is the source of all
  14146. art, and perhaps also of human reason) is derivable from another and
  14147. superhuman art--a conclusion which would perhaps be found incapable of
  14148. standing the test of subtle transcendental criticism. But to neither of
  14149. these opinions shall we at present object. We shall only remark that
  14150. it must be confessed that, if we are to discuss the subject of cause
  14151. at all, we cannot proceed more securely than with the guidance of the
  14152. analogy subsisting between nature and such products of design--these
  14153. being the only products whose causes and modes of organization are
  14154. completely known to us. Reason would be unable to satisfy her own
  14155. requirements, if she passed from a causality which she does know, to
  14156. obscure and indemonstrable principles of explanation which she does not
  14157. know.
  14158. According to the physico-theological argument, the connection and
  14159. harmony existing in the world evidence the contingency of the form
  14160. merely, but not of the matter, that is, of the substance of the world.
  14161. To establish the truth of the latter opinion, it would be necessary to
  14162. prove that all things would be in themselves incapable of this harmony
  14163. and order, unless they were, even as regards their substance, the
  14164. product of a supreme wisdom. But this would require very different
  14165. grounds of proof from those presented by the analogy with human art.
  14166. This proof can at most, therefore, demonstrate the existence of an
  14167. architect of the world, whose efforts are limited by the capabilities of
  14168. the material with which he works, but not of a creator of the world, to
  14169. whom all things are subject. Thus this argument is utterly insufficient
  14170. for the task before us--a demonstration of the existence of an
  14171. all-sufficient being. If we wish to prove the contingency of matter,
  14172. we must have recourse to a transcendental argument, which the
  14173. physico-theological was constructed expressly to avoid.
  14174. We infer, from the order and design visible in the universe, as a
  14175. disposition of a thoroughly contingent character, the existence of a
  14176. cause proportionate thereto. The conception of this cause must contain
  14177. certain determinate qualities, and it must therefore be regarded as the
  14178. conception of a being which possesses all power, wisdom, and so on, in
  14179. one word, all perfection--the conception, that is, of an all-sufficient
  14180. being. For the predicates of very great, astonishing, or immeasurable
  14181. power and excellence, give us no determinate conception of the thing,
  14182. nor do they inform us what the thing may be in itself. They merely
  14183. indicate the relation existing between the magnitude of the object and
  14184. the observer, who compares it with himself and with his own power of
  14185. comprehension, and are mere expressions of praise and reverence,
  14186. by which the object is either magnified, or the observing subject
  14187. depreciated in relation to the object. Where we have to do with the
  14188. magnitude (of the perfection) of a thing, we can discover no determinate
  14189. conception, except that which comprehends all possible perfection or
  14190. completeness, and it is only the total (omnitudo) of reality which is
  14191. completely determined in and through its conception alone.
  14192. Now it cannot be expected that any one will be bold enough to declare
  14193. that he has a perfect insight into the relation which the magnitude
  14194. of the world he contemplates bears (in its extent as well as in its
  14195. content) to omnipotence, into that of the order and design in the
  14196. world to the highest wisdom, and that of the unity of the world to
  14197. the absolute unity of a Supreme Being. Physico-theology is therefore
  14198. incapable of presenting a determinate conception of a supreme cause of
  14199. the world, and is therefore insufficient as a principle of theology--a
  14200. theology which is itself to be the basis of religion.
  14201. The attainment of absolute totality is completely impossible on the
  14202. path of empiricism. And yet this is the path pursued in the
  14203. physico-theological argument. What means shall we employ to bridge the
  14204. abyss?
  14205. After elevating ourselves to admiration of the magnitude of the power,
  14206. wisdom, and other attributes of the author of the world, and finding we
  14207. can advance no further, we leave the argument on empirical grounds,
  14208. and proceed to infer the contingency of the world from the order and
  14209. conformity to aims that are observable in it. From this contingency we
  14210. infer, by the help of transcendental conceptions alone, the existence of
  14211. something absolutely necessary; and, still advancing, proceed from
  14212. the conception of the absolute necessity of the first cause to the
  14213. completely determined or determining conception thereof--the conception
  14214. of an all-embracing reality. Thus the physico-theological, failing
  14215. in its undertaking, recurs in its embarrassment to the cosmological
  14216. argument; and, as this is merely the ontological argument in disguise,
  14217. it executes its design solely by the aid of pure reason, although it at
  14218. first professed to have no connection with this faculty and to base its
  14219. entire procedure upon experience alone.
  14220. The physico-theologians have therefore no reason to regard with such
  14221. contempt the transcendental mode of argument, and to look down upon
  14222. it, with the conceit of clear-sighted observers of nature, as the
  14223. brain-cobweb of obscure speculatists. For, if they reflect upon and
  14224. examine their own arguments, they will find that, after following for
  14225. some time the path of nature and experience, and discovering themselves
  14226. no nearer their object, they suddenly leave this path and pass into the
  14227. region of pure possibility, where they hope to reach upon the wings of
  14228. ideas what had eluded all their empirical investigations. Gaining, as
  14229. they think, a firm footing after this immense leap, they extend their
  14230. determinate conception--into the possession of which they have come,
  14231. they know not how--over the whole sphere of creation, and explain their
  14232. ideal, which is entirely a product of pure reason, by illustrations
  14233. drawn from experience--though in a degree miserably unworthy of the
  14234. grandeur of the object, while they refuse to acknowledge that they have
  14235. arrived at this cognition or hypothesis by a very different road from
  14236. that of experience.
  14237. Thus the physico-theological is based upon the cosmological, and this
  14238. upon the ontological proof of the existence of a Supreme Being; and as
  14239. besides these three there is no other path open to speculative reason,
  14240. the ontological proof, on the ground of pure conceptions of reason, is
  14241. the only possible one, if any proof of a proposition so far transcending
  14242. the empirical exercise of the understanding is possible at all.
  14243. SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative
  14244. Principles of Reason.
  14245. If by the term theology I understand the cognition of a primal being,
  14246. that cognition is based either upon reason alone (theologia rationalis)
  14247. or upon revelation (theologia revelata). The former cogitates its
  14248. object either by means of pure transcendental conceptions, as an ens
  14249. originarium, realissimum, ens entium, and is termed transcendental
  14250. theology; or, by means of a conception derived from the nature of our
  14251. own mind, as a supreme intelligence, and must then be entitled natural
  14252. theology. The person who believes in a transcendental theology alone,
  14253. is termed a deist; he who acknowledges the possibility of a natural
  14254. theology also, a theist. The former admits that we can cognize by pure
  14255. reason alone the existence of a Supreme Being, but at the same time
  14256. maintains that our conception of this being is purely transcendental,
  14257. and that all we can say of it is that it possesses all reality, without
  14258. being able to define it more closely. The second asserts that reason
  14259. is capable of presenting us, from the analogy with nature, with a more
  14260. definite conception of this being, and that its operations, as the cause
  14261. of all things, are the results of intelligence and free will. The former
  14262. regards the Supreme Being as the cause of the world--whether by the
  14263. necessity of his nature, or as a free agent, is left undetermined; the
  14264. latter considers this being as the author of the world.
  14265. Transcendental theology aims either at inferring the existence of a
  14266. Supreme Being from a general experience, without any closer reference
  14267. to the world to which this experience belongs, and in this case it is
  14268. called cosmotheology; or it endeavours to cognize the existence of such
  14269. a being, through mere conceptions, without the aid of experience, and is
  14270. then termed ontotheology.
  14271. Natural theology infers the attributes and the existence of an author of
  14272. the world, from the constitution of, the order and unity observable
  14273. in, the world, in which two modes of causality must be admitted to
  14274. exist--those of nature and freedom. Thus it rises from this world to a
  14275. supreme intelligence, either as the principle of all natural, or of
  14276. all moral order and perfection. In the former case it is termed
  14277. physico-theology, in the latter, ethical or moral-theology.*
  14278. [*Footnote: Not theological ethics; for this science contains ethical
  14279. laws, which presuppose the existence of a Supreme Governor of the world;
  14280. while moral-theology, on the contrary, is the expression of a conviction
  14281. of the existence of a Supreme Being, founded upon ethical laws.]
  14282. As we are wont to understand by the term God not merely an eternal
  14283. nature, the operations of which are insensate and blind, but a Supreme
  14284. Being, who is the free and intelligent author of all things, and as it
  14285. is this latter view alone that can be of interest to humanity, we might,
  14286. in strict rigour, deny to the deist any belief in God at all, and
  14287. regard him merely as a maintainer of the existence of a primal being or
  14288. thing--the supreme cause of all other things. But, as no one ought to be
  14289. blamed, merely because he does not feel himself justified in maintaining
  14290. a certain opinion, as if he altogether denied its truth and asserted
  14291. the opposite, it is more correct--as it is less harsh--to say, the deist
  14292. believes in a God, the theist in a living God (summa intelligentia). We
  14293. shall now proceed to investigate the sources of all these attempts of
  14294. reason to establish the existence of a Supreme Being.
  14295. It may be sufficient in this place to define theoretical knowledge or
  14296. cognition as knowledge of that which is, and practical knowledge as
  14297. knowledge of that which ought to be. In this view, the theoretical
  14298. employment of reason is that by which I cognize a priori (as necessary)
  14299. that something is, while the practical is that by which I cognize a
  14300. priori what ought to happen. Now, if it is an indubitably certain,
  14301. though at the same time an entirely conditioned truth, that something
  14302. is, or ought to happen, either a certain determinate condition of this
  14303. truth is absolutely necessary, or such a condition may be arbitrarily
  14304. presupposed. In the former case the condition is postulated (per
  14305. thesin), in the latter supposed (per hypothesin). There are certain
  14306. practical laws--those of morality--which are absolutely necessary. Now,
  14307. if these laws necessarily presuppose the existence of some being, as the
  14308. condition of the possibility of their obligatory power, this being must
  14309. be postulated, because the conditioned, from which we reason to this
  14310. determinate condition, is itself cognized a priori as absolutely
  14311. necessary. We shall at some future time show that the moral laws
  14312. not merely presuppose the existence of a Supreme Being, but also, as
  14313. themselves absolutely necessary in a different relation, demand
  14314. or postulate it--although only from a practical point of view. The
  14315. discussion of this argument we postpone for the present.
  14316. When the question relates merely to that which is, not to that which
  14317. ought to be, the conditioned which is presented in experience is
  14318. always cogitated as contingent. For this reason its condition cannot be
  14319. regarded as absolutely necessary, but merely as relatively necessary,
  14320. or rather as needful; the condition is in itself and a priori a mere
  14321. arbitrary presupposition in aid of the cognition, by reason, of the
  14322. conditioned. If, then, we are to possess a theoretical cognition of
  14323. the absolute necessity of a thing, we cannot attain to this cognition
  14324. otherwise than a priori by means of conceptions; while it is impossible
  14325. in this way to cognize the existence of a cause which bears any relation
  14326. to an existence given in experience.
  14327. Theoretical cognition is speculative when it relates to an object
  14328. or certain conceptions of an object which is not given and cannot be
  14329. discovered by means of experience. It is opposed to the cognition of
  14330. nature, which concerns only those objects or predicates which can be
  14331. presented in a possible experience.
  14332. The principle that everything which happens (the empirically contingent)
  14333. must have a cause, is a principle of the cognition of nature, but not of
  14334. speculative cognition. For, if we change it into an abstract principle,
  14335. and deprive it of its reference to experience and the empirical, we
  14336. shall find that it cannot with justice be regarded any longer as a
  14337. synthetical proposition, and that it is impossible to discover any
  14338. mode of transition from that which exists to something entirely
  14339. different--termed cause. Nay, more, the conception of a cause likewise
  14340. that of the contingent--loses, in this speculative mode of employing
  14341. it, all significance, for its objective reality and meaning are
  14342. comprehensible from experience alone.
  14343. When from the existence of the universe and the things in it the
  14344. existence of a cause of the universe is inferred, reason is proceeding
  14345. not in the natural, but in the speculative method. For the principle of
  14346. the former enounces, not that things themselves or substances, but only
  14347. that which happens or their states--as empirically contingent, have
  14348. a cause: the assertion that the existence of substance itself is
  14349. contingent is not justified by experience, it is the assertion of a
  14350. reason employing its principles in a speculative manner. If, again, I
  14351. infer from the form of the universe, from the way in which all things
  14352. are connected and act and react upon each other, the existence of
  14353. a cause entirely distinct from the universe--this would again be a
  14354. judgement of purely speculative reason; because the object in this
  14355. case--the cause--can never be an object of possible experience. In both
  14356. these cases the principle of causality, which is valid only in the field
  14357. of experience--useless and even meaningless beyond this region, would be
  14358. diverted from its proper destination.
  14359. Now I maintain that all attempts of reason to establish a theology
  14360. by the aid of speculation alone are fruitless, that the principles of
  14361. reason as applied to nature do not conduct us to any theological truths,
  14362. and, consequently, that a rational theology can have no existence,
  14363. unless it is founded upon the laws of morality. For all synthetical
  14364. principles of the understanding are valid only as immanent in
  14365. experience; while the cognition of a Supreme Being necessitates their
  14366. being employed transcendentally, and of this the understanding is quite
  14367. incapable. If the empirical law of causality is to conduct us to
  14368. a Supreme Being, this being must belong to the chain of empirical
  14369. objects--in which case it would be, like all phenomena, itself
  14370. conditioned. If the possibility of passing the limits of experience be
  14371. admitted, by means of the dynamical law of the relation of an effect to
  14372. its cause, what kind of conception shall we obtain by this procedure?
  14373. Certainly not the conception of a Supreme Being, because experience
  14374. never presents us with the greatest of all possible effects, and it is
  14375. only an effect of this character that could witness to the existence
  14376. of a corresponding cause. If, for the purpose of fully satisfying the
  14377. requirements of Reason, we recognize her right to assert the existence
  14378. of a perfect and absolutely necessary being, this can be admitted
  14379. only from favour, and cannot be regarded as the result or irresistible
  14380. demonstration. The physico-theological proof may add weight to
  14381. others--if other proofs there are--by connecting speculation with
  14382. experience; but in itself it rather prepares the mind for theological
  14383. cognition, and gives it a right and natural direction, than establishes
  14384. a sure foundation for theology.
  14385. It is now perfectly evident that transcendental questions admit only
  14386. of transcendental answers--those presented a priori by pure conceptions
  14387. without the least empirical admixture. But the question in the present
  14388. case is evidently synthetical--it aims at the extension of our cognition
  14389. beyond the bounds of experience--it requires an assurance respecting the
  14390. existence of a being corresponding with the idea in our minds, to which
  14391. no experience can ever be adequate. Now it has been abundantly proved
  14392. that all a priori synthetical cognition is possible only as the
  14393. expression of the formal conditions of a possible experience; and that
  14394. the validity of all principles depends upon their immanence in the field
  14395. of experience, that is, their relation to objects of empirical cognition
  14396. or phenomena. Thus all transcendental procedure in reference to
  14397. speculative theology is without result.
  14398. If any one prefers doubting the conclusiveness of the proofs of our
  14399. analytic to losing the persuasion of the validity of these old and
  14400. time honoured arguments, he at least cannot decline answering the
  14401. question--how he can pass the limits of all possible experience by the
  14402. help of mere ideas. If he talks of new arguments, or of improvements
  14403. upon old arguments, I request him to spare me. There is certainly no
  14404. great choice in this sphere of discussion, as all speculative arguments
  14405. must at last look for support to the ontological, and I have, therefore,
  14406. very little to fear from the argumentative fecundity of the dogmatical
  14407. defenders of a non-sensuous reason. Without looking upon myself as a
  14408. remarkably combative person, I shall not decline the challenge to detect
  14409. the fallacy and destroy the pretensions of every attempt of speculative
  14410. theology. And yet the hope of better fortune never deserts those who
  14411. are accustomed to the dogmatical mode of procedure. I shall, therefore,
  14412. restrict myself to the simple and equitable demand that such reasoners
  14413. will demonstrate, from the nature of the human mind as well as from that
  14414. of the other sources of knowledge, how we are to proceed to extend
  14415. our cognition completely a priori, and to carry it to that point where
  14416. experience abandons us, and no means exist of guaranteeing the objective
  14417. reality of our conceptions. In whatever way the understanding may have
  14418. attained to a conception, the existence of the object of the conception
  14419. cannot be discovered in it by analysis, because the cognition of the
  14420. existence of the object depends upon the object's being posited and
  14421. given in itself apart from the conception. But it is utterly impossible
  14422. to go beyond our conception, without the aid of experience--which
  14423. presents to the mind nothing but phenomena, or to attain by the help
  14424. of mere conceptions to a conviction of the existence of new kinds of
  14425. objects or supernatural beings.
  14426. But although pure speculative reason is far from sufficient to
  14427. demonstrate the existence of a Supreme Being, it is of the highest
  14428. utility in correcting our conception of this being--on the supposition
  14429. that we can attain to the cognition of it by some other means--in making
  14430. it consistent with itself and with all other conceptions of intelligible
  14431. objects, clearing it from all that is incompatible with the conception
  14432. of an ens summun, and eliminating from it all limitations or admixtures
  14433. of empirical elements.
  14434. Transcendental theology is still therefore, notwithstanding its
  14435. objective insufficiency, of importance in a negative respect; it is
  14436. useful as a test of the procedure of reason when engaged with pure
  14437. ideas, no other than a transcendental standard being in this case
  14438. admissible. For if, from a practical point of view, the hypothesis of
  14439. a Supreme and All-sufficient Being is to maintain its validity without
  14440. opposition, it must be of the highest importance to define this
  14441. conception in a correct and rigorous manner--as the transcendental
  14442. conception of a necessary being, to eliminate all phenomenal elements
  14443. (anthropomorphism in its most extended signification), and at the
  14444. same time to overflow all contradictory assertions--be they atheistic,
  14445. deistic, or anthropomorphic. This is of course very easy; as the same
  14446. arguments which demonstrated the inability of human reason to affirm
  14447. the existence of a Supreme Being must be alike sufficient to prove the
  14448. invalidity of its denial. For it is impossible to gain from the pure
  14449. speculation of reason demonstration that there exists no Supreme Being,
  14450. as the ground of all that exists, or that this being possesses none
  14451. of those properties which we regard as analogical with the dynamical
  14452. qualities of a thinking being, or that, as the anthropomorphists would
  14453. have us believe, it is subject to all the limitations which sensibility
  14454. imposes upon those intelligences which exist in the world of experience.
  14455. A Supreme Being is, therefore, for the speculative reason, a mere ideal,
  14456. though a faultless one--a conception which perfects and crowns the
  14457. system of human cognition, but the objective reality of which can
  14458. neither be proved nor disproved by pure reason. If this defect is ever
  14459. supplied by a moral theology, the problematic transcendental theology
  14460. which has preceded, will have been at least serviceable as demonstrating
  14461. the mental necessity existing for the conception, by the complete
  14462. determination of it which it has furnished, and the ceaseless testing of
  14463. the conclusions of a reason often deceived by sense, and not always in
  14464. harmony with its own ideas. The attributes of necessity, infinitude,
  14465. unity, existence apart from the world (and not as a world soul),
  14466. eternity (free from conditions of time), omnipresence (free from
  14467. conditions of space), omnipotence, and others, are pure transcendental
  14468. predicates; and thus the accurate conception of a Supreme Being, which
  14469. every theology requires, is furnished by transcendental theology alone.
  14470. APPENDIX.
  14471. Of the Regulative Employment of the Ideas of Pure Reason.
  14472. The result of all the dialectical attempts of pure reason not only
  14473. confirms the truth of what we have already proved in our Transcendental
  14474. Analytic, namely, that all inferences which would lead us beyond the
  14475. limits of experience are fallacious and groundless, but it at the same
  14476. time teaches us this important lesson, that human reason has a natural
  14477. inclination to overstep these limits, and that transcendental ideas
  14478. are as much the natural property of the reason as categories are of the
  14479. understanding. There exists this difference, however, that while the
  14480. categories never mislead us, outward objects being always in perfect
  14481. harmony therewith, ideas are the parents of irresistible illusions, the
  14482. severest and most subtle criticism being required to save us from the
  14483. fallacies which they induce.
  14484. Whatever is grounded in the nature of our powers will be found to be in
  14485. harmony with the final purpose and proper employment of these powers,
  14486. when once we have discovered their true direction and aim. We are
  14487. entitled to suppose, therefore, that there exists a mode of employing
  14488. transcendental ideas which is proper and immanent; although, when we
  14489. mistake their meaning, and regard them as conceptions of actual things,
  14490. their mode of application is transcendent and delusive. For it is not
  14491. the idea itself, but only the employment of the idea in relation to
  14492. possible experience, that is transcendent or immanent. An idea is
  14493. employed transcendently, when it is applied to an object falsely
  14494. believed to be adequate with and to correspond to it; imminently, when
  14495. it is applied solely to the employment of the understanding in the
  14496. sphere of experience. Thus all errors of subreptio--of misapplication,
  14497. are to be ascribed to defects of judgement, and not to understanding or
  14498. reason.
  14499. Reason never has an immediate relation to an object; it relates
  14500. immediately to the understanding alone. It is only through the
  14501. understanding that it can be employed in the field of experience. It
  14502. does not form conceptions of objects, it merely arranges them and gives
  14503. to them that unity which they are capable of possessing when the sphere
  14504. of their application has been extended as widely as possible. Reason
  14505. avails itself of the conception of the understanding for the sole
  14506. purpose of producing totality in the different series. This totality the
  14507. understanding does not concern itself with; its only occupation is the
  14508. connection of experiences, by which series of conditions in accordance
  14509. with conceptions are established. The object of reason is, therefore,
  14510. the understanding and its proper destination. As the latter brings unity
  14511. into the diversity of objects by means of its conceptions, so the former
  14512. brings unity into the diversity of conceptions by means of ideas; as
  14513. it sets the final aim of a collective unity to the operations of the
  14514. understanding, which without this occupies itself with a distributive
  14515. unity alone.
  14516. I accordingly maintain that transcendental ideas can never be employed
  14517. as constitutive ideas, that they cannot be conceptions of objects, and
  14518. that, when thus considered, they assume a fallacious and dialectical
  14519. character. But, on the other hand, they are capable of an admirable and
  14520. indispensably necessary application to objects--as regulative ideas,
  14521. directing the understanding to a certain aim, the guiding lines towards
  14522. which all its laws follow, and in which they all meet in one point. This
  14523. point--though a mere idea (focus imaginarius), that is, not a point from
  14524. which the conceptions of the understanding do really proceed, for it
  14525. lies beyond the sphere of possible experience--serves, notwithstanding,
  14526. to give to these conceptions the greatest possible unity combined with
  14527. the greatest possible extension. Hence arises the natural illusion which
  14528. induces us to believe that these lines proceed from an object which lies
  14529. out of the sphere of empirical cognition, just as objects reflected in
  14530. a mirror appear to be behind it. But this illusion--which we may hinder
  14531. from imposing upon us--is necessary and unavoidable, if we desire to
  14532. see, not only those objects which lie before us, but those which are at
  14533. a great distance behind us; that is to say, when, in the present case,
  14534. we direct the aims of the understanding, beyond every given experience,
  14535. towards an extension as great as can possibly be attained.
  14536. If we review our cognitions in their entire extent, we shall find that
  14537. the peculiar business of reason is to arrange them into a system, that
  14538. is to say, to give them connection according to a principle. This unity
  14539. presupposes an idea--the idea of the form of a whole (of cognition),
  14540. preceding the determinate cognition of the parts, and containing the
  14541. conditions which determine a priori to every part its place and relation
  14542. to the other parts of the whole system. This idea, accordingly, demands
  14543. complete unity in the cognition of the understanding--not the unity of
  14544. a contingent aggregate, but that of a system connected according to
  14545. necessary laws. It cannot be affirmed with propriety that this idea is a
  14546. conception of an object; it is merely a conception of the complete unity
  14547. of the conceptions of objects, in so far as this unity is available to
  14548. the understanding as a rule. Such conceptions of reason are not derived
  14549. from nature; on the contrary, we employ them for the interrogation and
  14550. investigation of nature, and regard our cognition as defective so long
  14551. as it is not adequate to them. We admit that such a thing as pure earth,
  14552. pure water, or pure air, is not to be discovered. And yet we require
  14553. these conceptions (which have their origin in the reason, so far as
  14554. regards their absolute purity and completeness) for the purpose of
  14555. determining the share which each of these natural causes has in every
  14556. phenomenon. Thus the different kinds of matter are all referred to
  14557. earths, as mere weight; to salts and inflammable bodies, as pure force;
  14558. and finally, to water and air, as the vehicula of the former, or the
  14559. machines employed by them in their operations--for the purpose of
  14560. explaining the chemical action and reaction of bodies in accordance with
  14561. the idea of a mechanism. For, although not actually so expressed, the
  14562. influence of such ideas of reason is very observable in the procedure of
  14563. natural philosophers.
  14564. If reason is the faculty of deducing the particular from the general,
  14565. and if the general be certain in se and given, it is only necessary
  14566. that the judgement should subsume the particular under the general,
  14567. the particular being thus necessarily determined. I shall term this
  14568. the demonstrative or apodeictic employment of reason. If, however,
  14569. the general is admitted as problematical only, and is a mere idea,
  14570. the particular case is certain, but the universality of the rule which
  14571. applies to this particular case remains a problem. Several particular
  14572. cases, the certainty of which is beyond doubt, are then taken and
  14573. examined, for the purpose of discovering whether the rule is applicable
  14574. to them; and if it appears that all the particular cases which can be
  14575. collected follow from the rule, its universality is inferred, and at the
  14576. same time, all the causes which have not, or cannot be presented to our
  14577. observation, are concluded to be of the same character with those which
  14578. we have observed. This I shall term the hypothetical employment of the
  14579. reason.
  14580. The hypothetical exercise of reason by the aid of ideas employed as
  14581. problematical conceptions is properly not constitutive. That is to say,
  14582. if we consider the subject strictly, the truth of the rule, which has
  14583. been employed as an hypothesis, does not follow from the use that is
  14584. made of it by reason. For how can we know all the possible cases
  14585. that may arise? some of which may, however, prove exceptions to
  14586. the universality of the rule. This employment of reason is merely
  14587. regulative, and its sole aim is the introduction of unity into the
  14588. aggregate of our particular cognitions, and thereby the approximating of
  14589. the rule to universality.
  14590. The object of the hypothetical employment of reason is therefore the
  14591. systematic unity of cognitions; and this unity is the criterion of the
  14592. truth of a rule. On the other hand, this systematic unity--as a mere
  14593. idea--is in fact merely a unity projected, not to be regarded as given,
  14594. but only in the light of a problem--a problem which serves, however, as
  14595. a principle for the various and particular exercise of the understanding
  14596. in experience, directs it with regard to those cases which are not
  14597. presented to our observation, and introduces harmony and consistency
  14598. into all its operations.
  14599. All that we can be certain of from the above considerations is that
  14600. this systematic unity is a logical principle, whose aim is to assist the
  14601. understanding, where it cannot of itself attain to rules, by means of
  14602. ideas, to bring all these various rules under one principle, and thus
  14603. to ensure the most complete consistency and connection that can be
  14604. attained. But the assertion that objects and the understanding by which
  14605. they are cognized are so constituted as to be determined to systematic
  14606. unity, that this may be postulated a priori, without any reference
  14607. to the interest of reason, and that we are justified in declaring all
  14608. possible cognitions--empirical and others--to possess systematic unity,
  14609. and to be subject to general principles from which, notwithstanding
  14610. their various character, they are all derivable such an assertion can
  14611. be founded only upon a transcendental principle of reason, which would
  14612. render this systematic unity not subjectively and logically--in its
  14613. character of a method, but objectively necessary.
  14614. We shall illustrate this by an example. The conceptions of the
  14615. understanding make us acquainted, among many other kinds of unity,
  14616. with that of the causality of a substance, which is termed power. The
  14617. different phenomenal manifestations of the same substance appear at
  14618. first view to be so very dissimilar that we are inclined to assume
  14619. the existence of just as many different powers as there are different
  14620. effects--as, in the case of the human mind, we have feeling,
  14621. consciousness, imagination, memory, wit, analysis, pleasure, desire
  14622. and so on. Now we are required by a logical maxim to reduce these
  14623. differences to as small a number as possible, by comparing them and
  14624. discovering the hidden identity which exists. We must inquire, for
  14625. example, whether or not imagination (connected with consciousness),
  14626. memory, wit, and analysis are not merely different forms of
  14627. understanding and reason. The idea of a fundamental power, the existence
  14628. of which no effort of logic can assure us of, is the problem to be
  14629. solved, for the systematic representation of the existing variety of
  14630. powers. The logical principle of reason requires us to produce as great
  14631. a unity as is possible in the system of our cognitions; and the more
  14632. the phenomena of this and the other power are found to be identical,
  14633. the more probable does it become, that they are nothing but different
  14634. manifestations of one and the same power, which may be called,
  14635. relatively speaking, a fundamental power. And so with other cases.
  14636. These relatively fundamental powers must again be compared with
  14637. each other, to discover, if possible, the one radical and absolutely
  14638. fundamental power of which they are but the manifestations. But this
  14639. unity is purely hypothetical. It is not maintained, that this unity does
  14640. really exist, but that we must, in the interest of reason, that is,
  14641. for the establishment of principles for the various rules presented by
  14642. experience, try to discover and introduce it, so far as is practicable,
  14643. into the sphere of our cognitions.
  14644. But the transcendental employment of the understanding would lead us to
  14645. believe that this idea of a fundamental power is not problematical, but
  14646. that it possesses objective reality, and thus the systematic unity
  14647. of the various powers or forces in a substance is demanded by the
  14648. understanding and erected into an apodeictic or necessary principle.
  14649. For, without having attempted to discover the unity of the various
  14650. powers existing in nature, nay, even after all our attempts have failed,
  14651. we notwithstanding presuppose that it does exist, and may be, sooner or
  14652. later, discovered. And this reason does, not only, as in the case
  14653. above adduced, with regard to the unity of substance, but where
  14654. many substances, although all to a certain extent homogeneous, are
  14655. discoverable, as in the case of matter in general. Here also does
  14656. reason presuppose the existence of the systematic unity of various
  14657. powers--inasmuch as particular laws of nature are subordinate to general
  14658. laws; and parsimony in principles is not merely an economical principle
  14659. of reason, but an essential law of nature.
  14660. We cannot understand, in fact, how a logical principle of unity can of
  14661. right exist, unless we presuppose a transcendental principle, by which
  14662. such a systematic unit--as a property of objects themselves--is regarded
  14663. as necessary a priori. For with what right can reason, in its logical
  14664. exercise, require us to regard the variety of forces which nature
  14665. displays, as in effect a disguised unity, and to deduce them from one
  14666. fundamental force or power, when she is free to admit that it is just
  14667. as possible that all forces should be different in kind, and that a
  14668. systematic unity is not conformable to the design of nature? In this
  14669. view of the case, reason would be proceeding in direct opposition to her
  14670. own destination, by setting as an aim an idea which entirely conflicts
  14671. with the procedure and arrangement of nature. Neither can we assert that
  14672. reason has previously inferred this unity from the contingent nature
  14673. of phenomena. For the law of reason which requires us to seek for this
  14674. unity is a necessary law, inasmuch as without it we should not possess
  14675. a faculty of reason, nor without reason a consistent and self-accordant
  14676. mode of employing the understanding, nor, in the absence of this, any
  14677. proper and sufficient criterion of empirical truth. In relation to this
  14678. criterion, therefore, we must suppose the idea of the systematic unity
  14679. of nature to possess objective validity and necessity.
  14680. We find this transcendental presupposition lurking in different forms in
  14681. the principles of philosophers, although they have neither recognized
  14682. it nor confessed to themselves its presence. That the diversities of
  14683. individual things do not exclude identity of species, that the various
  14684. species must be considered as merely different determinations of a
  14685. few genera, and these again as divisions of still higher races, and
  14686. so on--that, accordingly, a certain systematic unity of all possible
  14687. empirical conceptions, in so far as they can be deduced from higher and
  14688. more general conceptions, must be sought for, is a scholastic maxim or
  14689. logical principle, without which reason could not be employed by us. For
  14690. we can infer the particular from the general, only in so far as general
  14691. properties of things constitute the foundation upon which the particular
  14692. rest.
  14693. That the same unity exists in nature is presupposed by philosophers
  14694. in the well-known scholastic maxim, which forbids us unnecessarily to
  14695. augment the number of entities or principles (entia praeter necessitatem
  14696. non esse multiplicanda). This maxim asserts that nature herself assists
  14697. in the establishment of this unity of reason, and that the seemingly
  14698. infinite diversity of phenomena should not deter us from the expectation
  14699. of discovering beneath this diversity a unity of fundamental properties,
  14700. of which the aforesaid variety is but a more or less determined form.
  14701. This unity, although a mere idea, thinkers have found it necessary
  14702. rather to moderate the desire than to encourage it. It was considered
  14703. a great step when chemists were able to reduce all salts to two main
  14704. genera--acids and alkalis; and they regard this difference as itself a
  14705. mere variety, or different manifestation of one and the same fundamental
  14706. material. The different kinds of earths (stones and even metals)
  14707. chemists have endeavoured to reduce to three, and afterwards to two; but
  14708. still, not content with this advance, they cannot but think that behind
  14709. these diversities there lurks but one genus--nay, that even salts and
  14710. earths have a common principle. It might be conjectured that this is
  14711. merely an economical plan of reason, for the purpose of sparing itself
  14712. trouble, and an attempt of a purely hypothetical character, which,
  14713. when successful, gives an appearance of probability to the principle of
  14714. explanation employed by the reason. But a selfish purpose of this kind
  14715. is easily to be distinguished from the idea, according to which every
  14716. one presupposes that this unity is in accordance with the laws of
  14717. nature, and that reason does not in this case request, but requires,
  14718. although we are quite unable to determine the proper limits of this
  14719. unity.
  14720. If the diversity existing in phenomena--a diversity not of form (for
  14721. in this they may be similar) but of content--were so great that the
  14722. subtlest human reason could never by comparison discover in them the
  14723. least similarity (which is not impossible), in this case the logical law
  14724. of genera would be without foundation, the conception of a genus, nay,
  14725. all general conceptions would be impossible, and the faculty of the
  14726. understanding, the exercise of which is restricted to the world
  14727. of conceptions, could not exist. The logical principle of genera,
  14728. accordingly, if it is to be applied to nature (by which I mean objects
  14729. presented to our senses), presupposes a transcendental principle. In
  14730. accordance with this principle, homogeneity is necessarily presupposed
  14731. in the variety of phenomena (although we are unable to determine a
  14732. priori the degree of this homogeneity), because without it no empirical
  14733. conceptions, and consequently no experience, would be possible.
  14734. The logical principle of genera, which demands identity in phenomena, is
  14735. balanced by another principle--that of species, which requires variety
  14736. and diversity in things, notwithstanding their accordance in the same
  14737. genus, and directs the understanding to attend to the one no less than
  14738. to the other. This principle (of the faculty of distinction) acts as a
  14739. check upon the reason and reason exhibits in this respect a double and
  14740. conflicting interest--on the one hand, the interest in the extent (the
  14741. interest of generality) in relation to genera; on the other, that of the
  14742. content (the interest of individuality) in relation to the variety of
  14743. species. In the former case, the understanding cogitates more under its
  14744. conceptions, in the latter it cogitates more in them. This distinction
  14745. manifests itself likewise in the habits of thought peculiar to natural
  14746. philosophers, some of whom--the remarkably speculative heads--may be
  14747. said to be hostile to heterogeneity in phenomena, and have their
  14748. eyes always fixed on the unity of genera, while others--with a strong
  14749. empirical tendency--aim unceasingly at the analysis of phenomena,
  14750. and almost destroy in us the hope of ever being able to estimate the
  14751. character of these according to general principles.
  14752. The latter mode of thought is evidently based upon a logical principle,
  14753. the aim of which is the systematic completeness of all cognitions.
  14754. This principle authorizes me, beginning at the genus, to descend to the
  14755. various and diverse contained under it; and in this way extension, as
  14756. in the former case unity, is assured to the system. For if we merely
  14757. examine the sphere of the conception which indicates a genus, we cannot
  14758. discover how far it is possible to proceed in the division of that
  14759. sphere; just as it is impossible, from the consideration of the space
  14760. occupied by matter, to determine how far we can proceed in the division
  14761. of it. Hence every genus must contain different species, and these again
  14762. different subspecies; and as each of the latter must itself contain a
  14763. sphere (must be of a certain extent, as a conceptus communis), reason
  14764. demands that no species or sub-species is to be considered as the lowest
  14765. possible. For a species or sub-species, being always a conception, which
  14766. contains only what is common to a number of different things, does not
  14767. completely determine any individual thing, or relate immediately to
  14768. it, and must consequently contain other conceptions, that is, other
  14769. sub-species under it. This law of specification may be thus expressed:
  14770. entium varietates non temere sunt minuendae.
  14771. But it is easy to see that this logical law would likewise be without
  14772. sense or application, were it not based upon a transcendental law of
  14773. specification, which certainly does not require that the differences
  14774. existing phenomena should be infinite in number, for the logical
  14775. principle, which merely maintains the indeterminateness of the logical
  14776. sphere of a conception, in relation to its possible division, does not
  14777. authorize this statement; while it does impose upon the understanding
  14778. the duty of searching for subspecies to every species, and minor
  14779. differences in every difference. For, were there no lower conceptions,
  14780. neither could there be any higher. Now the understanding cognizes only
  14781. by means of conceptions; consequently, how far soever it may proceed
  14782. in division, never by mere intuition, but always by lower and lower
  14783. conceptions. The cognition of phenomena in their complete determination
  14784. (which is possible only by means of the understanding) requires an
  14785. unceasingly continued specification of conceptions, and a progression
  14786. to ever smaller differences, of which abstraction bad been made in the
  14787. conception of the species, and still more in that of the genus.
  14788. This law of specification cannot be deduced from experience; it can
  14789. never present us with a principle of so universal an application.
  14790. Empirical specification very soon stops in its distinction of
  14791. diversities, and requires the guidance of the transcendental law, as
  14792. a principle of the reason--a law which imposes on us the necessity of
  14793. never ceasing in our search for differences, even although these may not
  14794. present themselves to the senses. That absorbent earths are of different
  14795. kinds could only be discovered by obeying the anticipatory law of
  14796. reason, which imposes upon the understanding the task of discovering the
  14797. differences existing between these earths, and supposes that nature is
  14798. richer in substances than our senses would indicate. The faculty of the
  14799. understanding belongs to us just as much under the presupposition of
  14800. differences in the objects of nature, as under the condition that these
  14801. objects are homogeneous, because we could not possess conceptions, nor
  14802. make any use of our understanding, were not the phenomena included under
  14803. these conceptions in some respects dissimilar, as well as similar, in
  14804. their character.
  14805. Reason thus prepares the sphere of the understanding for the operations
  14806. of this faculty: 1. By the principle of the homogeneity of the diverse
  14807. in higher genera; 2. By the principle of the variety of the homogeneous
  14808. in lower species; and, to complete the systematic unity, it adds, 3.
  14809. A law of the affinity of all conceptions which prescribes a continuous
  14810. transition from one species to every other by the gradual increase of
  14811. diversity. We may term these the principles of the homogeneity, the
  14812. specification, and the continuity of forms. The latter results from the
  14813. union of the two former, inasmuch as we regard the systematic connection
  14814. as complete in thought, in the ascent to higher genera, as well as in
  14815. the descent to lower species. For all diversities must be related
  14816. to each other, as they all spring from one highest genus, descending
  14817. through the different gradations of a more and more extended
  14818. determination.
  14819. We may illustrate the systematic unity produced by the three logical
  14820. principles in the following manner. Every conception may be regarded as
  14821. a point, which, as the standpoint of a spectator, has a certain horizon,
  14822. which may be said to enclose a number of things that may be viewed,
  14823. so to speak, from that centre. Within this horizon there must be an
  14824. infinite number of other points, each of which has its own horizon,
  14825. smaller and more circumscribed; in other words, every species contains
  14826. sub-species, according to the principle of specification, and the
  14827. logical horizon consists of smaller horizons (subspecies), but not of
  14828. points (individuals), which possess no extent. But different horizons
  14829. or genera, which include under them so many conceptions, may have one
  14830. common horizon, from which, as from a mid-point, they may be surveyed;
  14831. and we may proceed thus, till we arrive at the highest genus, or
  14832. universal and true horizon, which is determined by the highest
  14833. conception, and which contains under itself all differences and
  14834. varieties, as genera, species, and subspecies.
  14835. To this highest standpoint I am conducted by the law of homogeneity,
  14836. as to all lower and more variously-determined conceptions by the law
  14837. of specification. Now as in this way there exists no void in the whole
  14838. extent of all possible conceptions, and as out of the sphere of these
  14839. the mind can discover nothing, there arises from the presupposition of
  14840. the universal horizon above mentioned, and its complete division, the
  14841. principle: Non datur vacuum formarum. This principle asserts that there
  14842. are not different primitive and highest genera, which stand isolated, so
  14843. to speak, from each other, but all the various genera are mere divisions
  14844. and limitations of one highest and universal genus; and hence follows
  14845. immediately the principle: Datur continuum formarum. This principle
  14846. indicates that all differences of species limit each other, and do not
  14847. admit of transition from one to another by a saltus, but only through
  14848. smaller degrees of the difference between the one species and the other.
  14849. In one word, there are no species or sub-species which (in the view of
  14850. reason) are the nearest possible to each other; intermediate species or
  14851. sub-species being always possible, the difference of which from each of
  14852. the former is always smaller than the difference existing between these.
  14853. The first law, therefore, directs us to avoid the notion that there
  14854. exist different primal genera, and enounces the fact of perfect
  14855. homogeneity; the second imposes a check upon this tendency to unity and
  14856. prescribes the distinction of sub-species, before proceeding to apply
  14857. our general conceptions to individuals. The third unites both the
  14858. former, by enouncing the fact of homogeneity as existing even in the
  14859. most various diversity, by means of the gradual transition from one
  14860. species to another. Thus it indicates a relationship between the
  14861. different branches or species, in so far as they all spring from the
  14862. same stem.
  14863. But this logical law of the continuum specierum (formarum logicarum)
  14864. presupposes a transcendental principle (lex continui in natura), without
  14865. which the understanding might be led into error, by following the
  14866. guidance of the former, and thus perhaps pursuing a path contrary to
  14867. that prescribed by nature. This law must, consequently, be based upon
  14868. pure transcendental, and not upon empirical, considerations. For, in the
  14869. latter case, it would come later than the system; whereas it is really
  14870. itself the parent of all that is systematic in our cognition of nature.
  14871. These principles are not mere hypotheses employed for the purpose
  14872. of experimenting upon nature; although when any such connection is
  14873. discovered, it forms a solid ground for regarding the hypothetical unity
  14874. as valid in the sphere of nature--and thus they are in this respect not
  14875. without their use. But we go farther, and maintain that it is manifest
  14876. that these principles of parsimony in fundamental causes, variety in
  14877. effects, and affinity in phenomena, are in accordance both with reason
  14878. and nature, and that they are not mere methods or plans devised for the
  14879. purpose of assisting us in our observation of the external world.
  14880. But it is plain that this continuity of forms is a mere idea, to which
  14881. no adequate object can be discovered in experience. And this for two
  14882. reasons. First, because the species in nature are really divided, and
  14883. hence form quanta discreta; and, if the gradual progression through
  14884. their affinity were continuous, the intermediate members lying between
  14885. two given species must be infinite in number, which is impossible.
  14886. Secondly, because we cannot make any determinate empirical use of this
  14887. law, inasmuch as it does not present us with any criterion of affinity
  14888. which could aid us in determining how far we ought to pursue the
  14889. graduation of differences: it merely contains a general indication that
  14890. it is our duty to seek for and, if possible, to discover them.
  14891. When we arrange these principles of systematic unity in the order
  14892. conformable to their employment in experience, they will stand thus:
  14893. Variety, Affinity, Unity, each of them, as ideas, being taken in the
  14894. highest degree of their completeness. Reason presupposes the existence
  14895. of cognitions of the understanding, which have a direct relation to
  14896. experience, and aims at the ideal unity of these cognitions--a unity
  14897. which far transcends all experience or empirical notions. The affinity
  14898. of the diverse, notwithstanding the differences existing between its
  14899. parts, has a relation to things, but a still closer one to the mere
  14900. properties and powers of things. For example, imperfect experience
  14901. may represent the orbits of the planets as circular. But we discover
  14902. variations from this course, and we proceed to suppose that the planets
  14903. revolve in a path which, if not a circle, is of a character very similar
  14904. to it. That is to say, the movements of those planets which do not form
  14905. a circle will approximate more or less to the properties of a circle,
  14906. and probably form an ellipse. The paths of comets exhibit still greater
  14907. variations, for, so far as our observation extends, they do not return
  14908. upon their own course in a circle or ellipse. But we proceed to the
  14909. conjecture that comets describe a parabola, a figure which is closely
  14910. allied to the ellipse. In fact, a parabola is merely an ellipse, with
  14911. its longer axis produced to an indefinite extent. Thus these principles
  14912. conduct us to a unity in the genera of the forms of these orbits, and,
  14913. proceeding farther, to a unity as regards the cause of the motions of
  14914. the heavenly bodies--that is, gravitation. But we go on extending our
  14915. conquests over nature, and endeavour to explain all seeming deviations
  14916. from these rules, and even make additions to our system which no
  14917. experience can ever substantiate--for example, the theory, in affinity
  14918. with that of ellipses, of hyperbolic paths of comets, pursuing which,
  14919. these bodies leave our solar system and, passing from sun to sun, unite
  14920. the most distant parts of the infinite universe, which is held together
  14921. by the same moving power.
  14922. The most remarkable circumstance connected with these principles is that
  14923. they seem to be transcendental, and, although only containing ideas
  14924. for the guidance of the empirical exercise of reason, and although this
  14925. empirical employment stands to these ideas in an asymptotic relation
  14926. alone (to use a mathematical term), that is, continually
  14927. approximate, without ever being able to attain to them, they possess,
  14928. notwithstanding, as a priori synthetical propositions, objective
  14929. though undetermined validity, and are available as rules for possible
  14930. experience. In the elaboration of our experience, they may also be
  14931. employed with great advantage, as heuristic [Footnote: From the Greek,
  14932. eurhioko.] principles. A transcendental deduction of them cannot be
  14933. made; such a deduction being always impossible in the case of ideas, as
  14934. has been already shown.
  14935. We distinguished, in the Transcendental Analytic, the dynamical
  14936. principles of the understanding, which are regulative principles of
  14937. intuition, from the mathematical, which are constitutive principles of
  14938. intuition. These dynamical laws are, however, constitutive in relation
  14939. to experience, inasmuch as they render the conceptions without which
  14940. experience could not exist possible a priori. But the principles of pure
  14941. reason cannot be constitutive even in regard to empirical conceptions,
  14942. because no sensuous schema corresponding to them can be discovered, and
  14943. they cannot therefore have an object in concreto. Now, if I grant that
  14944. they cannot be employed in the sphere of experience, as constitutive
  14945. principles, how shall I secure for them employment and objective
  14946. validity as regulative principles, and in what way can they be so
  14947. employed?
  14948. The understanding is the object of reason, as sensibility is the object
  14949. of the understanding. The production of systematic unity in all the
  14950. empirical operations of the understanding is the proper occupation of
  14951. reason; just as it is the business of the understanding to connect the
  14952. various content of phenomena by means of conceptions, and subject them
  14953. to empirical laws. But the operations of the understanding are, without
  14954. the schemata of sensibility, undetermined; and, in the same manner,
  14955. the unity of reason is perfectly undetermined as regards the conditions
  14956. under which, and the extent to which, the understanding ought to carry
  14957. the systematic connection of its conceptions. But, although it is
  14958. impossible to discover in intuition a schema for the complete systematic
  14959. unity of all the conceptions of the understanding, there must be some
  14960. analogon of this schema. This analogon is the idea of the maximum of the
  14961. division and the connection of our cognition in one principle. For we
  14962. may have a determinate notion of a maximum and an absolutely perfect,
  14963. all the restrictive conditions which are connected with an indeterminate
  14964. and various content having been abstracted. Thus the idea of reason
  14965. is analogous with a sensuous schema, with this difference, that the
  14966. application of the categories to the schema of reason does not present
  14967. a cognition of any object (as is the case with the application of the
  14968. categories to sensuous schemata), but merely provides us with a rule or
  14969. principle for the systematic unity of the exercise of the understanding.
  14970. Now, as every principle which imposes upon the exercise of the
  14971. understanding a priori compliance with the rule of systematic unity
  14972. also relates, although only in an indirect manner, to an object of
  14973. experience, the principles of pure reason will also possess objective
  14974. reality and validity in relation to experience. But they will not aim at
  14975. determining our knowledge in regard to any empirical object; they
  14976. will merely indicate the procedure, following which the empirical and
  14977. determinate exercise of the understanding may be in complete harmony and
  14978. connection with itself--a result which is produced by its being brought
  14979. into harmony with the principle of systematic unity, so far as that is
  14980. possible, and deduced from it.
  14981. I term all subjective principles, which are not derived from observation
  14982. of the constitution of an object, but from the interest which Reason
  14983. has in producing a certain completeness in her cognition of that object,
  14984. maxims of reason. Thus there are maxims of speculative reason, which are
  14985. based solely upon its speculative interest, although they appear to be
  14986. objective principles.
  14987. When principles which are really regulative are regarded as
  14988. constitutive, and employed as objective principles, contradictions must
  14989. arise; but if they are considered as mere maxims, there is no room for
  14990. contradictions of any kind, as they then merely indicate the different
  14991. interests of reason, which occasion differences in the mode of thought.
  14992. In effect, Reason has only one single interest, and the seeming
  14993. contradiction existing between her maxims merely indicates a difference
  14994. in, and a reciprocal limitation of, the methods by which this interest
  14995. is satisfied.
  14996. This reasoner has at heart the interest of diversity--in accordance
  14997. with the principle of specification; another, the interest of unity--in
  14998. accordance with the principle of aggregation. Each believes that
  14999. his judgement rests upon a thorough insight into the subject he is
  15000. examining, and yet it has been influenced solely by a greater or less
  15001. degree of adherence to some one of the two principles, neither of which
  15002. are objective, but originate solely from the interest of reason, and on
  15003. this account to be termed maxims rather than principles. When I observe
  15004. intelligent men disputing about the distinctive characteristics of men,
  15005. animals, or plants, and even of minerals, those on the one side assuming
  15006. the existence of certain national characteristics, certain well-defined
  15007. and hereditary distinctions of family, race, and so on, while the other
  15008. side maintain that nature has endowed all races of men with the same
  15009. faculties and dispositions, and that all differences are but the result
  15010. of external and accidental circumstances--I have only to consider for
  15011. a moment the real nature of the subject of discussion, to arrive at the
  15012. conclusion that it is a subject far too deep for us to judge of, and
  15013. that there is little probability of either party being able to speak
  15014. from a perfect insight into and understanding of the nature of the
  15015. subject itself. Both have, in reality, been struggling for the twofold
  15016. interest of reason; the one maintaining the one interest, the other the
  15017. other. But this difference between the maxims of diversity and unity
  15018. may easily be reconciled and adjusted; although, so long as they
  15019. are regarded as objective principles, they must occasion not only
  15020. contradictions and polemic, but place hinderances in the way of the
  15021. advancement of truth, until some means is discovered of reconciling
  15022. these conflicting interests, and bringing reason into union and harmony
  15023. with itself.
  15024. The same is the case with the so-called law discovered by Leibnitz, and
  15025. supported with remarkable ability by Bonnet--the law of the continuous
  15026. gradation of created beings, which is nothing more than an inference
  15027. from the principle of affinity; for observation and study of the order
  15028. of nature could never present it to the mind as an objective truth. The
  15029. steps of this ladder, as they appear in experience, are too far apart
  15030. from each other, and the so-called petty differences between different
  15031. kinds of animals are in nature commonly so wide separations that no
  15032. confidence can be placed in such views (particularly when we reflect
  15033. on the great variety of things, and the ease with which we can discover
  15034. resemblances), and no faith in the laws which are said to express
  15035. the aims and purposes of nature. On the other hand, the method of
  15036. investigating the order of nature in the light of this principle,
  15037. and the maxim which requires us to regard this order--it being still
  15038. undetermined how far it extends--as really existing in nature, is beyond
  15039. doubt a legitimate and excellent principle of reason--a principle which
  15040. extends farther than any experience or observation of ours and which,
  15041. without giving us any positive knowledge of anything in the region of
  15042. experience, guides us to the goal of systematic unity.
  15043. Of the Ultimate End of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason.
  15044. The ideas of pure reason cannot be, of themselves and in their own
  15045. nature, dialectical; it is from their misemployment alone that fallacies
  15046. and illusions arise. For they originate in the nature of reason itself,
  15047. and it is impossible that this supreme tribunal for all the rights and
  15048. claims of speculation should be itself undeserving of confidence and
  15049. promotive of error. It is to be expected, therefore, that these ideas
  15050. have a genuine and legitimate aim. It is true, the mob of sophists raise
  15051. against reason the cry of inconsistency and contradiction, and affect to
  15052. despise the government of that faculty, because they cannot understand
  15053. its constitution, while it is to its beneficial influences alone
  15054. that they owe the position and the intelligence which enable them to
  15055. criticize and to blame its procedure.
  15056. We cannot employ an a priori conception with certainty, until we have
  15057. made a transcendental deduction therefore. The ideas of pure reason do
  15058. not admit of the same kind of deduction as the categories. But if they
  15059. are to possess the least objective validity, and to represent anything
  15060. but mere creations of thought (entia rationis ratiocinantis), a
  15061. deduction of them must be possible. This deduction will complete the
  15062. critical task imposed upon pure reason; and it is to this part Of our
  15063. labours that we now proceed.
  15064. There is a great difference between a thing's being presented to the
  15065. mind as an object in an absolute sense, or merely as an ideal object. In
  15066. the former case I employ my conceptions to determine the object; in the
  15067. latter case nothing is present to the mind but a mere schema, which does
  15068. not relate directly to an object, not even in a hypothetical sense, but
  15069. which is useful only for the purpose of representing other objects to
  15070. the mind, in a mediate and indirect manner, by means of their relation
  15071. to the idea in the intellect. Thus I say the conception of a supreme
  15072. intelligence is a mere idea; that is to say, its objective reality does
  15073. not consist in the fact that it has an immediate relation to an object
  15074. (for in this sense we have no means of establishing its objective
  15075. validity), it is merely a schema constructed according to the necessary
  15076. conditions of the unity of reason--the schema of a thing in general,
  15077. which is useful towards the production of the highest degree of
  15078. systematic unity in the empirical exercise of reason, in which we deduce
  15079. this or that object of experience from the imaginary object of this
  15080. idea, as the ground or cause of the said object of experience. In this
  15081. way, the idea is properly a heuristic, and not an ostensive, conception;
  15082. it does not give us any information respecting the constitution of an
  15083. object, it merely indicates how, under the guidance of the idea, we
  15084. ought to investigate the constitution and the relations of objects in
  15085. the world of experience. Now, if it can be shown that the three kinds
  15086. of transcendental ideas (psychological, cosmological, and theological),
  15087. although not relating directly to any object nor determining it, do
  15088. nevertheless, on the supposition of the existence of an ideal object,
  15089. produce systematic unity in the laws of the empirical employment of
  15090. the reason, and extend our empirical cognition, without ever being
  15091. inconsistent or in opposition with it--it must be a necessary maxim
  15092. of reason to regulate its procedure according to these ideas. And this
  15093. forms the transcendental deduction of all speculative ideas, not as
  15094. constitutive principles of the extension of our cognition beyond the
  15095. limits of our experience, but as regulative principles of the systematic
  15096. unity of empirical cognition, which is by the aid of these ideas
  15097. arranged and emended within its own proper limits, to an extent
  15098. unattainable by the operation of the principles of the understanding
  15099. alone.
  15100. I shall make this plainer. Guided by the principles involved in these
  15101. ideas, we must, in the first place, so connect all the phenomena,
  15102. actions, and feelings of the mind, as if it were a simple substance,
  15103. which, endowed with personal identity, possesses a permanent existence
  15104. (in this life at least), while its states, among which those of the
  15105. body are to be included as external conditions, are in continual change.
  15106. Secondly, in cosmology, we must investigate the conditions of all
  15107. natural phenomena, internal as well as external, as if they belonged to
  15108. a chain infinite and without any prime or supreme member, while we do
  15109. not, on this account, deny the existence of intelligible grounds of
  15110. these phenomena, although we never employ them to explain phenomena, for
  15111. the simple reason that they are not objects of our cognition. Thirdly,
  15112. in the sphere of theology, we must regard the whole system of
  15113. possible experience as forming an absolute, but dependent and
  15114. sensuously-conditioned unity, and at the same time as based upon a
  15115. sole, supreme, and all-sufficient ground existing apart from the world
  15116. itself--a ground which is a self-subsistent, primeval and creative
  15117. reason, in relation to which we so employ our reason in the field of
  15118. experience, as if all objects drew their origin from that archetype
  15119. of all reason. In other words, we ought not to deduce the internal
  15120. phenomena of the mind from a simple thinking substance, but deduce them
  15121. from each other under the guidance of the regulative idea of a simple
  15122. being; we ought not to deduce the phenomena, order, and unity of the
  15123. universe from a supreme intelligence, but merely draw from this idea
  15124. of a supremely wise cause the rules which must guide reason in its
  15125. connection of causes and effects.
  15126. Now there is nothing to hinder us from admitting these ideas to possess
  15127. an objective and hyperbolic existence, except the cosmological ideas,
  15128. which lead reason into an antinomy: the psychological and theological
  15129. ideas are not antinomial. They contain no contradiction; and how, then,
  15130. can any one dispute their objective reality, since he who denies it
  15131. knows as little about their possibility as we who affirm? And yet,
  15132. when we wish to admit the existence of a thing, it is not sufficient to
  15133. convince ourselves that there is no positive obstacle in the way; for
  15134. it cannot be allowable to regard mere creations of thought, which
  15135. transcend, though they do not contradict, all our conceptions, as real
  15136. and determinate objects, solely upon the authority of a speculative
  15137. reason striving to compass its own aims. They cannot, therefore, be
  15138. admitted to be real in themselves; they can only possess a comparative
  15139. reality--that of a schema of the regulative principle of the systematic
  15140. unity of all cognition. They are to be regarded not as actual things,
  15141. but as in some measure analogous to them. We abstract from the object
  15142. of the idea all the conditions which limit the exercise of our
  15143. understanding, but which, on the other hand, are the sole conditions of
  15144. our possessing a determinate conception of any given thing. And thus we
  15145. cogitate a something, of the real nature of which we have not the
  15146. least conception, but which we represent to ourselves as standing in a
  15147. relation to the whole system of phenomena, analogous to that in which
  15148. phenomena stand to each other.
  15149. By admitting these ideal beings, we do not really extend our cognitions
  15150. beyond the objects of possible experience; we extend merely the
  15151. empirical unity of our experience, by the aid of systematic unity, the
  15152. schema of which is furnished by the idea, which is therefore valid--not
  15153. as a constitutive, but as a regulative principle. For although we posit
  15154. a thing corresponding to the idea--a something, an actual existence--we
  15155. do not on that account aim at the extension of our cognition by means
  15156. of transcendent conceptions. This existence is purely ideal, and not
  15157. objective; it is the mere expression of the systematic unity which is to
  15158. be the guide of reason in the field of experience. There are no attempts
  15159. made at deciding what the ground of this unity may be, or what the real
  15160. nature of this imaginary being.
  15161. Thus the transcendental and only determinate conception of God, which
  15162. is presented to us by speculative reason, is in the strictest sense
  15163. deistic. In other words, reason does not assure us of the objective
  15164. validity of the conception; it merely gives us the idea of something, on
  15165. which the supreme and necessary unity of all experience is based. This
  15166. something we cannot, following the analogy of a real substance, cogitate
  15167. otherwise than as the cause of all things operating in accordance with
  15168. rational laws, if we regard it as an individual object; although we
  15169. should rest contented with the idea alone as a regulative principle
  15170. of reason, and make no attempt at completing the sum of the conditions
  15171. imposed by thought. This attempt is, indeed, inconsistent with the grand
  15172. aim of complete systematic unity in the sphere of cognition--a unity to
  15173. which no bounds are set by reason.
  15174. Hence it happens that, admitting a divine being, I can have no
  15175. conception of the internal possibility of its perfection, or of the
  15176. necessity of its existence. The only advantage of this admission is that
  15177. it enables me to answer all other questions relating to the contingent,
  15178. and to give reason the most complete satisfaction as regards the unity
  15179. which it aims at attaining in the world of experience. But I cannot
  15180. satisfy reason with regard to this hypothesis itself; and this proves
  15181. that it is not its intelligence and insight into the subject, but its
  15182. speculative interest alone which induces it to proceed from a point
  15183. lying far beyond the sphere of our cognition, for the purpose of being
  15184. able to consider all objects as parts of a systematic whole.
  15185. Here a distinction presents itself, in regard to the way in which we may
  15186. cogitate a presupposition--a distinction which is somewhat subtle, but
  15187. of great importance in transcendental philosophy. I may have sufficient
  15188. grounds to admit something, or the existence of something, in a
  15189. relative point of view (suppositio relativa), without being justified
  15190. in admitting it in an absolute sense (suppositio absoluta). This
  15191. distinction is undoubtedly requisite, in the case of a regulative
  15192. principle, the necessity of which we recognize, though we are ignorant
  15193. of the source and cause of that necessity, and which we assume to
  15194. be based upon some ultimate ground, for the purpose of being able to
  15195. cogitate the universality of the principle in a more determinate way.
  15196. For example, I cogitate the existence of a being corresponding to a
  15197. pure transcendental idea. But I cannot admit that this being exists
  15198. absolutely and in itself, because all of the conceptions by which I can
  15199. cogitate an object in a determinate manner fall short of assuring me
  15200. of its existence; nay, the conditions of the objective validity of my
  15201. conceptions are excluded by the idea--by the very fact of its being an
  15202. idea. The conceptions of reality, substance, causality, nay, even that
  15203. of necessity in existence, have no significance out of the sphere of
  15204. empirical cognition, and cannot, beyond that sphere, determine any
  15205. object. They may, accordingly, be employed to explain the possibility of
  15206. things in the world of sense, but they are utterly inadequate to explain
  15207. the possibility of the universe itself considered as a whole; because
  15208. in this case the ground of explanation must lie out of and beyond the
  15209. world, and cannot, therefore, be an object of possible experience.
  15210. Now, I may admit the existence of an incomprehensible being of this
  15211. nature--the object of a mere idea, relatively to the world of sense;
  15212. although I have no ground to admit its existence absolutely and in
  15213. itself. For if an idea (that of a systematic and complete unity, of
  15214. which I shall presently speak more particularly) lies at the foundation
  15215. of the most extended empirical employment of reason, and if this
  15216. idea cannot be adequately represented in concreto, although it is
  15217. indispensably necessary for the approximation of empirical unity to the
  15218. highest possible degree--I am not only authorized, but compelled,
  15219. to realize this idea, that is, to posit a real object corresponding
  15220. thereto. But I cannot profess to know this object; it is to me merely a
  15221. something, to which, as the ground of systematic unity in cognition, I
  15222. attribute such properties as are analogous to the conceptions employed
  15223. by the understanding in the sphere of experience. Following the analogy
  15224. of the notions of reality, substance, causality, and necessity, I
  15225. cogitate a being, which possesses all these attributes in the highest
  15226. degree; and, as this idea is the offspring of my reason alone, I
  15227. cogitate this being as self-subsistent reason, and as the cause of the
  15228. universe operating by means of ideas of the greatest possible harmony
  15229. and unity. Thus I abstract all conditions that would limit my idea,
  15230. solely for the purpose of rendering systematic unity possible in the
  15231. world of empirical diversity, and thus securing the widest possible
  15232. extension for the exercise of reason in that sphere. This I am enabled
  15233. to do, by regarding all connections and relations in the world of sense,
  15234. as if they were the dispositions of a supreme reason, of which our
  15235. reason is but a faint image. I then proceed to cogitate this Supreme
  15236. Being by conceptions which have, properly, no meaning or application,
  15237. except in the world of sense. But as I am authorized to employ the
  15238. transcendental hypothesis of such a being in a relative respect
  15239. alone, that is, as the substratum of the greatest possible unity in
  15240. experience--I may attribute to a being which I regard as distinct from
  15241. the world, such properties as belong solely to the sphere of sense and
  15242. experience. For I do not desire, and am not justified in desiring, to
  15243. cognize this object of my idea, as it exists in itself; for I possess
  15244. no conceptions sufficient for or task, those of reality, substance,
  15245. causality, nay, even that of necessity in existence, losing all
  15246. significance, and becoming merely the signs of conceptions, without
  15247. content and without applicability, when I attempt to carry them beyond
  15248. the limits of the world of sense. I cogitate merely the relation of a
  15249. perfectly unknown being to the greatest possible systematic unity of
  15250. experience, solely for the purpose of employing it as the schema of the
  15251. regulative principle which directs reason in its empirical exercise.
  15252. It is evident, at the first view, that we cannot presuppose the reality
  15253. of this transcendental object, by means of the conceptions of reality,
  15254. substance, causality, and so on, because these conceptions cannot be
  15255. applied to anything that is distinct from the world of sense. Thus
  15256. the supposition of a Supreme Being or cause is purely relative; it is
  15257. cogitated only in behalf of the systematic unity of experience; such a
  15258. being is but a something, of whose existence in itself we have not the
  15259. least conception. Thus, too, it becomes sufficiently manifest why we
  15260. required the idea of a necessary being in relation to objects given by
  15261. sense, although we can never have the least conception of this being, or
  15262. of its absolute necessity.
  15263. And now we can clearly perceive the result of our transcendental
  15264. dialectic, and the proper aim of the ideas of pure reason--which become
  15265. dialectical solely from misunderstanding and inconsiderateness. Pure
  15266. reason is, in fact, occupied with itself, and not with any object.
  15267. Objects are not presented to it to be embraced in the unity of an
  15268. empirical conception; it is only the cognitions of the understanding
  15269. that are presented to it, for the purpose of receiving the unity of
  15270. a rational conception, that is, of being connected according to
  15271. a principle. The unity of reason is the unity of system; and this
  15272. systematic unity is not an objective principle, extending its dominion
  15273. over objects, but a subjective maxim, extending its authority over the
  15274. empirical cognition of objects. The systematic connection which reason
  15275. gives to the empirical employment of the understanding not only advances
  15276. the extension of that employment, but ensures its correctness, and thus
  15277. the principle of a systematic unity of this nature is also objective,
  15278. although only in an indefinite respect (principium vagum). It is not,
  15279. however, a constitutive principle, determining an object to which
  15280. it directly relates; it is merely a regulative principle or maxim,
  15281. advancing and strengthening the empirical exercise of reason, by the
  15282. opening up of new paths of which the understanding is ignorant, while
  15283. it never conflicts with the laws of its exercise in the sphere of
  15284. experience.
  15285. But reason cannot cogitate this systematic unity, without at the
  15286. same time cogitating an object of the idea--an object that cannot be
  15287. presented in any experience, which contains no concrete example of a
  15288. complete systematic unity. This being (ens rationis ratiocinatae) is
  15289. therefore a mere idea and is not assumed to be a thing which is
  15290. real absolutely and in itself. On the contrary, it forms merely the
  15291. problematical foundation of the connection which the mind introduces
  15292. among the phenomena of the sensuous world. We look upon this connection,
  15293. in the light of the above-mentioned idea, as if it drew its origin from
  15294. the supposed being which corresponds to the idea. And yet all we aim at
  15295. is the possession of this idea as a secure foundation for the systematic
  15296. unity of experience--a unity indispensable to reason, advantageous
  15297. to the understanding, and promotive of the interests of empirical
  15298. cognition.
  15299. We mistake the true meaning of this idea when we regard it as an
  15300. enouncement, or even as a hypothetical declaration of the existence of
  15301. a real thing, which we are to regard as the origin or ground of a
  15302. systematic constitution of the universe. On the contrary, it is left
  15303. completely undetermined what the nature or properties of this so-called
  15304. ground may be. The idea is merely to be adopted as a point of view,
  15305. from which this unity, so essential to reason and so beneficial to
  15306. the understanding, may be regarded as radiating. In one word, this
  15307. transcendental thing is merely the schema of a regulative principle, by
  15308. means of which Reason, so far as in her lies, extends the dominion of
  15309. systematic unity over the whole sphere of experience.
  15310. The first object of an idea of this kind is the ego, considered merely
  15311. as a thinking nature or soul. If I wish to investigate the properties of
  15312. a thinking being, I must interrogate experience. But I find that I
  15313. can apply none of the categories to this object, the schema of these
  15314. categories, which is the condition of their application, being given
  15315. only in sensuous intuition. But I cannot thus attain to the cognition of
  15316. a systematic unity of all the phenomena of the internal sense. Instead,
  15317. therefore, of an empirical conception of what the soul really is, reason
  15318. takes the conception of the empirical unity of all thought, and, by
  15319. cogitating this unity as unconditioned and primitive, constructs the
  15320. rational conception or idea of a simple substance which is in itself
  15321. unchangeable, possessing personal identity, and in connection with other
  15322. real things external to it; in one word, it constructs the idea of a
  15323. simple self-subsistent intelligence. But the real aim of reason in this
  15324. procedure is the attainment of principles of systematic unity for the
  15325. explanation of the phenomena of the soul. That is, reason desires to
  15326. be able to represent all the determinations of the internal sense as
  15327. existing in one subject, all powers as deduced from one fundamental
  15328. power, all changes as mere varieties in the condition of a being which
  15329. is permanent and always the same, and all phenomena in space as entirely
  15330. different in their nature from the procedure of thought. Essential
  15331. simplicity (with the other attributes predicated of the ego) is regarded
  15332. as the mere schema of this regulative principle; it is not assumed
  15333. that it is the actual ground of the properties of the soul. For these
  15334. properties may rest upon quite different grounds, of which we are
  15335. completely ignorant; just as the above predicates could not give us any
  15336. knowledge of the soul as it is in itself, even if we regarded them as
  15337. valid in respect of it, inasmuch as they constitute a mere idea, which
  15338. cannot be represented in concreto. Nothing but good can result from
  15339. a psychological idea of this kind, if we only take proper care not to
  15340. consider it as more than an idea; that is, if we regard it as valid
  15341. merely in relation to the employment of reason, in the sphere of the
  15342. phenomena of the soul. Under the guidance of this idea, or principle,
  15343. no empirical laws of corporeal phenomena are called in to explain that
  15344. which is a phenomenon of the internal sense alone; no windy hypotheses
  15345. of the generation, annihilation, and palingenesis of souls are admitted.
  15346. Thus the consideration of this object of the internal sense is kept
  15347. pure, and unmixed with heterogeneous elements; while the investigation
  15348. of reason aims at reducing all the grounds of explanation employed
  15349. in this sphere of knowledge to a single principle. All this is best
  15350. effected, nay, cannot be effected otherwise than by means of such
  15351. a schema, which requires us to regard this ideal thing as an actual
  15352. existence. The psychological idea is, therefore, meaningless and
  15353. inapplicable, except as the schema of a regulative conception. For, if
  15354. I ask whether the soul is not really of a spiritual nature--it is
  15355. a question which has no meaning. From such a conception has been
  15356. abstracted, not merely all corporeal nature, but all nature, that is,
  15357. all the predicates of a possible experience; and consequently, all the
  15358. conditions which enable us to cogitate an object to this conception have
  15359. disappeared. But, if these conditions are absent, it is evident that the
  15360. conception is meaningless.
  15361. The second regulative idea of speculative reason is the conception of
  15362. the universe. For nature is properly the only object presented to us,
  15363. in regard to which reason requires regulative principles. Nature is
  15364. twofold--thinking and corporeal nature. To cogitate the latter in regard
  15365. to its internal possibility, that is, to determine the application
  15366. of the categories to it, no idea is required--no representation which
  15367. transcends experience. In this sphere, therefore, an idea is impossible,
  15368. sensuous intuition being our only guide; while, in the sphere of
  15369. psychology, we require the fundamental idea (I), which contains a priori
  15370. a certain form of thought namely, the unity of the ego. Pure reason has,
  15371. therefore, nothing left but nature in general, and the completeness of
  15372. conditions in nature in accordance with some principle. The absolute
  15373. totality of the series of these conditions is an idea, which can never
  15374. be fully realized in the empirical exercise of reason, while it is
  15375. serviceable as a rule for the procedure of reason in relation to that
  15376. totality. It requires us, in the explanation of given phenomena (in
  15377. the regress or ascent in the series), to proceed as if the series were
  15378. infinite in itself, that is, were prolonged in indefinitum; while on
  15379. the other hand, where reason is regarded as itself the determining cause
  15380. (in the region of freedom), we are required to proceed as if we had not
  15381. before us an object of sense, but of the pure understanding. In this
  15382. latter case, the conditions do not exist in the series of phenomena, but
  15383. may be placed quite out of and beyond it, and the series of conditions
  15384. may be regarded as if it had an absolute beginning from an intelligible
  15385. cause. All this proves that the cosmological ideas are nothing but
  15386. regulative principles, and not constitutive; and that their aim is not
  15387. to realize an actual totality in such series. The full discussion of
  15388. this subject will be found in its proper place in the chapter on the
  15389. antinomy of pure reason.
  15390. The third idea of pure reason, containing the hypothesis of a being
  15391. which is valid merely as a relative hypothesis, is that of the one and
  15392. all-sufficient cause of all cosmological series, in other words, the
  15393. idea of God. We have not the slightest ground absolutely to admit the
  15394. existence of an object corresponding to this idea; for what can empower
  15395. or authorize us to affirm the existence of a being of the highest
  15396. perfection--a being whose existence is absolutely necessary--merely
  15397. because we possess the conception of such a being? The answer is: It is
  15398. the existence of the world which renders this hypothesis necessary. But
  15399. this answer makes it perfectly evident that the idea of this being, like
  15400. all other speculative ideas, is essentially nothing more than a demand
  15401. upon reason that it shall regulate the connection which it and its
  15402. subordinate faculties introduce into the phenomena of the world by
  15403. principles of systematic unity and, consequently, that it shall regard
  15404. all phenomena as originating from one all-embracing being, as the
  15405. supreme and all-sufficient cause. From this it is plain that the only
  15406. aim of reason in this procedure is the establishment of its own formal
  15407. rule for the extension of its dominion in the world of experience; that
  15408. it does not aim at an extension of its cognition beyond the limits
  15409. of experience; and that, consequently, this idea does not contain any
  15410. constitutive principle.
  15411. The highest formal unity, which is based upon ideas alone, is the unity
  15412. of all things--a unity in accordance with an aim or purpose; and the
  15413. speculative interest of reason renders it necessary to regard all order
  15414. in the world as if it originated from the intention and design of a
  15415. supreme reason. This principle unfolds to the view of reason in the
  15416. sphere of experience new and enlarged prospects, and invites it to
  15417. connect the phenomena of the world according to teleological laws,
  15418. and in this way to attain to the highest possible degree of systematic
  15419. unity. The hypothesis of a supreme intelligence, as the sole cause of
  15420. the universe--an intelligence which has for us no more than an ideal
  15421. existence--is accordingly always of the greatest service to reason.
  15422. Thus, if we presuppose, in relation to the figure of the earth (which
  15423. is round, but somewhat flattened at the poles),* or that of mountains or
  15424. seas, wise designs on the part of an author of the universe, we cannot
  15425. fail to make, by the light of this supposition, a great number of
  15426. interesting discoveries. If we keep to this hypothesis, as a principle
  15427. which is purely regulative, even error cannot be very detrimental. For,
  15428. in this case, error can have no more serious consequences than that,
  15429. where we expected to discover a teleological connection (nexus finalis),
  15430. only a mechanical or physical connection appears. In such a case, we
  15431. merely fail to find the additional form of unity we expected, but we do
  15432. not lose the rational unity which the mind requires in its procedure in
  15433. experience. But even a miscarriage of this sort cannot affect the law in
  15434. its general and teleological relations. For although we may convict an
  15435. anatomist of an error, when he connects the limb of some animal with a
  15436. certain purpose, it is quite impossible to prove in a single case that
  15437. any arrangement of nature, be it what it may, is entirely without aim or
  15438. design. And thus medical physiology, by the aid of a principle presented
  15439. to it by pure reason, extends its very limited empirical knowledge of
  15440. the purposes of the different parts of an organized body so far that it
  15441. may be asserted with the utmost confidence, and with the approbation of
  15442. all reflecting men, that every organ or bodily part of an animal has its
  15443. use and answers a certain design. Now, this is a supposition which,
  15444. if regarded as of a constitutive character, goes much farther than any
  15445. experience or observation of ours can justify. Hence it is evident that
  15446. it is nothing more than a regulative principle of reason, which aims
  15447. at the highest degree of systematic unity, by the aid of the idea of
  15448. a causality according to design in a supreme cause--a cause which it
  15449. regards as the highest intelligence.
  15450. [*Footnote: The advantages which a circular form, in the case of the
  15451. earth, has over every other, are well known. But few are aware that the
  15452. slight flattening at the poles, which gives it the figure of a spheroid,
  15453. is the only cause which prevents the elevations of continents or even
  15454. of mountains, perhaps thrown up by some internal convulsion, from
  15455. continually altering the position of the axis of the earth--and that to
  15456. some considerable degree in a short time. The great protuberance of the
  15457. earth under the Equator serves to overbalance the impetus of all other
  15458. masses of earth, and thus to preserve the axis of the earth, so far as
  15459. we can observe, in its present position. And yet this wise arrangement
  15460. has been unthinkingly explained from the equilibrium of the formerly
  15461. fluid mass.]
  15462. If, however, we neglect this restriction of the idea to a purely
  15463. regulative influence, reason is betrayed into numerous errors. For it
  15464. has then left the ground of experience, in which alone are to be
  15465. found the criteria of truth, and has ventured into the region of the
  15466. incomprehensible and unsearchable, on the heights of which it loses
  15467. its power and collectedness, because it has completely severed its
  15468. connection with experience.
  15469. The first error which arises from our employing the idea of a Supreme
  15470. Being as a constitutive (in repugnance to the very nature of an idea),
  15471. and not as a regulative principle, is the error of inactive reason
  15472. (ignava ratio).* We may so term every principle which requires us to
  15473. regard our investigations of nature as absolutely complete, and allows
  15474. reason to cease its inquiries, as if it had fully executed its task.
  15475. Thus the psychological idea of the ego, when employed as a constitutive
  15476. principle for the explanation of the phenomena of the soul, and for the
  15477. extension of our knowledge regarding this subject beyond the limits of
  15478. experience--even to the condition of the soul after death--is convenient
  15479. enough for the purposes of pure reason, but detrimental and even ruinous
  15480. to its interests in the sphere of nature and experience. The dogmatizing
  15481. spiritualist explains the unchanging unity of our personality through
  15482. all changes of condition from the unity of a thinking substance, the
  15483. interest which we take in things and events that can happen only after
  15484. our death, from a consciousness of the immaterial nature of our thinking
  15485. subject, and so on. Thus he dispenses with all empirical investigations
  15486. into the cause of these internal phenomena, and with all possible
  15487. explanations of them upon purely natural grounds; while, at the
  15488. dictation of a transcendent reason, he passes by the immanent sources of
  15489. cognition in experience, greatly to his own ease and convenience, but
  15490. to the sacrifice of all, genuine insight and intelligence. These
  15491. prejudicial consequences become still more evident, in the case of the
  15492. dogmatical treatment of our idea of a Supreme Intelligence, and the
  15493. theological system of nature (physico-theology) which is falsely based
  15494. upon it. For, in this case, the aims which we observe in nature, and
  15495. often those which we merely fancy to exist, make the investigation
  15496. of causes a very easy task, by directing us to refer such and such
  15497. phenomena immediately to the unsearchable will and counsel of the
  15498. Supreme Wisdom, while we ought to investigate their causes in the
  15499. general laws of the mechanism of matter. We are thus recommended to
  15500. consider the labour of reason as ended, when we have merely dispensed
  15501. with its employment, which is guided surely and safely only by the order
  15502. of nature and the series of changes in the world--which are arranged
  15503. according to immanent and general laws. This error may be avoided, if we
  15504. do not merely consider from the view-point of final aims certain parts
  15505. of nature, such as the division and structure of a continent, the
  15506. constitution and direction of certain mountain-chains, or even the
  15507. organization existing in the vegetable and animal kingdoms, but look
  15508. upon this systematic unity of nature in a perfectly general way, in
  15509. relation to the idea of a Supreme Intelligence. If we pursue this
  15510. advice, we lay as a foundation for all investigation the conformity to
  15511. aims of all phenomena of nature in accordance with universal laws, for
  15512. which no particular arrangement of nature is exempt, but only cognized
  15513. by us with more or less difficulty; and we possess a regulative
  15514. principle of the systematic unity of a teleological connection, which we
  15515. do not attempt to anticipate or predetermine. All that we do, and ought
  15516. to do, is to follow out the physico-mechanical connection in nature
  15517. according to general laws, with the hope of discovering, sooner or
  15518. later, the teleological connection also. Thus, and thus only, can the
  15519. principle of final unity aid in the extension of the employment
  15520. of reason in the sphere of experience, without being in any case
  15521. detrimental to its interests.
  15522. [*Footnote: This was the term applied by the old dialecticians to a
  15523. sophistical argument, which ran thus: If it is your fate to die of this
  15524. disease, you will die, whether you employ a physician or not. Cicero
  15525. says that this mode of reasoning has received this appellation, because,
  15526. if followed, it puts an end to the employment of reason in the affairs
  15527. of life. For a similar reason, I have applied this designation to the
  15528. sophistical argument of pure reason.]
  15529. The second error which arises from the misconception of the principle
  15530. of systematic unity is that of perverted reason (perversa ratio, usteron
  15531. roteron rationis). The idea of systematic unity is available as a
  15532. regulative principle in the connection of phenomena according to general
  15533. natural laws; and, how far soever we have to travel upon the path of
  15534. experience to discover some fact or event, this idea requires us to
  15535. believe that we have approached all the more nearly to the completion of
  15536. its use in the sphere of nature, although that completion can never be
  15537. attained. But this error reverses the procedure of reason. We begin
  15538. by hypostatizing the principle of systematic unity, and by giving
  15539. an anthropomorphic determination to the conception of a Supreme
  15540. Intelligence, and then proceed forcibly to impose aims upon nature. Thus
  15541. not only does teleology, which ought to aid in the completion of unity
  15542. in accordance with general laws, operate to the destruction of its
  15543. influence, but it hinders reason from attaining its proper aim, that
  15544. is, the proof, upon natural grounds, of the existence of a supreme
  15545. intelligent cause. For, if we cannot presuppose supreme finality in
  15546. nature a priori, that is, as essentially belonging to nature, how can
  15547. we be directed to endeavour to discover this unity and, rising gradually
  15548. through its different degrees, to approach the supreme perfection of an
  15549. author of all--a perfection which is absolutely necessary, and therefore
  15550. cognizable a priori? The regulative principle directs us to presuppose
  15551. systematic unity absolutely and, consequently, as following from the
  15552. essential nature of things--but only as a unity of nature, not merely
  15553. cognized empirically, but presupposed a priori, although only in
  15554. an indeterminate manner. But if I insist on basing nature upon the
  15555. foundation of a supreme ordaining Being, the unity of nature is in
  15556. effect lost. For, in this case, it is quite foreign and unessential to
  15557. the nature of things, and cannot be cognized from the general laws of
  15558. nature. And thus arises a vicious circular argument, what ought to have
  15559. been proved having been presupposed.
  15560. To take the regulative principle of systematic unity in nature for a
  15561. constitutive principle, and to hypostatize and make a cause out of that
  15562. which is properly the ideal ground of the consistent and harmonious
  15563. exercise of reason, involves reason in inextricable embarrassments. The
  15564. investigation of nature pursues its own path under the guidance of the
  15565. chain of natural causes, in accordance with the general laws of nature,
  15566. and ever follows the light of the idea of an author of the universe--not
  15567. for the purpose of deducing the finality, which it constantly pursues,
  15568. from this Supreme Being, but to attain to the cognition of his existence
  15569. from the finality which it seeks in the existence of the phenomena of
  15570. nature, and, if possible, in that of all things to cognize this being,
  15571. consequently, as absolutely necessary. Whether this latter purpose
  15572. succeed or not, the idea is and must always be a true one, and its
  15573. employment, when merely regulative, must always be accompanied by
  15574. truthful and beneficial results.
  15575. Complete unity, in conformity with aims, constitutes absolute
  15576. perfection. But if we do not find this unity in the nature of the things
  15577. which go to constitute the world of experience, that is, of objective
  15578. cognition, consequently in the universal and necessary laws of nature,
  15579. how can we infer from this unity the idea of the supreme and absolutely
  15580. necessary perfection of a primal being, which is the origin of all
  15581. causality? The greatest systematic unity, and consequently teleological
  15582. unity, constitutes the very foundation of the possibility of the most
  15583. extended employment of human reason. The idea of unity is therefore
  15584. essentially and indissolubly connected with the nature of our reason.
  15585. This idea is a legislative one; and hence it is very natural that we
  15586. should assume the existence of a legislative reason corresponding to it,
  15587. from which the systematic unity of nature--the object of the operations
  15588. of reason--must be derived.
  15589. In the course of our discussion of the antinomies, we stated that it is
  15590. always possible to answer all the questions which pure reason may raise;
  15591. and that the plea of the limited nature of our cognition, which is
  15592. unavoidable and proper in many questions regarding natural phenomena,
  15593. cannot in this case be admitted, because the questions raised do not
  15594. relate to the nature of things, but are necessarily originated by the
  15595. nature of reason itself, and relate to its own internal constitution. We
  15596. can now establish this assertion, which at first sight appeared so rash,
  15597. in relation to the two questions in which reason takes the greatest
  15598. interest, and thus complete our discussion of the dialectic of pure
  15599. reason.
  15600. If, then, the question is asked, in relation to transcendental
  15601. theology,* first, whether there is anything distinct from the world,
  15602. which contains the ground of cosmical order and connection according
  15603. to general laws? The answer is: Certainly. For the world is a sum of
  15604. phenomena; there must, therefore, be some transcendental basis of these
  15605. phenomena, that is, a basis cogitable by the pure understanding alone.
  15606. If, secondly, the question is asked whether this being is substance,
  15607. whether it is of the greatest reality, whether it is necessary, and so
  15608. forth? I answer that this question is utterly without meaning. For all
  15609. the categories which aid me in forming a conception of an object cannot
  15610. be employed except in the world of sense, and are without meaning when
  15611. not applied to objects of actual or possible experience. Out of this
  15612. sphere, they are not properly conceptions, but the mere marks or indices
  15613. of conceptions, which we may admit, although they cannot, without the
  15614. help of experience, help us to understand any subject or thing. If,
  15615. thirdly, the question is whether we may not cogitate this being, which
  15616. is distinct from the world, in analogy with the objects of experience?
  15617. The answer is: Undoubtedly, but only as an ideal, and not as a real
  15618. object. That is, we must cogitate it only as an unknown substratum of
  15619. the systematic unity, order, and finality of the world--a unity which
  15620. reason must employ as the regulative principle of its investigation of
  15621. nature. Nay, more, we may admit into the idea certain anthropomorphic
  15622. elements, which are promotive of the interests of this regulative
  15623. principle. For it is no more than an idea, which does not relate
  15624. directly to a being distinct from the world, but to the regulative
  15625. principle of the systematic unity of the world, by means, however, of a
  15626. schema of this unity--the schema of a Supreme Intelligence, who is the
  15627. wisely-designing author of the universe. What this basis of cosmical
  15628. unity may be in itself, we know not--we cannot discover from the
  15629. idea; we merely know how we ought to employ the idea of this unity,
  15630. in relation to the systematic operation of reason in the sphere of
  15631. experience.
  15632. [*Footnote: After what has been said of the psychological idea of
  15633. the ego and its proper employment as a regulative principle of the
  15634. operations of reason, I need not enter into details regarding the
  15635. transcendental illusion by which the systematic unity of all the various
  15636. phenomena of the internal sense is hypostatized. The procedure is in
  15637. this case very similar to that which has been discussed in our remarks
  15638. on the theological ideal.]
  15639. But, it will be asked again, can we on these grounds, admit the
  15640. existence of a wise and omnipotent author of the world? Without doubt;
  15641. and not only so, but we must assume the existence of such a being.
  15642. But do we thus extend the limits of our knowledge beyond the field
  15643. of possible experience? By no means. For we have merely presupposed a
  15644. something, of which we have no conception, which we do not know as it
  15645. is in itself; but, in relation to the systematic disposition of the
  15646. universe, which we must presuppose in all our observation of nature,
  15647. we have cogitated this unknown being in analogy with an intelligent
  15648. existence (an empirical conception), that is to say, we have endowed it
  15649. with those attributes, which, judging from the nature of our own
  15650. reason, may contain the ground of such a systematic unity. This idea is
  15651. therefore valid only relatively to the employment in experience of our
  15652. reason. But if we attribute to it absolute and objective validity, we
  15653. overlook the fact that it is merely an ideal being that we cogitate;
  15654. and, by setting out from a basis which is not determinable by
  15655. considerations drawn from experience, we place ourselves in a position
  15656. which incapacitates us from applying this principle to the empirical
  15657. employment of reason.
  15658. But, it will be asked further, can I make any use of this conception and
  15659. hypothesis in my investigations into the world and nature? Yes, for this
  15660. very purpose was the idea established by reason as a fundamental basis.
  15661. But may I regard certain arrangements, which seemed to have been made in
  15662. conformity with some fixed aim, as the arrangements of design, and look
  15663. upon them as proceeding from the divine will, with the intervention,
  15664. however, of certain other particular arrangements disposed to that
  15665. end? Yes, you may do so; but at the same time you must regard it as
  15666. indifferent, whether it is asserted that divine wisdom has disposed all
  15667. things in conformity with his highest aims, or that the idea of supreme
  15668. wisdom is a regulative principle in the investigation of nature, and at
  15669. the same time a principle of the systematic unity of nature according to
  15670. general laws, even in those cases where we are unable to discover that
  15671. unity. In other words, it must be perfectly indifferent to you whether
  15672. you say, when you have discovered this unity: God has wisely willed
  15673. it so; or: Nature has wisely arranged this. For it was nothing but the
  15674. systematic unity, which reason requires as a basis for the investigation
  15675. of nature, that justified you in accepting the idea of a supreme
  15676. intelligence as a schema for a regulative principle; and, the farther
  15677. you advance in the discovery of design and finality, the more certain
  15678. the validity of your idea. But, as the whole aim of this regulative
  15679. principle was the discovery of a necessary and systematic unity in
  15680. nature, we have, in so far as we attain this, to attribute our success
  15681. to the idea of a Supreme Being; while, at the same time, we cannot,
  15682. without involving ourselves in contradictions, overlook the general
  15683. laws of nature, as it was in reference to them alone that this idea was
  15684. employed. We cannot, I say, overlook the general laws of nature, and
  15685. regard this conformity to aims observable in nature as contingent or
  15686. hyperphysical in its origin; inasmuch as there is no ground which can
  15687. justify us in the admission of a being with such properties distinct
  15688. from and above nature. All that we are authorized to assert is that
  15689. this idea may be employed as a principle, and that the properties of
  15690. the being which is assumed to correspond to it may be regarded as
  15691. systematically connected in analogy with the causal determination of
  15692. phenomena.
  15693. For the same reasons we are justified in introducing into the idea of
  15694. the supreme cause other anthropomorphic elements (for without these we
  15695. could not predicate anything of it); we may regard it as allowable
  15696. to cogitate this cause as a being with understanding, the feelings of
  15697. pleasure and displeasure, and faculties of desire and will corresponding
  15698. to these. At the same time, we may attribute to this being infinite
  15699. perfection--a perfection which necessarily transcends that which our
  15700. knowledge of the order and design in the world authorize us to predicate
  15701. of it. For the regulative law of systematic unity requires us to study
  15702. nature on the supposition that systematic and final unity in infinitum
  15703. is everywhere discoverable, even in the highest diversity. For, although
  15704. we may discover little of this cosmical perfection, it belongs to the
  15705. legislative prerogative of reason to require us always to seek for
  15706. and to expect it; while it must always be beneficial to institute all
  15707. inquiries into nature in accordance with this principle. But it is
  15708. evident that, by this idea of a supreme author of all, which I place as
  15709. the foundation of all inquiries into nature, I do not mean to assert
  15710. the existence of such a being, or that I have any knowledge of its
  15711. existence; and, consequently, I do not really deduce anything from the
  15712. existence of this being, but merely from its idea, that is to say, from
  15713. the nature of things in this world, in accordance with this idea. A
  15714. certain dim consciousness of the true use of this idea seems to have
  15715. dictated to the philosophers of all times the moderate language used
  15716. by them regarding the cause of the world. We find them employing
  15717. the expressions wisdom and care of nature, and divine wisdom, as
  15718. synonymous--nay, in purely speculative discussions, preferring the
  15719. former, because it does not carry the appearance of greater pretensions
  15720. than such as we are entitled to make, and at the same time directs
  15721. reason to its proper field of action--nature and her phenomena.
  15722. Thus, pure reason, which at first seemed to promise us nothing less
  15723. than the extension of our cognition beyond the limits of experience,
  15724. is found, when thoroughly examined, to contain nothing but regulative
  15725. principles, the virtue and function of which is to introduce into our
  15726. cognition a higher degree of unity than the understanding could of
  15727. itself. These principles, by placing the goal of all our struggles at
  15728. so great a distance, realize for us the most thorough connection
  15729. between the different parts of our cognition, and the highest degree of
  15730. systematic unity. But, on the other hand, if misunderstood and employed
  15731. as constitutive principles of transcendent cognition, they become the
  15732. parents of illusions and contradictions, while pretending to introduce
  15733. us to new regions of knowledge.
  15734. Thus all human cognition begins with intuitions, proceeds from thence to
  15735. conceptions, and ends with ideas. Although it possesses, in relation
  15736. to all three elements, a priori sources of cognition, which seemed
  15737. to transcend the limits of all experience, a thoroughgoing criticism
  15738. demonstrates that speculative reason can never, by the aid of these
  15739. elements, pass the bounds of possible experience, and that the proper
  15740. destination of this highest faculty of cognition is to employ all
  15741. methods, and all the principles of these methods, for the purpose of
  15742. penetrating into the innermost secrets of nature, by the aid of the
  15743. principles of unity (among all kinds of which teleological unity is
  15744. the highest), while it ought not to attempt to soar above the sphere of
  15745. experience, beyond which there lies nought for us but the void inane.
  15746. The critical examination, in our Transcendental Analytic, of all the
  15747. propositions which professed to extend cognition beyond the sphere of
  15748. experience, completely demonstrated that they can only conduct us to
  15749. a possible experience. If we were not distrustful even of the clearest
  15750. abstract theorems, if we were not allured by specious and inviting
  15751. prospects to escape from the constraining power of their evidence, we
  15752. might spare ourselves the laborious examination of all the dialectical
  15753. arguments which a transcendent reason adduces in support of its
  15754. pretensions; for we should know with the most complete certainty that,
  15755. however honest such professions might be, they are null and valueless,
  15756. because they relate to a kind of knowledge to which no man can by any
  15757. possibility attain. But, as there is no end to discussion, if we cannot
  15758. discover the true cause of the illusions by which even the wisest are
  15759. deceived, and as the analysis of all our transcendent cognition into its
  15760. elements is of itself of no slight value as a psychological study, while
  15761. it is a duty incumbent on every philosopher--it was found necessary to
  15762. investigate the dialectical procedure of reason in its primary sources.
  15763. And as the inferences of which this dialectic is the parent are not only
  15764. deceitful, but naturally possess a profound interest for humanity, it
  15765. was advisable at the same time, to give a full account of the momenta of
  15766. this dialectical procedure, and to deposit it in the archives of human
  15767. reason, as a warning to all future metaphysicians to avoid these causes
  15768. of speculative error.
  15769. II.
  15770. TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD.
  15771. If we regard the sum of the cognition of pure speculative reason as an
  15772. edifice, the idea of which, at least, exists in the human mind, it may
  15773. be said that we have in the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements examined
  15774. the materials and determined to what edifice these belong, and what
  15775. its height and stability. We have found, indeed, that, although we had
  15776. purposed to build for ourselves a tower which should reach to Heaven,
  15777. the supply of materials sufficed merely for a habitation, which was
  15778. spacious enough for all terrestrial purposes, and high enough to
  15779. enable us to survey the level plain of experience, but that the bold
  15780. undertaking designed necessarily failed for want of materials--not to
  15781. mention the confusion of tongues, which gave rise to endless disputes
  15782. among the labourers on the plan of the edifice, and at last scattered
  15783. them over all the world, each to erect a separate building for himself,
  15784. according to his own plans and his own inclinations. Our present task
  15785. relates not to the materials, but to the plan of an edifice; and, as we
  15786. have had sufficient warning not to venture blindly upon a design which
  15787. may be found to transcend our natural powers, while, at the same time,
  15788. we cannot give up the intention of erecting a secure abode for the mind,
  15789. we must proportion our design to the material which is presented to us,
  15790. and which is, at the same time, sufficient for all our wants.
  15791. I understand, then, by the transcendental doctrine of method, the
  15792. determination of the formal conditions of a complete system of pure
  15793. reason. We shall accordingly have to treat of the discipline, the canon,
  15794. the architectonic, and, finally, the history of pure reason. This part
  15795. of our Critique will accomplish, from the transcendental point of view,
  15796. what has been usually attempted, but miserably executed, under the name
  15797. of practical logic. It has been badly executed, I say, because general
  15798. logic, not being limited to any particular kind of cognition (not
  15799. even to the pure cognition of the understanding) nor to any particular
  15800. objects, it cannot, without borrowing from other sciences, do more than
  15801. present merely the titles or signs of possible methods and the technical
  15802. expressions, which are employed in the systematic parts of all sciences;
  15803. and thus the pupil is made acquainted with names, the meaning and
  15804. application of which he is to learn only at some future time.
  15805. CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason.
  15806. Negative judgements--those which are so not merely as regards their
  15807. logical form, but in respect of their content--are not commonly held in
  15808. especial respect. They are, on the contrary, regarded as jealous enemies
  15809. of our insatiable desire for knowledge; and it almost requires an
  15810. apology to induce us to tolerate, much less to prize and to respect
  15811. them.
  15812. All propositions, indeed, may be logically expressed in a negative form;
  15813. but, in relation to the content of our cognition, the peculiar province
  15814. of negative judgements is solely to prevent error. For this reason, too,
  15815. negative propositions, which are framed for the purpose of correcting
  15816. false cognitions where error is absolutely impossible, are undoubtedly
  15817. true, but inane and senseless; that is, they are in reality purposeless
  15818. and, for this reason, often very ridiculous. Such is the proposition
  15819. of the schoolman that Alexander could not have subdued any countries
  15820. without an army.
  15821. But where the limits of our possible cognition are very much contracted,
  15822. the attraction to new fields of knowledge great, the illusions to
  15823. which the mind is subject of the most deceptive character, and the
  15824. evil consequences of error of no inconsiderable magnitude--the negative
  15825. element in knowledge, which is useful only to guard us against error,
  15826. is of far more importance than much of that positive instruction which
  15827. makes additions to the sum of our knowledge. The restraint which is
  15828. employed to repress, and finally to extirpate the constant inclination
  15829. to depart from certain rules, is termed discipline. It is distinguished
  15830. from culture, which aims at the formation of a certain degree of skill,
  15831. without attempting to repress or to destroy any other mental power,
  15832. already existing. In the cultivation of a talent, which has given
  15833. evidence of an impulse towards self-development, discipline takes a
  15834. negative,* culture and doctrine a positive, part.
  15835. [*Footnote: I am well aware that, in the language of the schools, the
  15836. term discipline is usually employed as synonymous with instruction.
  15837. But there are so many cases in which it is necessary to distinguish the
  15838. notion of the former, as a course of corrective training, from that of
  15839. the latter, as the communication of knowledge, and the nature of things
  15840. itself demands the appropriation of the most suitable expressions for
  15841. this distinction, that it is my desire that the former terms should
  15842. never be employed in any other than a negative signification.]
  15843. That natural dispositions and talents (such as imagination and wit),
  15844. which ask a free and unlimited development, require in many respects the
  15845. corrective influence of discipline, every one will readily grant. But
  15846. it may well appear strange that reason, whose proper duty it is to
  15847. prescribe rules of discipline to all the other powers of the mind,
  15848. should itself require this corrective. It has, in fact, hitherto
  15849. escaped this humiliation, only because, in presence of its magnificent
  15850. pretensions and high position, no one could readily suspect it to be
  15851. capable of substituting fancies for conceptions, and words for things.
  15852. Reason, when employed in the field of experience, does not stand in need
  15853. of criticism, because its principles are subjected to the continual test
  15854. of empirical observations. Nor is criticism requisite in the sphere of
  15855. mathematics, where the conceptions of reason must always be presented
  15856. in concreto in pure intuition, and baseless or arbitrary assertions are
  15857. discovered without difficulty. But where reason is not held in a plain
  15858. track by the influence of empirical or of pure intuition, that is, when
  15859. it is employed in the transcendental sphere of pure conceptions, it
  15860. stands in great need of discipline, to restrain its propensity to
  15861. overstep the limits of possible experience and to keep it from wandering
  15862. into error. In fact, the utility of the philosophy of pure reason is
  15863. entirely of this negative character. Particular errors may be corrected
  15864. by particular animadversions, and the causes of these errors may be
  15865. eradicated by criticism. But where we find, as in the case of pure
  15866. reason, a complete system of illusions and fallacies, closely connected
  15867. with each other and depending upon grand general principles, there
  15868. seems to be required a peculiar and negative code of mental legislation,
  15869. which, under the denomination of a discipline, and founded upon the
  15870. nature of reason and the objects of its exercise, shall constitute a
  15871. system of thorough examination and testing, which no fallacy will be
  15872. able to withstand or escape from, under whatever disguise or concealment
  15873. it may lurk.
  15874. But the reader must remark that, in this the second division of our
  15875. transcendental Critique the discipline of pure reason is not directed
  15876. to the content, but to the method of the cognition of pure reason. The
  15877. former task has been completed in the doctrine of elements. But there
  15878. is so much similarity in the mode of employing the faculty of reason,
  15879. whatever be the object to which it is applied, while, at the same time,
  15880. its employment in the transcendental sphere is so essentially different
  15881. in kind from every other, that, without the warning negative influence
  15882. of a discipline specially directed to that end, the errors are
  15883. unavoidable which spring from the unskillful employment of the methods
  15884. which are originated by reason but which are out of place in this
  15885. sphere.
  15886. SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism.
  15887. The science of mathematics presents the most brilliant example of the
  15888. extension of the sphere of pure reason without the aid of experience.
  15889. Examples are always contagious; and they exert an especial influence on
  15890. the same faculty, which naturally flatters itself that it will have
  15891. the same good fortune in other case as fell to its lot in one fortunate
  15892. instance. Hence pure reason hopes to be able to extend its empire in the
  15893. transcendental sphere with equal success and security, especially
  15894. when it applies the same method which was attended with such brilliant
  15895. results in the science of mathematics. It is, therefore, of the
  15896. highest importance for us to know whether the method of arriving at
  15897. demonstrative certainty, which is termed mathematical, be identical with
  15898. that by which we endeavour to attain the same degree of certainty in
  15899. philosophy, and which is termed in that science dogmatical.
  15900. Philosophical cognition is the cognition of reason by means of
  15901. conceptions; mathematical cognition is cognition by means of the
  15902. construction of conceptions. The construction of a conception is
  15903. the presentation a priori of the intuition which corresponds to the
  15904. conception. For this purpose a non-empirical intuition is requisite,
  15905. which, as an intuition, is an individual object; while, as the
  15906. construction of a conception (a general representation), it must be seen
  15907. to be universally valid for all the possible intuitions which rank under
  15908. that conception. Thus I construct a triangle, by the presentation of the
  15909. object which corresponds to this conception, either by mere imagination,
  15910. in pure intuition, or upon paper, in empirical intuition, in both cases
  15911. completely a priori, without borrowing the type of that figure from any
  15912. experience. The individual figure drawn upon paper is empirical; but
  15913. it serves, notwithstanding, to indicate the conception, even in its
  15914. universality, because in this empirical intuition we keep our eye merely
  15915. on the act of the construction of the conception, and pay no attention
  15916. to the various modes of determining it, for example, its size, the
  15917. length of its sides, the size of its angles, these not in the least
  15918. affecting the essential character of the conception.
  15919. Philosophical cognition, accordingly, regards the particular only in
  15920. the general; mathematical the general in the particular, nay, in the
  15921. individual. This is done, however, entirely a priori and by means of
  15922. pure reason, so that, as this individual figure is determined under
  15923. certain universal conditions of construction, the object of the
  15924. conception, to which this individual figure corresponds as its schema,
  15925. must be cogitated as universally determined.
  15926. The essential difference of these two modes of cognition consists,
  15927. therefore, in this formal quality; it does not regard the difference of
  15928. the matter or objects of both. Those thinkers who aim at distinguishing
  15929. philosophy from mathematics by asserting that the former has to do with
  15930. quality merely, and the latter with quantity, have mistaken the effect
  15931. for the cause. The reason why mathematical cognition can relate only to
  15932. quantity is to be found in its form alone. For it is the conception of
  15933. quantities only that is capable of being constructed, that is, presented
  15934. a priori in intuition; while qualities cannot be given in any other than
  15935. an empirical intuition. Hence the cognition of qualities by reason is
  15936. possible only through conceptions. No one can find an intuition which
  15937. shall correspond to the conception of reality, except in experience;
  15938. it cannot be presented to the mind a priori and antecedently to the
  15939. empirical consciousness of a reality. We can form an intuition, by means
  15940. of the mere conception of it, of a cone, without the aid of experience;
  15941. but the colour of the cone we cannot know except from experience. I
  15942. cannot present an intuition of a cause, except in an example which
  15943. experience offers to me. Besides, philosophy, as well as mathematics,
  15944. treats of quantities; as, for example, of totality, infinity, and so
  15945. on. Mathematics, too, treats of the difference of lines and surfaces--as
  15946. spaces of different quality, of the continuity of extension--as a
  15947. quality thereof. But, although in such cases they have a common object,
  15948. the mode in which reason considers that object is very different in
  15949. philosophy from what it is in mathematics. The former confines itself
  15950. to the general conceptions; the latter can do nothing with a mere
  15951. conception, it hastens to intuition. In this intuition it regards the
  15952. conception in concreto, not empirically, but in an a priori intuition,
  15953. which it has constructed; and in which, all the results which follow
  15954. from the general conditions of the construction of the conception are in
  15955. all cases valid for the object of the constructed conception.
  15956. Suppose that the conception of a triangle is given to a philosopher
  15957. and that he is required to discover, by the philosophical method, what
  15958. relation the sum of its angles bears to a right angle. He has nothing
  15959. before him but the conception of a figure enclosed within three right
  15960. lines, and, consequently, with the same number of angles. He may analyse
  15961. the conception of a right line, of an angle, or of the number three
  15962. as long as he pleases, but he will not discover any properties not
  15963. contained in these conceptions. But, if this question is proposed to
  15964. a geometrician, he at once begins by constructing a triangle. He knows
  15965. that two right angles are equal to the sum of all the contiguous angles
  15966. which proceed from one point in a straight line; and he goes on to
  15967. produce one side of his triangle, thus forming two adjacent angles which
  15968. are together equal to two right angles. He then divides the exterior of
  15969. these angles, by drawing a line parallel with the opposite side of the
  15970. triangle, and immediately perceives that he has thus got an exterior
  15971. adjacent angle which is equal to the interior. Proceeding in this way,
  15972. through a chain of inferences, and always on the ground of intuition, he
  15973. arrives at a clear and universally valid solution of the question.
  15974. But mathematics does not confine itself to the construction of
  15975. quantities (quanta), as in the case of geometry; it occupies itself
  15976. with pure quantity also (quantitas), as in the case of algebra, where
  15977. complete abstraction is made of the properties of the object indicated
  15978. by the conception of quantity. In algebra, a certain method of
  15979. notation by signs is adopted, and these indicate the different possible
  15980. constructions of quantities, the extraction of roots, and so on. After
  15981. having thus denoted the general conception of quantities, according to
  15982. their different relations, the different operations by which quantity
  15983. or number is increased or diminished are presented in intuition in
  15984. accordance with general rules. Thus, when one quantity is to be divided
  15985. by another, the signs which denote both are placed in the form peculiar
  15986. to the operation of division; and thus algebra, by means of a symbolical
  15987. construction of quantity, just as geometry, with its ostensive or
  15988. geometrical construction (a construction of the objects themselves),
  15989. arrives at results which discursive cognition cannot hope to reach by
  15990. the aid of mere conceptions.
  15991. Now, what is the cause of this difference in the fortune of the
  15992. philosopher and the mathematician, the former of whom follows the path
  15993. of conceptions, while the latter pursues that of intuitions, which he
  15994. represents, a priori, in correspondence with his conceptions? The cause
  15995. is evident from what has been already demonstrated in the introduction
  15996. to this Critique. We do not, in the present case, want to discover
  15997. analytical propositions, which may be produced merely by analysing our
  15998. conceptions--for in this the philosopher would have the advantage over
  15999. his rival; we aim at the discovery of synthetical propositions--such
  16000. synthetical propositions, moreover, as can be cognized a priori. I must
  16001. not confine myself to that which I actually cogitate in my conception
  16002. of a triangle, for this is nothing more than the mere definition; I
  16003. must try to go beyond that, and to arrive at properties which are not
  16004. contained in, although they belong to, the conception. Now, this is
  16005. impossible, unless I determine the object present to my mind according
  16006. to the conditions, either of empirical, or of pure, intuition. In the
  16007. former case, I should have an empirical proposition (arrived at by
  16008. actual measurement of the angles of the triangle), which would possess
  16009. neither universality nor necessity; but that would be of no value. In
  16010. the latter, I proceed by geometrical construction, by means of which I
  16011. collect, in a pure intuition, just as I would in an empirical intuition,
  16012. all the various properties which belong to the schema of a triangle
  16013. in general, and consequently to its conception, and thus construct
  16014. synthetical propositions which possess the attribute of universality.
  16015. It would be vain to philosophize upon the triangle, that is, to reflect
  16016. on it discursively; I should get no further than the definition with
  16017. which I had been obliged to set out. There are certainly transcendental
  16018. synthetical propositions which are framed by means of pure conceptions,
  16019. and which form the peculiar distinction of philosophy; but these do not
  16020. relate to any particular thing, but to a thing in general, and enounce
  16021. the conditions under which the perception of it may become a part of
  16022. possible experience. But the science of mathematics has nothing to do
  16023. with such questions, nor with the question of existence in any fashion;
  16024. it is concerned merely with the properties of objects in themselves,
  16025. only in so far as these are connected with the conception of the
  16026. objects.
  16027. In the above example, we merely attempted to show the great difference
  16028. which exists between the discursive employment of reason in the sphere
  16029. of conceptions, and its intuitive exercise by means of the construction
  16030. of conceptions. The question naturally arises: What is the cause which
  16031. necessitates this twofold exercise of reason, and how are we to discover
  16032. whether it is the philosophical or the mathematical method which reason
  16033. is pursuing in an argument?
  16034. All our knowledge relates, finally, to possible intuitions, for it
  16035. is these alone that present objects to the mind. An a priori or
  16036. non-empirical conception contains either a pure intuition--and in this
  16037. case it can be constructed; or it contains nothing but the synthesis of
  16038. possible intuitions, which are not given a priori. In this latter case,
  16039. it may help us to form synthetical a priori judgements, but only in the
  16040. discursive method, by conceptions, not in the intuitive, by means of the
  16041. construction of conceptions.
  16042. The only a priori intuition is that of the pure form of phenomena--space
  16043. and time. A conception of space and time as quanta may be presented
  16044. a priori in intuition, that is, constructed, either alone with their
  16045. quality (figure), or as pure quantity (the mere synthesis of the
  16046. homogeneous), by means of number. But the matter of phenomena, by which
  16047. things are given in space and time, can be presented only in perception,
  16048. a posteriori. The only conception which represents a priori this
  16049. empirical content of phenomena is the conception of a thing in general;
  16050. and the a priori synthetical cognition of this conception can give
  16051. us nothing more than the rule for the synthesis of that which may be
  16052. contained in the corresponding a posteriori perception; it is utterly
  16053. inadequate to present an a priori intuition of the real object, which
  16054. must necessarily be empirical.
  16055. Synthetical propositions, which relate to things in general, an a priori
  16056. intuition of which is impossible, are transcendental. For this
  16057. reason transcendental propositions cannot be framed by means of the
  16058. construction of conceptions; they are a priori, and based entirely on
  16059. conceptions themselves. They contain merely the rule, by which we are to
  16060. seek in the world of perception or experience the synthetical unity
  16061. of that which cannot be intuited a priori. But they are incompetent
  16062. to present any of the conceptions which appear in them in an a priori
  16063. intuition; these can be given only a posteriori, in experience, which,
  16064. however, is itself possible only through these synthetical principles.
  16065. If we are to form a synthetical judgement regarding a conception, we
  16066. must go beyond it, to the intuition in which it is given. If we keep
  16067. to what is contained in the conception, the judgement is merely
  16068. analytical--it is merely an explanation of what we have cogitated in the
  16069. conception. But I can pass from the conception to the pure or empirical
  16070. intuition which corresponds to it. I can proceed to examine my
  16071. conception in concreto, and to cognize, either a priori or a posterio,
  16072. what I find in the object of the conception. The former--a priori
  16073. cognition--is rational-mathematical cognition by means of the
  16074. construction of the conception; the latter--a posteriori cognition--is
  16075. purely empirical cognition, which does not possess the attributes of
  16076. necessity and universality. Thus I may analyse the conception I have
  16077. of gold; but I gain no new information from this analysis, I merely
  16078. enumerate the different properties which I had connected with the notion
  16079. indicated by the word. My knowledge has gained in logical clearness
  16080. and arrangement, but no addition has been made to it. But if I take the
  16081. matter which is indicated by this name, and submit it to the examination
  16082. of my senses, I am enabled to form several synthetical--although still
  16083. empirical--propositions. The mathematical conception of a triangle I
  16084. should construct, that is, present a priori in intuition, and in
  16085. this way attain to rational-synthetical cognition. But when the
  16086. transcendental conception of reality, or substance, or power is
  16087. presented to my mind, I find that it does not relate to or indicate
  16088. either an empirical or pure intuition, but that it indicates merely the
  16089. synthesis of empirical intuitions, which cannot of course be given
  16090. a priori. The synthesis in such a conception cannot proceed a
  16091. priori--without the aid of experience--to the intuition which
  16092. corresponds to the conception; and, for this reason, none of these
  16093. conceptions can produce a determinative synthetical proposition, they
  16094. can never present more than a principle of the synthesis* of possible
  16095. empirical intuitions. A transcendental proposition is, therefore, a
  16096. synthetical cognition of reason by means of pure conceptions and the
  16097. discursive method, and it renders possible all synthetical unity in
  16098. empirical cognition, though it cannot present us with any intuition a
  16099. priori.
  16100. [*Footnote: In the case of the conception of cause, I do really go
  16101. beyond the empirical conception of an event--but not to the
  16102. intuition which presents this conception in concreto, but only to the
  16103. time-conditions, which may be found in experience to correspond to
  16104. the conception. My procedure is, therefore, strictly according to
  16105. conceptions; I cannot in a case of this kind employ the construction of
  16106. conceptions, because the conception is merely a rule for the synthesis
  16107. of perceptions, which are not pure intuitions, and which, therefore,
  16108. cannot be given a priori.]
  16109. There is thus a twofold exercise of reason. Both modes have the
  16110. properties of universality and an a priori origin in common, but are,
  16111. in their procedure, of widely different character. The reason of this is
  16112. that in the world of phenomena, in which alone objects are presented to
  16113. our minds, there are two main elements--the form of intuition (space and
  16114. time), which can be cognized and determined completely a priori, and the
  16115. matter or content--that which is presented in space and time, and which,
  16116. consequently, contains a something--an existence corresponding to our
  16117. powers of sensation. As regards the latter, which can never be given in
  16118. a determinate mode except by experience, there are no a priori notions
  16119. which relate to it, except the undetermined conceptions of the synthesis
  16120. of possible sensations, in so far as these belong (in a possible
  16121. experience) to the unity of consciousness. As regards the former, we
  16122. can determine our conceptions a priori in intuition, inasmuch as we are
  16123. ourselves the creators of the objects of the conceptions in space and
  16124. time--these objects being regarded simply as quanta. In the one case,
  16125. reason proceeds according to conceptions and can do nothing more than
  16126. subject phenomena to these--which can only be determined empirically,
  16127. that is, a posteriori--in conformity, however, with those conceptions as
  16128. the rules of all empirical synthesis. In the other case, reason proceeds
  16129. by the construction of conceptions; and, as these conceptions relate
  16130. to an a priori intuition, they may be given and determined in pure
  16131. intuition a priori, and without the aid of empirical data. The
  16132. examination and consideration of everything that exists in space
  16133. or time--whether it is a quantum or not, in how far the particular
  16134. something (which fills space or time) is a primary substratum, or a mere
  16135. determination of some other existence, whether it relates to anything
  16136. else--either as cause or effect, whether its existence is isolated or in
  16137. reciprocal connection with and dependence upon others, the possibility
  16138. of this existence, its reality and necessity or opposites--all these
  16139. form part of the cognition of reason on the ground of conceptions, and
  16140. this cognition is termed philosophical. But to determine a priori an
  16141. intuition in space (its figure), to divide time into periods, or merely
  16142. to cognize the quantity of an intuition in space and time, and to
  16143. determine it by number--all this is an operation of reason by means of
  16144. the construction of conceptions, and is called mathematical.
  16145. The success which attends the efforts of reason in the sphere of
  16146. mathematics naturally fosters the expectation that the same good fortune
  16147. will be its lot, if it applies the mathematical method in other regions
  16148. of mental endeavour besides that of quantities. Its success is thus
  16149. great, because it can support all its conceptions by a priori intuitions
  16150. and, in this way, make itself a master, as it were, over nature; while
  16151. pure philosophy, with its a priori discursive conceptions, bungles
  16152. about in the world of nature, and cannot accredit or show any a priori
  16153. evidence of the reality of these conceptions. Masters in the science of
  16154. mathematics are confident of the success of this method; indeed, it is a
  16155. common persuasion that it is capable of being applied to any subject of
  16156. human thought. They have hardly ever reflected or philosophized on
  16157. their favourite science--a task of great difficulty; and the specific
  16158. difference between the two modes of employing the faculty of reason
  16159. has never entered their thoughts. Rules current in the field of common
  16160. experience, and which common sense stamps everywhere with its approval,
  16161. are regarded by them as axiomatic. From what source the conceptions of
  16162. space and time, with which (as the only primitive quanta) they have
  16163. to deal, enter their minds, is a question which they do not trouble
  16164. themselves to answer; and they think it just as unnecessary to examine
  16165. into the origin of the pure conceptions of the understanding and the
  16166. extent of their validity. All they have to do with them is to employ
  16167. them. In all this they are perfectly right, if they do not overstep the
  16168. limits of the sphere of nature. But they pass, unconsciously, from the
  16169. world of sense to the insecure ground of pure transcendental conceptions
  16170. (instabilis tellus, innabilis unda), where they can neither stand nor
  16171. swim, and where the tracks of their footsteps are obliterated by time;
  16172. while the march of mathematics is pursued on a broad and magnificent
  16173. highway, which the latest posterity shall frequent without fear of
  16174. danger or impediment.
  16175. As we have taken upon us the task of determining, clearly and certainly,
  16176. the limits of pure reason in the sphere of transcendentalism, and as
  16177. the efforts of reason in this direction are persisted in, even after the
  16178. plainest and most expressive warnings, hope still beckoning us past the
  16179. limits of experience into the splendours of the intellectual world--it
  16180. becomes necessary to cut away the last anchor of this fallacious and
  16181. fantastic hope. We shall, accordingly, show that the mathematical
  16182. method is unattended in the sphere of philosophy by the least
  16183. advantage--except, perhaps, that it more plainly exhibits its own
  16184. inadequacy--that geometry and philosophy are two quite different things,
  16185. although they go band in hand in hand in the field of natural science,
  16186. and, consequently, that the procedure of the one can never be imitated
  16187. by the other.
  16188. The evidence of mathematics rests upon definitions, axioms, and
  16189. demonstrations. I shall be satisfied with showing that none of these
  16190. forms can be employed or imitated in philosophy in the sense in which
  16191. they are understood by mathematicians; and that the geometrician, if
  16192. he employs his method in philosophy, will succeed only in building
  16193. card-castles, while the employment of the philosophical method in
  16194. mathematics can result in nothing but mere verbiage. The essential
  16195. business of philosophy, indeed, is to mark out the limits of the
  16196. science; and even the mathematician, unless his talent is naturally
  16197. circumscribed and limited to this particular department of knowledge,
  16198. cannot turn a deaf ear to the warnings of philosophy, or set himself
  16199. above its direction.
  16200. I. Of Definitions. A definition is, as the term itself indicates, the
  16201. representation, upon primary grounds, of the complete conception of
  16202. a thing within its own limits.* Accordingly, an empirical conception
  16203. cannot be defined, it can only be explained. For, as there are in such
  16204. a conception only a certain number of marks or signs, which denote a
  16205. certain class of sensuous objects, we can never be sure that we do not
  16206. cogitate under the word which indicates the same object, at one time
  16207. a greater, at another a smaller number of signs. Thus, one person may
  16208. cogitate in his conception of gold, in addition to its properties of
  16209. weight, colour, malleability, that of resisting rust, while another
  16210. person may be ignorant of this quality. We employ certain signs only so
  16211. long as we require them for the sake of distinction; new observations
  16212. abstract some and add new ones, so that an empirical conception never
  16213. remains within permanent limits. It is, in fact, useless to define a
  16214. conception of this kind. If, for example, we are speaking of water and
  16215. its properties, we do not stop at what we actually think by the word
  16216. water, but proceed to observation and experiment; and the word, with
  16217. the few signs attached to it, is more properly a designation than a
  16218. conception of the thing. A definition in this case would evidently be
  16219. nothing more than a determination of the word. In the second place, no
  16220. a priori conception, such as those of substance, cause, right, fitness,
  16221. and so on, can be defined. For I can never be sure, that the clear
  16222. representation of a given conception (which is given in a confused
  16223. state) has been fully developed, until I know that the representation
  16224. is adequate with its object. But, inasmuch as the conception, as it is
  16225. presented to the mind, may contain a number of obscure representations,
  16226. which we do not observe in our analysis, although we employ them in our
  16227. application of the conception, I can never be sure that my analysis is
  16228. complete, while examples may make this probable, although they can never
  16229. demonstrate the fact. Instead of the word definition, I should rather
  16230. employ the term exposition--a more modest expression, which the critic
  16231. may accept without surrendering his doubts as to the completeness of the
  16232. analysis of any such conception. As, therefore, neither empirical nor a
  16233. priori conceptions are capable of definition, we have to see whether the
  16234. only other kind of conceptions--arbitrary conceptions--can be subjected
  16235. to this mental operation. Such a conception can always be defined; for
  16236. I must know thoroughly what I wished to cogitate in it, as it was I who
  16237. created it, and it was not given to my mind either by the nature of my
  16238. understanding or by experience. At the same time, I cannot say that, by
  16239. such a definition, I have defined a real object. If the conception is
  16240. based upon empirical conditions, if, for example, I have a conception of
  16241. a clock for a ship, this arbitrary conception does not assure me of the
  16242. existence or even of the possibility of the object. My definition of
  16243. such a conception would with more propriety be termed a declaration of
  16244. a project than a definition of an object. There are no other conceptions
  16245. which can bear definition, except those which contain an arbitrary
  16246. synthesis, which can be constructed a priori. Consequently, the science
  16247. of mathematics alone possesses definitions. For the object here thought
  16248. is presented a priori in intuition; and thus it can never contain more
  16249. or less than the conception, because the conception of the object has
  16250. been given by the definition--and primarily, that is, without deriving
  16251. the definition from any other source. Philosophical definitions are,
  16252. therefore, merely expositions of given conceptions, while mathematical
  16253. definitions are constructions of conceptions originally formed by the
  16254. mind itself; the former are produced by analysis, the completeness of
  16255. which is never demonstratively certain, the latter by a synthesis. In
  16256. a mathematical definition the conception is formed, in a philosophical
  16257. definition it is only explained. From this it follows:
  16258. [*Footnote: The definition must describe the conception completely that
  16259. is, omit none of the marks or signs of which it composed; within its own
  16260. limits, that is, it must be precise, and enumerate no more signs than
  16261. belong to the conception; and on primary grounds, that is to say, the
  16262. limitations of the bounds of the conception must not be deduced from
  16263. other conceptions, as in this case a proof would be necessary, and the
  16264. so-called definition would be incapable of taking its place at the bead
  16265. of all the judgements we have to form regarding an object.]
  16266. (a) That we must not imitate, in philosophy, the mathematical usage of
  16267. commencing with definitions--except by way of hypothesis or experiment.
  16268. For, as all so-called philosophical definitions are merely analyses of
  16269. given conceptions, these conceptions, although only in a confused form,
  16270. must precede the analysis; and the incomplete exposition must precede
  16271. the complete, so that we may be able to draw certain inferences from the
  16272. characteristics which an incomplete analysis has enabled us to discover,
  16273. before we attain to the complete exposition or definition of the
  16274. conception. In one word, a full and clear definition ought, in
  16275. philosophy, rather to form the conclusion than the commencement of our
  16276. labours.* In mathematics, on the contrary, we cannot have a conception
  16277. prior to the definition; it is the definition which gives us the
  16278. conception, and it must for this reason form the commencement of every
  16279. chain of mathematical reasoning.
  16280. [*Footnote: Philosophy abounds in faulty definitions, especially such as
  16281. contain some of the elements requisite to form a complete definition.
  16282. If a conception could not be employed in reasoning before it had been
  16283. defined, it would fare ill with all philosophical thought. But,
  16284. as incompletely defined conceptions may always be employed without
  16285. detriment to truth, so far as our analysis of the elements contained in
  16286. them proceeds, imperfect definitions, that is, propositions which are
  16287. properly not definitions, but merely approximations thereto, may be used
  16288. with great advantage. In mathematics, definition belongs ad esse, in
  16289. philosophy ad melius esse. It is a difficult task to construct a proper
  16290. definition. Jurists are still without a complete definition of the idea
  16291. of right.]
  16292. (b) Mathematical definitions cannot be erroneous. For the conception is
  16293. given only in and through the definition, and thus it contains only what
  16294. has been cogitated in the definition. But although a definition cannot
  16295. be incorrect, as regards its content, an error may sometimes, although
  16296. seldom, creep into the form. This error consists in a want of precision.
  16297. Thus the common definition of a circle--that it is a curved line,
  16298. every point in which is equally distant from another point called the
  16299. centre--is faulty, from the fact that the determination indicated by the
  16300. word curved is superfluous. For there ought to be a particular theorem,
  16301. which may be easily proved from the definition, to the effect that every
  16302. line, which has all its points at equal distances from another point,
  16303. must be a curved line--that is, that not even the smallest part of
  16304. it can be straight. Analytical definitions, on the other hand, may be
  16305. erroneous in many respects, either by the introduction of signs which do
  16306. not actually exist in the conception, or by wanting in that completeness
  16307. which forms the essential of a definition. In the latter case, the
  16308. definition is necessarily defective, because we can never be fully
  16309. certain of the completeness of our analysis. For these reasons, the
  16310. method of definition employed in mathematics cannot be imitated in
  16311. philosophy.
  16312. 2. Of Axioms. These, in so far as they are immediately certain, are a
  16313. priori synthetical principles. Now, one conception cannot be connected
  16314. synthetically and yet immediately with another; because, if we wish to
  16315. proceed out of and beyond a conception, a third mediating cognition is
  16316. necessary. And, as philosophy is a cognition of reason by the aid
  16317. of conceptions alone, there is to be found in it no principle which
  16318. deserves to be called an axiom. Mathematics, on the other hand, may
  16319. possess axioms, because it can always connect the predicates of an
  16320. object a priori, and without any mediating term, by means of the
  16321. construction of conceptions in intuition. Such is the case with the
  16322. proposition: Three points can always lie in a plane. On the other hand,
  16323. no synthetical principle which is based upon conceptions, can ever
  16324. be immediately certain (for example, the proposition: Everything that
  16325. happens has a cause), because I require a mediating term to connect
  16326. the two conceptions of event and cause--namely, the condition of
  16327. time-determination in an experience, and I cannot cognize any such
  16328. principle immediately and from conceptions alone. Discursive principles
  16329. are, accordingly, very different from intuitive principles or axioms.
  16330. The former always require deduction, which in the case of the latter
  16331. may be altogether dispensed with. Axioms are, for this reason, always
  16332. self-evident, while philosophical principles, whatever may be the degree
  16333. of certainty they possess, cannot lay any claim to such a distinction.
  16334. No synthetical proposition of pure transcendental reason can be so
  16335. evident, as is often rashly enough declared, as the statement, twice two
  16336. are four. It is true that in the Analytic I introduced into the list of
  16337. principles of the pure understanding, certain axioms of intuition; but
  16338. the principle there discussed was not itself an axiom, but served merely
  16339. to present the principle of the possibility of axioms in general, while
  16340. it was really nothing more than a principle based upon conceptions. For
  16341. it is one part of the duty of transcendental philosophy to establish
  16342. the possibility of mathematics itself. Philosophy possesses, then, no
  16343. axioms, and has no right to impose its a priori principles upon thought,
  16344. until it has established their authority and validity by a thoroughgoing
  16345. deduction.
  16346. 3. Of Demonstrations. Only an apodeictic proof, based upon intuition,
  16347. can be termed a demonstration. Experience teaches us what is, but it
  16348. cannot convince us that it might not have been otherwise. Hence a proof
  16349. upon empirical grounds cannot be apodeictic. A priori conceptions, in
  16350. discursive cognition, can never produce intuitive certainty or evidence,
  16351. however certain the judgement they present may be. Mathematics alone,
  16352. therefore, contains demonstrations, because it does not deduce its
  16353. cognition from conceptions, but from the construction of conceptions,
  16354. that is, from intuition, which can be given a priori in accordance with
  16355. conceptions. The method of algebra, in equations, from which the
  16356. correct answer is deduced by reduction, is a kind of construction--not
  16357. geometrical, but by symbols--in which all conceptions, especially those
  16358. of the relations of quantities, are represented in intuition by signs;
  16359. and thus the conclusions in that science are secured from errors by the
  16360. fact that every proof is submitted to ocular evidence. Philosophical
  16361. cognition does not possess this advantage, it being required to consider
  16362. the general always in abstracto (by means of conceptions), while
  16363. mathematics can always consider it in concreto (in an individual
  16364. intuition), and at the same time by means of a priori representation,
  16365. whereby all errors are rendered manifest to the senses. The
  16366. former--discursive proofs--ought to be termed acroamatic proofs,
  16367. rather than demonstrations, as only words are employed in them, while
  16368. demonstrations proper, as the term itself indicates, always require a
  16369. reference to the intuition of the object.
  16370. It follows from all these considerations that it is not consonant with
  16371. the nature of philosophy, especially in the sphere of pure reason, to
  16372. employ the dogmatical method, and to adorn itself with the titles and
  16373. insignia of mathematical science. It does not belong to that order, and
  16374. can only hope for a fraternal union with that science. Its attempts at
  16375. mathematical evidence are vain pretensions, which can only keep it back
  16376. from its true aim, which is to detect the illusory procedure of reason
  16377. when transgressing its proper limits, and by fully explaining and
  16378. analysing our conceptions, to conduct us from the dim regions of
  16379. speculation to the clear region of modest self-knowledge. Reason must
  16380. not, therefore, in its transcendental endeavours, look forward with such
  16381. confidence, as if the path it is pursuing led straight to its aim,
  16382. nor reckon with such security upon its premisses, as to consider it
  16383. unnecessary to take a step back, or to keep a strict watch for errors,
  16384. which, overlooked in the principles, may be detected in the arguments
  16385. themselves--in which case it may be requisite either to determine these
  16386. principles with greater strictness, or to change them entirely.
  16387. I divide all apodeictic propositions, whether demonstrable or
  16388. immediately certain, into dogmata and mathemata. A direct synthetical
  16389. proposition, based on conceptions, is a dogma; a proposition of the same
  16390. kind, based on the construction of conceptions, is a mathema. Analytical
  16391. judgements do not teach us any more about an object than what was
  16392. contained in the conception we had of it; because they do not extend our
  16393. cognition beyond our conception of an object, they merely elucidate the
  16394. conception. They cannot therefore be with propriety termed dogmas. Of
  16395. the two kinds of a priori synthetical propositions above mentioned, only
  16396. those which are employed in philosophy can, according to the general
  16397. mode of speech, bear this name; those of arithmetic or geometry would
  16398. not be rightly so denominated. Thus the customary mode of speaking
  16399. confirms the explanation given above, and the conclusion arrived at,
  16400. that only those judgements which are based upon conceptions, not on the
  16401. construction of conceptions, can be termed dogmatical.
  16402. Thus, pure reason, in the sphere of speculation, does not contain a
  16403. single direct synthetical judgement based upon conceptions. By means
  16404. of ideas, it is, as we have shown, incapable of producing synthetical
  16405. judgements, which are objectively valid; by means of the conceptions of
  16406. the understanding, it establishes certain indubitable principles, not,
  16407. however, directly on the basis of conceptions, but only indirectly by
  16408. means of the relation of these conceptions to something of a purely
  16409. contingent nature, namely, possible experience. When experience is
  16410. presupposed, these principles are apodeictically certain, but in
  16411. themselves, and directly, they cannot even be cognized a priori. Thus
  16412. the given conceptions of cause and event will not be sufficient for
  16413. the demonstration of the proposition: Every event has a cause. For this
  16414. reason, it is not a dogma; although from another point of view, that of
  16415. experience, it is capable of being proved to demonstration. The proper
  16416. term for such a proposition is principle, and not theorem (although
  16417. it does require to be proved), because it possesses the remarkable
  16418. peculiarity of being the condition of the possibility of its own ground
  16419. of proof, that is, experience, and of forming a necessary presupposition
  16420. in all empirical observation.
  16421. If then, in the speculative sphere of pure reason, no dogmata are to
  16422. be found; all dogmatical methods, whether borrowed from mathematics,
  16423. or invented by philosophical thinkers, are alike inappropriate and
  16424. inefficient. They only serve to conceal errors and fallacies, and to
  16425. deceive philosophy, whose duty it is to see that reason pursues a safe
  16426. and straight path. A philosophical method may, however, be systematical.
  16427. For our reason is, subjectively considered, itself a system, and, in
  16428. the sphere of mere conceptions, a system of investigation according to
  16429. principles of unity, the material being supplied by experience alone.
  16430. But this is not the proper place for discussing the peculiar method
  16431. of transcendental philosophy, as our present task is simply to examine
  16432. whether our faculties are capable of erecting an edifice on the basis
  16433. of pure reason, and how far they may proceed with the materials at their
  16434. command.
  16435. SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics.
  16436. Reason must be subject, in all its operations, to criticism, which
  16437. must always be permitted to exercise its functions without restraint;
  16438. otherwise its interests are imperilled and its influence obnoxious to
  16439. suspicion. There is nothing, however useful, however sacred it may be,
  16440. that can claim exemption from the searching examination of this supreme
  16441. tribunal, which has no respect of persons. The very existence of reason
  16442. depends upon this freedom; for the voice of reason is not that of
  16443. a dictatorial and despotic power, it is rather like the vote of the
  16444. citizens of a free state, every member of which must have the privilege
  16445. of giving free expression to his doubts, and possess even the right of
  16446. veto.
  16447. But while reason can never decline to submit itself to the tribunal of
  16448. criticism, it has not always cause to dread the judgement of this court.
  16449. Pure reason, however, when engaged in the sphere of dogmatism, is not so
  16450. thoroughly conscious of a strict observance of its highest laws, as to
  16451. appear before a higher judicial reason with perfect confidence. On the
  16452. contrary, it must renounce its magnificent dogmatical pretensions in
  16453. philosophy.
  16454. Very different is the case when it has to defend itself, not before a
  16455. judge, but against an equal. If dogmatical assertions are advanced on
  16456. the negative side, in opposition to those made by reason on the positive
  16457. side, its justification kat authrhopon is complete, although the proof
  16458. of its propositions is kat aletheian unsatisfactory.
  16459. By the polemic of pure reason I mean the defence of its propositions
  16460. made by reason, in opposition to the dogmatical counter-propositions
  16461. advanced by other parties. The question here is not whether its own
  16462. statements may not also be false; it merely regards the fact that
  16463. reason proves that the opposite cannot be established with demonstrative
  16464. certainty, nor even asserted with a higher degree of probability. Reason
  16465. does not hold her possessions upon sufferance; for, although she cannot
  16466. show a perfectly satisfactory title to them, no one can prove that she
  16467. is not the rightful possessor.
  16468. It is a melancholy reflection that reason, in its highest exercise,
  16469. falls into an antithetic; and that the supreme tribunal for the
  16470. settlement of differences should not be at union with itself. It is true
  16471. that we had to discuss the question of an apparent antithetic, but we
  16472. found that it was based upon a misconception. In conformity with the
  16473. common prejudice, phenomena were regarded as things in themselves, and
  16474. thus an absolute completeness in their synthesis was required in the one
  16475. mode or in the other (it was shown to be impossible in both); a demand
  16476. entirely out of place in regard to phenomena. There was, then, no
  16477. real self-contradiction of reason in the propositions: The series of
  16478. phenomena given in themselves has an absolutely first beginning; and:
  16479. This series is absolutely and in itself without beginning. The two
  16480. propositions are perfectly consistent with each other, because phenomena
  16481. as phenomena are in themselves nothing, and consequently the hypothesis
  16482. that they are things in themselves must lead to self-contradictory
  16483. inferences.
  16484. But there are cases in which a similar misunderstanding cannot be
  16485. provided against, and the dispute must remain unsettled. Take, for
  16486. example, the theistic proposition: There is a Supreme Being; and on the
  16487. other hand, the atheistic counter-statement: There exists no Supreme
  16488. Being; or, in psychology: Everything that thinks possesses the attribute
  16489. of absolute and permanent unity, which is utterly different from the
  16490. transitory unity of material phenomena; and the counter-proposition: The
  16491. soul is not an immaterial unity, and its nature is transitory, like that
  16492. of phenomena. The objects of these questions contain no heterogeneous or
  16493. contradictory elements, for they relate to things in themselves, and not
  16494. to phenomena. There would arise, indeed, a real contradiction, if reason
  16495. came forward with a statement on the negative side of these questions
  16496. alone. As regards the criticism to which the grounds of proof on the
  16497. affirmative side must be subjected, it may be freely admitted, without
  16498. necessitating the surrender of the affirmative propositions, which have,
  16499. at least, the interest of reason in their favour--an advantage which the
  16500. opposite party cannot lay claim to.
  16501. I cannot agree with the opinion of several admirable thinkers--Sulzer
  16502. among the rest--that, in spite of the weakness of the arguments hitherto
  16503. in use, we may hope, one day, to see sufficient demonstrations of the
  16504. two cardinal propositions of pure reason--the existence of a Supreme
  16505. Being, and the immortality of the soul. I am certain, on the contrary,
  16506. that this will never be the case. For on what ground can reason base
  16507. such synthetical propositions, which do not relate to the objects
  16508. of experience and their internal possibility? But it is also
  16509. demonstratively certain that no one will ever be able to maintain the
  16510. contrary with the least show of probability. For, as he can attempt such
  16511. a proof solely upon the basis of pure reason, he is bound to prove
  16512. that a Supreme Being, and a thinking subject in the character of a pure
  16513. intelligence, are impossible. But where will he find the knowledge which
  16514. can enable him to enounce synthetical judgements in regard to things
  16515. which transcend the region of experience? We may, therefore, rest
  16516. assured that the opposite never will be demonstrated. We need not, then,
  16517. have recourse to scholastic arguments; we may always admit the truth of
  16518. those propositions which are consistent with the speculative interests
  16519. of reason in the sphere of experience, and form, moreover, the only
  16520. means of uniting the speculative with the practical interest. Our
  16521. opponent, who must not be considered here as a critic solely, we can
  16522. be ready to meet with a non liquet which cannot fail to disconcert him;
  16523. while we cannot deny his right to a similar retort, as we have on our
  16524. side the advantage of the support of the subjective maxim of reason,
  16525. and can therefore look upon all his sophistical arguments with calm
  16526. indifference.
  16527. From this point of view, there is properly no antithetic of pure reason.
  16528. For the only arena for such a struggle would be upon the field of
  16529. pure theology and psychology; but on this ground there can appear no
  16530. combatant whom we need to fear. Ridicule and boasting can be his
  16531. only weapons; and these may be laughed at, as mere child's play.
  16532. This consideration restores to Reason her courage; for what source
  16533. of confidence could be found, if she, whose vocation it is to destroy
  16534. error, were at variance with herself and without any reasonable hope of
  16535. ever reaching a state of permanent repose?
  16536. Everything in nature is good for some purpose. Even poisons are
  16537. serviceable; they destroy the evil effects of other poisons generated
  16538. in our system, and must always find a place in every complete
  16539. pharmacopoeia. The objections raised against the fallacies and
  16540. sophistries of speculative reason, are objections given by the nature
  16541. of this reason itself, and must therefore have a destination and
  16542. purpose which can only be for the good of humanity. For what purpose has
  16543. Providence raised many objects, in which we have the deepest interest,
  16544. so far above us, that we vainly try to cognize them with certainty, and
  16545. our powers of mental vision are rather excited than satisfied by the
  16546. glimpses we may chance to seize? It is very doubtful whether it is for
  16547. our benefit to advance bold affirmations regarding subjects involved
  16548. in such obscurity; perhaps it would even be detrimental to our best
  16549. interests. But it is undoubtedly always beneficial to leave the
  16550. investigating, as well as the critical reason, in perfect freedom, and
  16551. permit it to take charge of its own interests, which are advanced as
  16552. much by its limitation, as by its extension of its views, and which
  16553. always suffer by the interference of foreign powers forcing it, against
  16554. its natural tendencies, to bend to certain preconceived designs.
  16555. Allow your opponent to say what he thinks reasonable, and combat him
  16556. only with the weapons of reason. Have no anxiety for the practical
  16557. interests of humanity--these are never imperilled in a purely
  16558. speculative dispute. Such a dispute serves merely to disclose the
  16559. antinomy of reason, which, as it has its source in the nature of
  16560. reason, ought to be thoroughly investigated. Reason is benefited by the
  16561. examination of a subject on both sides, and its judgements are corrected
  16562. by being limited. It is not the matter that may give occasion to
  16563. dispute, but the manner. For it is perfectly permissible to employ,
  16564. in the presence of reason, the language of a firmly rooted faith, even
  16565. after we have been obliged to renounce all pretensions to knowledge.
  16566. If we were to ask the dispassionate David Hume--a philosopher endowed,
  16567. in a degree that few are, with a well-balanced judgement: What motive
  16568. induced you to spend so much labour and thought in undermining the
  16569. consoling and beneficial persuasion that reason is capable of assuring
  16570. us of the existence, and presenting us with a determinate conception
  16571. of a Supreme Being?--his answer would be: Nothing but the desire of
  16572. teaching reason to know its own powers better, and, at the same time, a
  16573. dislike of the procedure by which that faculty was compelled to support
  16574. foregone conclusions, and prevented from confessing the internal
  16575. weaknesses which it cannot but feel when it enters upon a rigid
  16576. self-examination. If, on the other hand, we were to ask Priestley--a
  16577. philosopher who had no taste for transcendental speculation, but was
  16578. entirely devoted to the principles of empiricism--what his motives were
  16579. for overturning those two main pillars of religion--the doctrines of
  16580. the freedom of the will and the immortality of the soul (in his view
  16581. the hope of a future life is but the expectation of the miracle of
  16582. resurrection)--this philosopher, himself a zealous and pious teacher of
  16583. religion, could give no other answer than this: I acted in the interest
  16584. of reason, which always suffers, when certain objects are explained
  16585. and judged by a reference to other supposed laws than those of material
  16586. nature--the only laws which we know in a determinate manner. It would be
  16587. unfair to decry the latter philosopher, who endeavoured to harmonize his
  16588. paradoxical opinions with the interests of religion, and to undervalue
  16589. an honest and reflecting man, because he finds himself at a loss the
  16590. moment he has left the field of natural science. The same grace must be
  16591. accorded to Hume, a man not less well-disposed, and quite as blameless
  16592. in his moral character, and who pushed his abstract speculations to an
  16593. extreme length, because, as he rightly believed, the object of them lies
  16594. entirely beyond the bounds of natural science, and within the sphere of
  16595. pure ideas.
  16596. What is to be done to provide against the danger which seems in the
  16597. present case to menace the best interests of humanity? The course to be
  16598. pursued in reference to this subject is a perfectly plain and natural
  16599. one. Let each thinker pursue his own path; if he shows talent, if he
  16600. gives evidence of profound thought, in one word, if he shows that he
  16601. possesses the power of reasoning--reason is always the gainer. If you
  16602. have recourse to other means, if you attempt to coerce reason, if you
  16603. raise the cry of treason to humanity, if you excite the feelings of
  16604. the crowd, which can neither understand nor sympathize with such subtle
  16605. speculations--you will only make yourselves ridiculous. For the question
  16606. does not concern the advantage or disadvantage which we are expected
  16607. to reap from such inquiries; the question is merely how far reason can
  16608. advance in the field of speculation, apart from all kinds of interest,
  16609. and whether we may depend upon the exertions of speculative reason, or
  16610. must renounce all reliance on it. Instead of joining the combatants,
  16611. it is your part to be a tranquil spectator of the struggle--a laborious
  16612. struggle for the parties engaged, but attended, in its progress as
  16613. well as in its result, with the most advantageous consequences for
  16614. the interests of thought and knowledge. It is absurd to expect to be
  16615. enlightened by Reason, and at the same time to prescribe to her what
  16616. side of the question she must adopt. Moreover, reason is sufficiently
  16617. held in check by its own power, the limits imposed on it by its own
  16618. nature are sufficient; it is unnecessary for you to place over it
  16619. additional guards, as if its power were dangerous to the constitution of
  16620. the intellectual state. In the dialectic of reason there is no victory
  16621. gained which need in the least disturb your tranquility.
  16622. The strife of dialectic is a necessity of reason, and we cannot but wish
  16623. that it had been conducted long ere this with that perfect freedom which
  16624. ought to be its essential condition. In this case, we should have had at
  16625. an earlier period a matured and profound criticism, which must have
  16626. put an end to all dialectical disputes, by exposing the illusions and
  16627. prejudices in which they originated.
  16628. There is in human nature an unworthy propensity--a propensity which,
  16629. like everything that springs from nature, must in its final purpose be
  16630. conducive to the good of humanity--to conceal our real sentiments, and
  16631. to give expression only to certain received opinions, which are regarded
  16632. as at once safe and promotive of the common good. It is true, this
  16633. tendency, not only to conceal our real sentiments, but to profess those
  16634. which may gain us favour in the eyes of society, has not only civilized,
  16635. but, in a certain measure, moralized us; as no one can break through the
  16636. outward covering of respectability, honour, and morality, and thus
  16637. the seemingly-good examples which we which we see around us form an
  16638. excellent school for moral improvement, so long as our belief in
  16639. their genuineness remains unshaken. But this disposition to represent
  16640. ourselves as better than we are, and to utter opinions which are not
  16641. our own, can be nothing more than a kind of provisionary arrangement
  16642. of nature to lead us from the rudeness of an uncivilized state, and to
  16643. teach us how to assume at least the appearance and manner of the good we
  16644. see. But when true principles have been developed, and have obtained a
  16645. sure foundation in our habit of thought, this conventionalism must
  16646. be attacked with earnest vigour, otherwise it corrupts the heart, and
  16647. checks the growth of good dispositions with the mischievous weed of air
  16648. appearances.
  16649. I am sorry to remark the same tendency to misrepresentation and
  16650. hypocrisy in the sphere of speculative discussion, where there is less
  16651. temptation to restrain the free expression of thought. For what can be
  16652. more prejudicial to the interests of intelligence than to falsify our
  16653. real sentiments, to conceal the doubts which we feel in regard to our
  16654. statements, or to maintain the validity of grounds of proof which we
  16655. well know to be insufficient? So long as mere personal vanity is the
  16656. source of these unworthy artifices--and this is generally the case
  16657. in speculative discussions, which are mostly destitute of practical
  16658. interest, and are incapable of complete demonstration--the vanity of
  16659. the opposite party exaggerates as much on the other side; and thus the
  16660. result is the same, although it is not brought about so soon as if the
  16661. dispute had been conducted in a sincere and upright spirit. But
  16662. where the mass entertains the notion that the aim of certain subtle
  16663. speculators is nothing less than to shake the very foundations of public
  16664. welfare and morality--it seems not only prudent, but even praise worthy,
  16665. to maintain the good cause by illusory arguments, rather than to give to
  16666. our supposed opponents the advantage of lowering our declarations to the
  16667. moderate tone of a merely practical conviction, and of compelling us to
  16668. confess our inability to attain to apodeictic certainty in speculative
  16669. subjects. But we ought to reflect that there is nothing, in the
  16670. world more fatal to the maintenance of a good cause than deceit,
  16671. misrepresentation, and falsehood. That the strictest laws of honesty
  16672. should be observed in the discussion of a purely speculative subject is
  16673. the least requirement that can be made. If we could reckon with security
  16674. even upon so little, the conflict of speculative reason regarding the
  16675. important questions of God, immortality, and freedom, would have been
  16676. either decided long ago, or would very soon be brought to a conclusion.
  16677. But, in general, the uprightness of the defence stands in an inverse
  16678. ratio to the goodness of the cause; and perhaps more honesty and
  16679. fairness are shown by those who deny than by those who uphold these
  16680. doctrines.
  16681. I shall persuade myself, then, that I have readers who do not wish
  16682. to see a righteous cause defended by unfair arguments. Such will now
  16683. recognize the fact that, according to the principles of this Critique,
  16684. if we consider not what is, but what ought to be the case, there can be
  16685. really no polemic of pure reason. For how can two persons dispute about
  16686. a thing, the reality of which neither can present in actual or even in
  16687. possible experience? Each adopts the plan of meditating on his idea for
  16688. the purpose of drawing from the idea, if he can, what is more than the
  16689. idea, that is, the reality of the object which it indicates. How shall
  16690. they settle the dispute, since neither is able to make his assertions
  16691. directly comprehensible and certain, but must restrict himself to
  16692. attacking and confuting those of his opponent? All statements enounced
  16693. by pure reason transcend the conditions of possible experience, beyond
  16694. the sphere of which we can discover no criterion of truth, while
  16695. they are at the same time framed in accordance with the laws of the
  16696. understanding, which are applicable only to experience; and thus it is
  16697. the fate of all such speculative discussions that while the one party
  16698. attacks the weaker side of his opponent, he infallibly lays open his own
  16699. weaknesses.
  16700. The critique of pure reason may be regarded as the highest tribunal
  16701. for all speculative disputes; for it is not involved in these disputes,
  16702. which have an immediate relation to certain objects and not to the laws
  16703. of the mind, but is instituted for the purpose of determining the rights
  16704. and limits of reason.
  16705. Without the control of criticism, reason is, as it were, in a state
  16706. of nature, and can only establish its claims and assertions by war.
  16707. Criticism, on the contrary, deciding all questions according to the
  16708. fundamental laws of its own institution, secures to us the peace of
  16709. law and order, and enables us to discuss all differences in the more
  16710. tranquil manner of a legal process. In the former case, disputes are
  16711. ended by victory, which both sides may claim and which is followed by a
  16712. hollow armistice; in the latter, by a sentence, which, as it strikes
  16713. at the root of all speculative differences, ensures to all concerned a
  16714. lasting peace. The endless disputes of a dogmatizing reason compel us
  16715. to look for some mode of arriving at a settled decision by a critical
  16716. investigation of reason itself; just as Hobbes maintains that the state
  16717. of nature is a state of injustice and violence, and that we must leave
  16718. it and submit ourselves to the constraint of law, which indeed limits
  16719. individual freedom, but only that it may consist with the freedom of
  16720. others and with the common good of all.
  16721. This freedom will, among other things, permit of our openly stating the
  16722. difficulties and doubts which we are ourselves unable to solve, without
  16723. being decried on that account as turbulent and dangerous citizens.
  16724. This privilege forms part of the native rights of human reason, which
  16725. recognizes no other judge than the universal reason of humanity; and
  16726. as this reason is the source of all progress and improvement, such a
  16727. privilege is to be held sacred and inviolable. It is unwise, moreover,
  16728. to denounce as dangerous any bold assertions against, or rash attacks
  16729. upon, an opinion which is held by the largest and most moral class of
  16730. the community; for that would be giving them an importance which they
  16731. do not deserve. When I hear that the freedom of the will, the hope of
  16732. a future life, and the existence of God have been overthrown by the
  16733. arguments of some able writer, I feel a strong desire to read his
  16734. book; for I expect that he will add to my knowledge and impart greater
  16735. clearness and distinctness to my views by the argumentative power shown
  16736. in his writings. But I am perfectly certain, even before I have opened
  16737. the book, that he has not succeeded in a single point, not because
  16738. I believe I am in possession of irrefutable demonstrations of these
  16739. important propositions, but because this transcendental critique, which
  16740. has disclosed to me the power and the limits of pure reason, has fully
  16741. convinced me that, as it is insufficient to establish the affirmative,
  16742. it is as powerless, and even more so, to assure us of the truth of
  16743. the negative answer to these questions. From what source does this
  16744. free-thinker derive his knowledge that there is, for example, no Supreme
  16745. Being? This proposition lies out of the field of possible experience,
  16746. and, therefore, beyond the limits of human cognition. But I would not
  16747. read at, all the answer which the dogmatical maintainer of the good
  16748. cause makes to his opponent, because I know well beforehand, that he
  16749. will merely attack the fallacious grounds of his adversary, without
  16750. being able to establish his own assertions. Besides, a new illusory
  16751. argument, in the construction of which talent and acuteness are shown,
  16752. is suggestive of new ideas and new trains of reasoning, and in this
  16753. respect the old and everyday sophistries are quite useless. Again,
  16754. the dogmatical opponent of religion gives employment to criticism,
  16755. and enables us to test and correct its principles, while there is no
  16756. occasion for anxiety in regard to the influence and results of his
  16757. reasoning.
  16758. But, it will be said, must we not warn the youth entrusted to academical
  16759. care against such writings, must we not preserve them from the knowledge
  16760. of these dangerous assertions, until their judgement is ripened, or
  16761. rather until the doctrines which we wish to inculcate are so firmly
  16762. rooted in their minds as to withstand all attempts at instilling the
  16763. contrary dogmas, from whatever quarter they may come?
  16764. If we are to confine ourselves to the dogmatical procedure in the
  16765. sphere of pure reason, and find ourselves unable to settle such
  16766. disputes otherwise than by becoming a party in them, and setting
  16767. counter-assertions against the statements advanced by our opponents,
  16768. there is certainly no plan more advisable for the moment, but, at the
  16769. same time, none more absurd and inefficient for the future, than this
  16770. retaining of the youthful mind under guardianship for a time, and thus
  16771. preserving it--for so long at least--from seduction into error. But
  16772. when, at a later period, either curiosity, or the prevalent fashion
  16773. of thought places such writings in their hands, will the so-called
  16774. convictions of their youth stand firm? The young thinker, who has in his
  16775. armoury none but dogmatical weapons with which to resist the attacks of
  16776. his opponent, and who cannot detect the latent dialectic which lies in
  16777. his own opinions as well as in those of the opposite party, sees the
  16778. advance of illusory arguments and grounds of proof which have the
  16779. advantage of novelty, against as illusory grounds of proof destitute
  16780. of this advantage, and which, perhaps, excite the suspicion that the
  16781. natural credulity of his youth has been abused by his instructors. He
  16782. thinks he can find no better means of showing that he has out grown the
  16783. discipline of his minority than by despising those well-meant warnings,
  16784. and, knowing no system of thought but that of dogmatism, he drinks deep
  16785. draughts of the poison that is to sap the principles in which his early
  16786. years were trained.
  16787. Exactly the opposite of the system here recommended ought to be pursued
  16788. in academical instruction. This can only be effected, however, by a
  16789. thorough training in the critical investigation of pure reason. For, in
  16790. order to bring the principles of this critique into exercise as soon as
  16791. possible, and to demonstrate their perfect even in the presence of the
  16792. highest degree of dialectical illusion, the student ought to examine the
  16793. assertions made on both sides of speculative questions step by step, and
  16794. to test them by these principles. It cannot be a difficult task for him
  16795. to show the fallacies inherent in these propositions, and thus he begins
  16796. early to feel his own power of securing himself against the influence of
  16797. such sophistical arguments, which must finally lose, for him, all their
  16798. illusory power. And, although the same blows which overturn the edifice
  16799. of his opponent are as fatal to his own speculative structures, if such
  16800. he has wished to rear; he need not feel any sorrow in regard to this
  16801. seeming misfortune, as he has now before him a fair prospect into the
  16802. practical region in which he may reasonably hope to find a more secure
  16803. foundation for a rational system.
  16804. There is, accordingly, no proper polemic in the sphere of pure reason.
  16805. Both parties beat the air and fight with their own shadows, as they
  16806. pass beyond the limits of nature, and can find no tangible point
  16807. of attack--no firm footing for their dogmatical conflict. Fight as
  16808. vigorously as they may, the shadows which they hew down, immediately
  16809. start up again, like the heroes in Walhalla, and renew the bloodless and
  16810. unceasing contest.
  16811. But neither can we admit that there is any proper sceptical employment
  16812. of pure reason, such as might be based upon the principle of neutrality
  16813. in all speculative disputes. To excite reason against itself, to place
  16814. weapons in the hands of the party on the one side as well as in those of
  16815. the other, and to remain an undisturbed and sarcastic spectator of the
  16816. fierce struggle that ensues, seems, from the dogmatical point of view,
  16817. to be a part fitting only a malevolent disposition. But, when the
  16818. sophist evidences an invincible obstinacy and blindness, and a pride
  16819. which no criticism can moderate, there is no other practicable course
  16820. than to oppose to this pride and obstinacy similar feelings and
  16821. pretensions on the other side, equally well or ill founded, so that
  16822. reason, staggered by the reflections thus forced upon it, finds it
  16823. necessary to moderate its confidence in such pretensions and to listen
  16824. to the advice of criticism. But we cannot stop at these doubts, much
  16825. less regard the conviction of our ignorance, not only as a cure for the
  16826. conceit natural to dogmatism, but as the settlement of the disputes in
  16827. which reason is involved with itself. On the contrary, scepticism is
  16828. merely a means of awakening reason from its dogmatic dreams and exciting
  16829. it to a more careful investigation into its own powers and pretensions.
  16830. But, as scepticism appears to be the shortest road to a permanent peace
  16831. in the domain of philosophy, and as it is the track pursued by the
  16832. many who aim at giving a philosophical colouring to their contemptuous
  16833. dislike of all inquiries of this kind, I think it necessary to present
  16834. to my readers this mode of thought in its true light.
  16835. Scepticism not a Permanent State for Human Reason.
  16836. The consciousness of ignorance--unless this ignorance is recognized to
  16837. be absolutely necessary ought, instead of forming the conclusion of
  16838. my inquiries, to be the strongest motive to the pursuit of them. All
  16839. ignorance is either ignorance of things or of the limits of knowledge.
  16840. If my ignorance is accidental and not necessary, it must incite me, in
  16841. the first case, to a dogmatical inquiry regarding the objects of which I
  16842. am ignorant; in the second, to a critical investigation into the bounds
  16843. of all possible knowledge. But that my ignorance is absolutely necessary
  16844. and unavoidable, and that it consequently absolves from the duty of all
  16845. further investigation, is a fact which cannot be made out upon empirical
  16846. grounds--from observation--but upon critical grounds alone, that is, by
  16847. a thoroughgoing investigation into the primary sources of cognition. It
  16848. follows that the determination of the bounds of reason can be made only
  16849. on a priori grounds; while the empirical limitation of reason, which
  16850. is merely an indeterminate cognition of an ignorance that can never be
  16851. completely removed, can take place only a posteriori. In other words,
  16852. our empirical knowledge is limited by that which yet remains for us to
  16853. know. The former cognition of our ignorance, which is possible only on a
  16854. rational basis, is a science; the latter is merely a perception, and we
  16855. cannot say how far the inferences drawn from it may extend. If I regard
  16856. the earth, as it really appears to my senses, as a flat surface, I am
  16857. ignorant how far this surface extends. But experience teaches me that,
  16858. how far soever I go, I always see before me a space in which I can
  16859. proceed farther; and thus I know the limits--merely visual--of my actual
  16860. knowledge of the earth, although I am ignorant of the limits of the
  16861. earth itself. But if I have got so far as to know that the earth is a
  16862. sphere, and that its surface is spherical, I can cognize a priori and
  16863. determine upon principles, from my knowledge of a small part of this
  16864. surface--say to the extent of a degree--the diameter and circumference
  16865. of the earth; and although I am ignorant of the objects which this
  16866. surface contains, I have a perfect knowledge of its limits and extent.
  16867. The sum of all the possible objects of our cognition seems to us to be
  16868. a level surface, with an apparent horizon--that which forms the limit
  16869. of its extent, and which has been termed by us the idea of unconditioned
  16870. totality. To reach this limit by empirical means is impossible, and all
  16871. attempts to determine it a priori according to a principle, are alike in
  16872. vain. But all the questions raised by pure reason relate to that which
  16873. lies beyond this horizon, or, at least, in its boundary line.
  16874. The celebrated David Hume was one of those geographers of human reason
  16875. who believe that they have given a sufficient answer to all such
  16876. questions by declaring them to lie beyond the horizon of our
  16877. knowledge--a horizon which, however, Hume was unable to determine. His
  16878. attention especially was directed to the principle of causality; and he
  16879. remarked with perfect justice that the truth of this principle, and even
  16880. the objective validity of the conception of a cause, was not commonly
  16881. based upon clear insight, that is, upon a priori cognition. Hence
  16882. he concluded that this law does not derive its authority from its
  16883. universality and necessity, but merely from its general applicability
  16884. in the course of experience, and a kind of subjective necessity
  16885. thence arising, which he termed habit. From the inability of reason to
  16886. establish this principle as a necessary law for the acquisition of all
  16887. experience, he inferred the nullity of all the attempts of reason to
  16888. pass the region of the empirical.
  16889. This procedure of subjecting the facta of reason to examination, and,
  16890. if necessary, to disapproval, may be termed the censura of reason. This
  16891. censura must inevitably lead us to doubts regarding all transcendent
  16892. employment of principles. But this is only the second step in our
  16893. inquiry. The first step in regard to the subjects of pure reason, and
  16894. which marks the infancy of that faculty, is that of dogmatism. The
  16895. second, which we have just mentioned, is that of scepticism, and it
  16896. gives evidence that our judgement has been improved by experience. But
  16897. a third step is necessary--indicative of the maturity and manhood of the
  16898. judgement, which now lays a firm foundation upon universal and necessary
  16899. principles. This is the period of criticism, in which we do not examine
  16900. the facta of reason, but reason itself, in the whole extent of its
  16901. powers, and in regard to its capability of a priori cognition; and thus
  16902. we determine not merely the empirical and ever-shifting bounds of our
  16903. knowledge, but its necessary and eternal limits. We demonstrate from
  16904. indubitable principles, not merely our ignorance in respect to this
  16905. or that subject, but in regard to all possible questions of a certain
  16906. class. Thus scepticism is a resting place for reason, in which it may
  16907. reflect on its dogmatical wanderings and gain some knowledge of the
  16908. region in which it happens to be, that it may pursue its way with
  16909. greater certainty; but it cannot be its permanent dwelling-place. It
  16910. must take up its abode only in the region of complete certitude, whether
  16911. this relates to the cognition of objects themselves, or to the limits
  16912. which bound all our cognition.
  16913. Reason is not to be considered as an indefinitely extended plane, of the
  16914. bounds of which we have only a general knowledge; it ought rather to
  16915. be compared to a sphere, the radius of which may be found from the
  16916. curvature of its surface--that is, the nature of a priori synthetical
  16917. propositions--and, consequently, its circumference and extent. Beyond
  16918. the sphere of experience there are no objects which it can cognize; nay,
  16919. even questions regarding such supposititious objects relate only to the
  16920. subjective principles of a complete determination of the relations
  16921. which exist between the understanding-conceptions which lie within this
  16922. sphere.
  16923. We are actually in possession of a priori synthetical cognitions, as is
  16924. proved by the existence of the principles of the understanding, which
  16925. anticipate experience. If any one cannot comprehend the possibility
  16926. of these principles, he may have some reason to doubt whether they
  16927. are really a priori; but he cannot on this account declare them to be
  16928. impossible, and affirm the nullity of the steps which reason may have
  16929. taken under their guidance. He can only say: If we perceived their
  16930. origin and their authenticity, we should be able to determine the
  16931. extent and limits of reason; but, till we can do this, all propositions
  16932. regarding the latter are mere random assertions. In this view, the
  16933. doubt respecting all dogmatical philosophy, which proceeds without the
  16934. guidance of criticism, is well grounded; but we cannot therefore deny
  16935. to reason the ability to construct a sound philosophy, when the way has
  16936. been prepared by a thorough critical investigation. All the conceptions
  16937. produced, and all the questions raised, by pure reason, do not lie in
  16938. the sphere of experience, but in that of reason itself, and hence they
  16939. must be solved, and shown to be either valid or inadmissible, by that
  16940. faculty. We have no right to decline the solution of such problems, on
  16941. the ground that the solution can be discovered only from the nature of
  16942. things, and under pretence of the limitation of human faculties, for
  16943. reason is the sole creator of all these ideas, and is therefore bound
  16944. either to establish their validity or to expose their illusory nature.
  16945. The polemic of scepticism is properly directed against the dogmatist,
  16946. who erects a system of philosophy without having examined the
  16947. fundamental objective principles on which it is based, for the purpose
  16948. of evidencing the futility of his designs, and thus bringing him to a
  16949. knowledge of his own powers. But, in itself, scepticism does not give
  16950. us any certain information in regard to the bounds of our knowledge. All
  16951. unsuccessful dogmatical attempts of reason are facia, which it is always
  16952. useful to submit to the censure of the sceptic. But this cannot help
  16953. us to any decision regarding the expectations which reason cherishes of
  16954. better success in future endeavours; the investigations of scepticism
  16955. cannot, therefore, settle the dispute regarding the rights and powers of
  16956. human reason.
  16957. Hume is perhaps the ablest and most ingenious of all sceptical
  16958. philosophers, and his writings have, undoubtedly, exerted the most
  16959. powerful influence in awakening reason to a thorough investigation into
  16960. its own powers. It will, therefore, well repay our labours to consider
  16961. for a little the course of reasoning which he followed and the errors
  16962. into which he strayed, although setting out on the path of truth and
  16963. certitude.
  16964. Hume was probably aware, although he never clearly developed the notion,
  16965. that we proceed in judgements of a certain class beyond our conception
  16966. if the object. I have termed this kind of judgement synthetical. As
  16967. regard the manner in which I pass beyond my conception by the aid
  16968. of experience, no doubts can be entertained. Experience is itself a
  16969. synthesis of perceptions; and it employs perceptions to increment the
  16970. conception, which I obtain by means of another perception. But we feel
  16971. persuaded that we are able to proceed beyond a conception, and to extend
  16972. our cognition a priori. We attempt this in two ways--either, through the
  16973. pure understanding, in relation to that which may become an object of
  16974. experience, or, through pure reason, in relation to such properties of
  16975. things, or of the existence of things, as can never be presented in any
  16976. experience. This sceptical philosopher did not distinguish these
  16977. two kinds of judgements, as he ought to have done, but regarded this
  16978. augmentation of conceptions, and, if we may so express ourselves, the
  16979. spontaneous generation of understanding and reason, independently of the
  16980. impregnation of experience, as altogether impossible. The so-called a
  16981. priori principles of these faculties he consequently held to be invalid
  16982. and imaginary, and regarded them as nothing but subjective habits of
  16983. thought originating in experience, and therefore purely empirical
  16984. and contingent rules, to which we attribute a spurious necessity and
  16985. universality. In support of this strange assertion, he referred us to
  16986. the generally acknowledged principle of the relation between cause and
  16987. effect. No faculty of the mind can conduct us from the conception of a
  16988. thing to the existence of something else; and hence he believed he could
  16989. infer that, without experience, we possess no source from which we can
  16990. augment a conception, and no ground sufficient to justify us in framing
  16991. a judgement that is to extend our cognition a priori. That the light of
  16992. the sun, which shines upon a piece of wax, at the same time melts it,
  16993. while it hardens clay, no power of the understanding could infer from
  16994. the conceptions which we previously possessed of these substances;
  16995. much less is there any a priori law that could conduct us to such a
  16996. conclusion, which experience alone can certify. On the other hand, we
  16997. have seen in our discussion of transcendental logic, that, although we
  16998. can never proceed immediately beyond the content of the conception which
  16999. is given us, we can always cognize completely a priori--in relation,
  17000. however, to a third term, namely, possible experience--the law of its
  17001. connection with other things. For example, if I observe that a piece of
  17002. wax melts, I can cognize a priori that there must have been something
  17003. (the sun's heat) preceding, which this law; although, without the aid
  17004. of experience, I could not cognize a priori and in a determinate manner
  17005. either the cause from the effect, or the effect from the cause.
  17006. Hume was, therefore, wrong in inferring, from the contingency of the
  17007. determination according to law, the contingency of the law itself; and
  17008. the passing beyond the conception of a thing to possible experience
  17009. (which is an a priori proceeding, constituting the objective reality of
  17010. the conception), he confounded with our synthesis of objects in actual
  17011. experience, which is always, of course, empirical. Thus, too,
  17012. he regarded the principle of affinity, which has its seat in the
  17013. understanding and indicates a necessary connection, as a mere rule of
  17014. association, lying in the imitative faculty of imagination, which can
  17015. present only contingent, and not objective connections.
  17016. The sceptical errors of this remarkably acute thinker arose principally
  17017. from a defect, which was common to him with the dogmatists, namely, that
  17018. he had never made a systematic review of all the different kinds of
  17019. a priori synthesis performed by the understanding. Had he done so, he
  17020. would have found, to take one example among many, that the principle of
  17021. permanence was of this character, and that it, as well as the principle
  17022. of causality, anticipates experience. In this way he might have been
  17023. able to describe the determinate limits of the a priori operations of
  17024. understanding and reason. But he merely declared the understanding to be
  17025. limited, instead of showing what its limits were; he created a
  17026. general mistrust in the power of our faculties, without giving us any
  17027. determinate knowledge of the bounds of our necessary and unavoidable
  17028. ignorance; he examined and condemned some of the principles of
  17029. the understanding, without investigating all its powers with the
  17030. completeness necessary to criticism. He denies, with truth, certain
  17031. powers to the understanding, but he goes further, and declares it to be
  17032. utterly inadequate to the a priori extension of knowledge, although he
  17033. has not fully examined all the powers which reside in the faculty; and
  17034. thus the fate which always overtakes scepticism meets him too. That is
  17035. to say, his own declarations are doubted, for his objections were based
  17036. upon facta, which are contingent, and not upon principles, which can
  17037. alone demonstrate the necessary invalidity of all dogmatical assertions.
  17038. As Hume makes no distinction between the well-grounded claims of the
  17039. understanding and the dialectical pretensions of reason, against which,
  17040. however, his attacks are mainly directed, reason does not feel itself
  17041. shut out from all attempts at the extension of a priori cognition, and
  17042. hence it refuses, in spite of a few checks in this or that quarter, to
  17043. relinquish such efforts. For one naturally arms oneself to resist an
  17044. attack, and becomes more obstinate in the resolve to establish the
  17045. claims he has advanced. But a complete review of the powers of reason,
  17046. and the conviction thence arising that we are in possession of a limited
  17047. field of action, while we must admit the vanity of higher claims, puts
  17048. an end to all doubt and dispute, and induces reason to rest satisfied
  17049. with the undisturbed possession of its limited domain.
  17050. To the uncritical dogmatist, who has not surveyed the sphere of his
  17051. understanding, nor determined, in accordance with principles, the limits
  17052. of possible cognition, who, consequently, is ignorant of his own powers,
  17053. and believes he will discover them by the attempts he makes in the field
  17054. of cognition, these attacks of scepticism are not only dangerous, but
  17055. destructive. For if there is one proposition in his chain of reasoning
  17056. which be he cannot prove, or the fallacy in which he cannot evolve in
  17057. accordance with a principle, suspicion falls on all his statements,
  17058. however plausible they may appear.
  17059. And thus scepticism, the bane of dogmatical philosophy, conducts us to
  17060. a sound investigation into the understanding and the reason. When we are
  17061. thus far advanced, we need fear no further attacks; for the limits of
  17062. our domain are clearly marked out, and we can make no claims nor become
  17063. involved in any disputes regarding the region that lies beyond these
  17064. limits. Thus the sceptical procedure in philosophy does not present any
  17065. solution of the problems of reason, but it forms an excellent exercise
  17066. for its powers, awakening its circumspection, and indicating the
  17067. means whereby it may most fully establish its claims to its legitimate
  17068. possessions.
  17069. SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis.
  17070. This critique of reason has now taught us that all its efforts to extend
  17071. the bounds of knowledge, by means of pure speculation, are utterly
  17072. fruitless. So much the wider field, it may appear, lies open to
  17073. hypothesis; as, where we cannot know with certainty, we are at liberty
  17074. to make guesses and to form suppositions.
  17075. Imagination may be allowed, under the strict surveillance of reason,
  17076. to invent suppositions; but, these must be based on something that is
  17077. perfectly certain--and that is the possibility of the object. If we
  17078. are well assured upon this point, it is allowable to have recourse to
  17079. supposition in regard to the reality of the object; but this supposition
  17080. must, unless it is utterly groundless, be connected, as its ground of
  17081. explanation, with that which is really given and absolutely certain.
  17082. Such a supposition is termed a hypothesis.
  17083. It is beyond our power to form the least conception a priori of the
  17084. possibility of dynamical connection in phenomena; and the category
  17085. of the pure understanding will not enable us to excogitate any such
  17086. connection, but merely helps us to understand it, when we meet with
  17087. it in experience. For this reason we cannot, in accordance with the
  17088. categories, imagine or invent any object or any property of an object
  17089. not given, or that may not be given in experience, and employ it in a
  17090. hypothesis; otherwise, we should be basing our chain of reasoning upon
  17091. mere chimerical fancies, and not upon conceptions of things. Thus, we
  17092. have no right to assume the existence of new powers, not existing in
  17093. nature--for example, an understanding with a non-sensuous intuition,
  17094. a force of attraction without contact, or some new kind of substances
  17095. occupying space, and yet without the property of impenetrability--and,
  17096. consequently, we cannot assume that there is any other kind of community
  17097. among substances than that observable in experience, any kind of
  17098. presence than that in space, or any kind of duration than that in time.
  17099. In one word, the conditions of possible experience are for reason the
  17100. only conditions of the possibility of things; reason cannot venture
  17101. to form, independently of these conditions, any conceptions of things,
  17102. because such conceptions, although not self-contradictory, are without
  17103. object and without application.
  17104. The conceptions of reason are, as we have already shown, mere ideas, and
  17105. do not relate to any object in any kind of experience. At the same time,
  17106. they do not indicate imaginary or possible objects. They are purely
  17107. problematical in their nature and, as aids to the heuristic exercise
  17108. of the faculties, form the basis of the regulative principles for the
  17109. systematic employment of the understanding in the field of experience.
  17110. If we leave this ground of experience, they become mere fictions of
  17111. thought, the possibility of which is quite indemonstrable; and they
  17112. cannot, consequently, be employed as hypotheses in the explanation of
  17113. real phenomena. It is quite admissible to cogitate the soul as simple,
  17114. for the purpose of enabling ourselves to employ the idea of a perfect
  17115. and necessary unity of all the faculties of the mind as the principle
  17116. of all our inquiries into its internal phenomena, although we cannot
  17117. cognize this unity in concreto. But to assume that the soul is a simple
  17118. substance (a transcendental conception) would be enouncing a proposition
  17119. which is not only indemonstrable--as many physical hypotheses are--but
  17120. a proposition which is purely arbitrary, and in the highest degree rash.
  17121. The simple is never presented in experience; and, if by substance is
  17122. here meant the permanent object of sensuous intuition, the possibility
  17123. of a simple phenomenon is perfectly inconceivable. Reason affords no
  17124. good grounds for admitting the existence of intelligible beings, or
  17125. of intelligible properties of sensuous things, although--as we have no
  17126. conception either of their possibility or of their impossibility--it
  17127. will always be out of our power to affirm dogmatically that they do not
  17128. exist. In the explanation of given phenomena, no other things and no
  17129. other grounds of explanation can be employed than those which stand
  17130. in connection with the given phenomena according to the known laws of
  17131. experience. A transcendental hypothesis, in which a mere idea of reason
  17132. is employed to explain the phenomena of nature, would not give us any
  17133. better insight into a phenomenon, as we should be trying to explain what
  17134. we do not sufficiently understand from known empirical principles, by
  17135. what we do not understand at all. The principles of such a hypothesis
  17136. might conduce to the satisfaction of reason, but it would not assist
  17137. the understanding in its application to objects. Order and conformity to
  17138. aims in the sphere of nature must be themselves explained upon natural
  17139. grounds and according to natural laws; and the wildest hypotheses, if
  17140. they are only physical, are here more admissible than a hyperphysical
  17141. hypothesis, such as that of a divine author. For such a hypothesis would
  17142. introduce the principle of ignava ratio, which requires us to give
  17143. up the search for causes that might be discovered in the course of
  17144. experience and to rest satisfied with a mere idea. As regards the
  17145. absolute totality of the grounds of explanation in the series of these
  17146. causes, this can be no hindrance to the understanding in the case of
  17147. phenomena; because, as they are to us nothing more than phenomena, we
  17148. have no right to look for anything like completeness in the synthesis of
  17149. the series of their conditions.
  17150. Transcendental hypotheses are therefore inadmissible; and we cannot
  17151. use the liberty of employing, in the absence of physical, hyperphysical
  17152. grounds of explanation. And this for two reasons; first, because such
  17153. hypothesis do not advance reason, but rather stop it in its progress;
  17154. secondly, because this licence would render fruitless all its exertions
  17155. in its own proper sphere, which is that of experience. For, when the
  17156. explanation of natural phenomena happens to be difficult, we have
  17157. constantly at hand a transcendental ground of explanation, which lifts
  17158. us above the necessity of investigating nature; and our inquiries are
  17159. brought to a close, not because we have obtained all the
  17160. requisite knowledge, but because we abut upon a principle which is
  17161. incomprehensible and which, indeed, is so far back in the track of
  17162. thought as to contain the conception of the absolutely primal being.
  17163. The next requisite for the admissibility of a hypothesis is its
  17164. sufficiency. That is, it must determine a priori the consequences
  17165. which are given in experience and which are supposed to follow from the
  17166. hypothesis itself. If we require to employ auxiliary hypotheses, the
  17167. suspicion naturally arises that they are mere fictions; because the
  17168. necessity for each of them requires the same justification as in the
  17169. case of the original hypothesis, and thus their testimony is invalid.
  17170. If we suppose the existence of an infinitely perfect cause, we possess
  17171. sufficient grounds for the explanation of the conformity to aims, the
  17172. order and the greatness which we observe in the universe; but we
  17173. find ourselves obliged, when we observe the evil in the world and the
  17174. exceptions to these laws, to employ new hypothesis in support of the
  17175. original one. We employ the idea of the simple nature of the human soul
  17176. as the foundation of all the theories we may form of its phenomena; but
  17177. when we meet with difficulties in our way, when we observe in the soul
  17178. phenomena similar to the changes which take place in matter, we require
  17179. to call in new auxiliary hypotheses. These may, indeed, not be false,
  17180. but we do not know them to be true, because the only witness to their
  17181. certitude is the hypothesis which they themselves have been called in to
  17182. explain.
  17183. We are not discussing the above-mentioned assertions regarding the
  17184. immaterial unity of the soul and the existence of a Supreme Being as
  17185. dogmata, which certain philosophers profess to demonstrate a priori, but
  17186. purely as hypotheses. In the former case, the dogmatist must take care
  17187. that his arguments possess the apodeictic certainty of a demonstration.
  17188. For the assertion that the reality of such ideas is probable is as
  17189. absurd as a proof of the probability of a proposition in geometry. Pure
  17190. abstract reason, apart from all experience, can either cognize nothing
  17191. at all; and hence the judgements it enounces are never mere opinions,
  17192. they are either apodeictic certainties, or declarations that nothing can
  17193. be known on the subject. Opinions and probable judgements on the nature
  17194. of things can only be employed to explain given phenomena, or they may
  17195. relate to the effect, in accordance with empirical laws, of an actually
  17196. existing cause. In other words, we must restrict the sphere of opinion
  17197. to the world of experience and nature. Beyond this region opinion is
  17198. mere invention; unless we are groping about for the truth on a path not
  17199. yet fully known, and have some hopes of stumbling upon it by chance.
  17200. But, although hypotheses are inadmissible in answers to the questions
  17201. of pure speculative reason, they may be employed in the defence of these
  17202. answers. That is to say, hypotheses are admissible in polemic, but
  17203. not in the sphere of dogmatism. By the defence of statements of this
  17204. character, I do not mean an attempt at discovering new grounds for their
  17205. support, but merely the refutation of the arguments of opponents. All a
  17206. priori synthetical propositions possess the peculiarity that, although
  17207. the philosopher who maintains the reality of the ideas contained in the
  17208. proposition is not in possession of sufficient knowledge to establish
  17209. the certainty of his statements, his opponent is as little able to prove
  17210. the truth of the opposite. This equality of fortune does not allow
  17211. the one party to be superior to the other in the sphere of speculative
  17212. cognition; and it is this sphere, accordingly, that is the proper arena
  17213. of these endless speculative conflicts. But we shall afterwards show
  17214. that, in relation to its practical exercise, Reason has the right of
  17215. admitting what, in the field of pure speculation, she would not be
  17216. justified in supposing, except upon perfectly sufficient grounds;
  17217. because all such suppositions destroy the necessary completeness of
  17218. speculation--a condition which the practical reason, however, does not
  17219. consider to be requisite. In this sphere, therefore, Reason is
  17220. mistress of a possession, her title to which she does not require to
  17221. prove--which, in fact, she could not do. The burden of proof accordingly
  17222. rests upon the opponent. But as he has just as little knowledge
  17223. regarding the subject discussed, and is as little able to prove the
  17224. non-existence of the object of an idea, as the philosopher on the other
  17225. side is to demonstrate its reality, it is evident that there is an
  17226. advantage on the side of the philosopher who maintains his proposition
  17227. as a practically necessary supposition (melior est conditio
  17228. possidentis). For he is at liberty to employ, in self-defence, the same
  17229. weapons as his opponent makes use of in attacking him; that is, he has a
  17230. right to use hypotheses not for the purpose of supporting the arguments
  17231. in favour of his own propositions, but to show that his opponent knows
  17232. no more than himself regarding the subject under 'discussion and cannot
  17233. boast of any speculative advantage.
  17234. Hypotheses are, therefore, admissible in the sphere of pure reason
  17235. only as weapons for self-defence, and not as supports to dogmatical
  17236. assertions. But the opposing party we must always seek for in ourselves.
  17237. For speculative reason is, in the sphere of transcendentalism,
  17238. dialectical in its own nature. The difficulties and objections we have
  17239. to fear lie in ourselves. They are like old but never superannuated
  17240. claims; and we must seek them out, and settle them once and for ever, if
  17241. we are to expect a permanent peace. External tranquility is hollow and
  17242. unreal. The root of these contradictions, which lies in the nature of
  17243. human reason, must be destroyed; and this can only be done by giving it,
  17244. in the first instance, freedom to grow, nay, by nourishing it, that it
  17245. may send out shoots, and thus betray its own existence. It is our duty,
  17246. therefore, to try to discover new objections, to put weapons in the
  17247. bands of our opponent, and to grant him the most favourable position
  17248. in the arena that he can wish. We have nothing to fear from these
  17249. concessions; on the contrary, we may rather hope that we shall thus
  17250. make ourselves master of a possession which no one will ever venture to
  17251. dispute.
  17252. The thinker requires, to be fully equipped, the hypotheses of pure
  17253. reason, which, although but leaden weapons (for they have not been
  17254. steeled in the armoury of experience), are as useful as any that can
  17255. be employed by his opponents. If, accordingly, we have assumed, from a
  17256. non-speculative point of view, the immaterial nature of the soul, and
  17257. are met by the objection that experience seems to prove that the growth
  17258. and decay of our mental faculties are mere modifications of the sensuous
  17259. organism--we can weaken the force of this objection by the assumption
  17260. that the body is nothing but the fundamental phenomenon, to which, as
  17261. a necessary condition, all sensibility, and consequently all thought,
  17262. relates in the present state of our existence; and that the separation
  17263. of soul and body forms the conclusion of the sensuous exercise of our
  17264. power of cognition and the beginning of the intellectual. The body
  17265. would, in this view of the question, be regarded, not as the cause of
  17266. thought, but merely as its restrictive condition, as promotive of the
  17267. sensuous and animal, but as a hindrance to the pure and spiritual life;
  17268. and the dependence of the animal life on the constitution of the body,
  17269. would not prove that the whole life of man was also dependent on the
  17270. state of the organism. We might go still farther, and discover new
  17271. objections, or carry out to their extreme consequences those which have
  17272. already been adduced.
  17273. Generation, in the human race as well as among the irrational animals,
  17274. depends on so many accidents--of occasion, of proper sustenance, of the
  17275. laws enacted by the government of a country of vice even, that it is
  17276. difficult to believe in the eternal existence of a being whose life has
  17277. begun under circumstances so mean and trivial, and so entirely dependent
  17278. upon our own control. As regards the continuance of the existence of the
  17279. whole race, we need have no difficulties, for accident in single cases
  17280. is subject to general laws; but, in the case of each individual, it
  17281. would seem as if we could hardly expect so wonderful an effect from
  17282. causes so insignificant. But, in answer to these objections, we
  17283. may adduce the transcendental hypothesis that all life is properly
  17284. intelligible, and not subject to changes of time, and that it neither
  17285. began in birth, nor will end in death. We may assume that this life is
  17286. nothing more than a sensuous representation of pure spiritual life; that
  17287. the whole world of sense is but an image, hovering before the faculty of
  17288. cognition which we exercise in this sphere, and with no more objective
  17289. reality than a dream; and that if we could intuite ourselves and
  17290. other things as they really are, we should see ourselves in a world of
  17291. spiritual natures, our connection with which did not begin at our birth
  17292. and will not cease with the destruction of the body. And so on.
  17293. We cannot be said to know what has been above asserted, nor do we
  17294. seriously maintain the truth of these assertions; and the notions
  17295. therein indicated are not even ideas of reason, they are purely
  17296. fictitious conceptions. But this hypothetical procedure is in perfect
  17297. conformity with the laws of reason. Our opponent mistakes the absence
  17298. of empirical conditions for a proof of the complete impossibility of all
  17299. that we have asserted; and we have to show him that he has not exhausted
  17300. the whole sphere of possibility and that he can as little compass that
  17301. sphere by the laws of experience and nature, as we can lay a secure
  17302. foundation for the operations of reason beyond the region of experience.
  17303. Such hypothetical defences against the pretensions of an opponent must
  17304. not be regarded as declarations of opinion. The philosopher abandons
  17305. them, so soon as the opposite party renounces its dogmatical conceit.
  17306. To maintain a simply negative position in relation to propositions which
  17307. rest on an insecure foundation, well befits the moderation of a true
  17308. philosopher; but to uphold the objections urged against an opponent as
  17309. proofs of the opposite statement is a proceeding just as unwarrantable
  17310. and arrogant as it is to attack the position of a philosopher who
  17311. advances affirmative propositions regarding such a subject.
  17312. It is evident, therefore, that hypotheses, in the speculative sphere,
  17313. are valid, not as independent propositions, but only relatively to
  17314. opposite transcendent assumptions. For, to make the principles of
  17315. possible experience conditions of the possibility of things in general
  17316. is just as transcendent a procedure as to maintain the objective reality
  17317. of ideas which can be applied to no objects except such as lie without
  17318. the limits of possible experience. The judgements enounced by pure
  17319. reason must be necessary, or they must not be enounced at all. Reason
  17320. cannot trouble herself with opinions. But the hypotheses we have been
  17321. discussing are merely problematical judgements, which can neither be
  17322. confuted nor proved; while, therefore, they are not personal opinions,
  17323. they are indispensable as answers to objections which are liable to
  17324. be raised. But we must take care to confine them to this function,
  17325. and guard against any assumption on their part of absolute validity, a
  17326. proceeding which would involve reason in inextricable difficulties and
  17327. contradictions.
  17328. SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs.
  17329. It is a peculiarity, which distinguishes the proofs of transcendental
  17330. synthetical propositions from those of all other a priori synthetical
  17331. cognitions, that reason, in the case of the former, does not apply its
  17332. conceptions directly to an object, but is first obliged to prove, a
  17333. priori, the objective validity of these conceptions and the possibility
  17334. of their syntheses. This is not merely a prudential rule, it is
  17335. essential to the very possibility of the proof of a transcendental
  17336. proposition. If I am required to pass, a priori, beyond the conception
  17337. of an object, I find that it is utterly impossible without the guidance
  17338. of something which is not contained in the conception. In mathematics,
  17339. it is a priori intuition that guides my synthesis; and, in this case,
  17340. all our conclusions may be drawn immediately from pure intuition.
  17341. In transcendental cognition, so long as we are dealing only with
  17342. conceptions of the understanding, we are guided by possible experience.
  17343. That is to say, a proof in the sphere of transcendental cognition does
  17344. not show that the given conception (that of an event, for example) leads
  17345. directly to another conception (that of a cause)--for this would be a
  17346. saltus which nothing can justify; but it shows that experience itself,
  17347. and consequently the object of experience, is impossible without the
  17348. connection indicated by these conceptions. It follows that such a
  17349. proof must demonstrate the possibility of arriving, synthetically and a
  17350. priori, at a certain knowledge of things, which was not contained in our
  17351. conceptions of these things. Unless we pay particular attention to this
  17352. requirement, our proofs, instead of pursuing the straight path indicated
  17353. by reason, follow the tortuous road of mere subjective association. The
  17354. illusory conviction, which rests upon subjective causes of association,
  17355. and which is considered as resulting from the perception of a real and
  17356. objective natural affinity, is always open to doubt and suspicion.
  17357. For this reason, all the attempts which have been made to prove the
  17358. principle of sufficient reason, have, according to the universal
  17359. admission of philosophers, been quite unsuccessful; and, before the
  17360. appearance of transcendental criticism, it was considered better, as
  17361. this principle could not be abandoned, to appeal boldly to the common
  17362. sense of mankind (a proceeding which always proves that the problem,
  17363. which reason ought to solve, is one in which philosophers find great
  17364. difficulties), rather than attempt to discover new dogmatical proofs.
  17365. But, if the proposition to be proved is a proposition of pure reason,
  17366. and if I aim at passing beyond my empirical conceptions by the aid of
  17367. mere ideas, it is necessary that the proof should first show that such
  17368. a step in synthesis is possible (which it is not), before it proceeds
  17369. to prove the truth of the proposition itself. The so-called proof of
  17370. the simple nature of the soul from the unity of apperception, is a very
  17371. plausible one. But it contains no answer to the objection, that, as
  17372. the notion of absolute simplicity is not a conception which is directly
  17373. applicable to a perception, but is an idea which must be inferred--if
  17374. at all--from observation, it is by no means evident how the mere fact of
  17375. consciousness, which is contained in all thought, although in so far a
  17376. simple representation, can conduct me to the consciousness and cognition
  17377. of a thing which is purely a thinking substance. When I represent to my
  17378. mind the power of my body as in motion, my body in this thought is so
  17379. far absolute unity, and my representation of it is a simple one; and
  17380. hence I can indicate this representation by the motion of a point,
  17381. because I have made abstraction of the size or volume of the body. But
  17382. I cannot hence infer that, given merely the moving power of a body,
  17383. the body may be cogitated as simple substance, merely because the
  17384. representation in my mind takes no account of its content in space, and
  17385. is consequently simple. The simple, in abstraction, is very different
  17386. from the objectively simple; and hence the Ego, which is simple in the
  17387. first sense, may, in the second sense, as indicating the soul itself,
  17388. be a very complex conception, with a very various content. Thus it is
  17389. evident that in all such arguments there lurks a paralogism. We guess
  17390. (for without some such surmise our suspicion would not be excited
  17391. in reference to a proof of this character) at the presence of the
  17392. paralogism, by keeping ever before us a criterion of the possibility of
  17393. those synthetical propositions which aim at proving more than experience
  17394. can teach us. This criterion is obtained from the observation that such
  17395. proofs do not lead us directly from the subject of the proposition to
  17396. be proved to the required predicate, but find it necessary to presuppose
  17397. the possibility of extending our cognition a priori by means of ideas.
  17398. We must, accordingly, always use the greatest caution; we require,
  17399. before attempting any proof, to consider how it is possible to extend
  17400. the sphere of cognition by the operations of pure reason, and from
  17401. what source we are to derive knowledge, which is not obtained from
  17402. the analysis of conceptions, nor relates, by anticipation, to possible
  17403. experience. We shall thus spare ourselves much severe and fruitless
  17404. labour, by not expecting from reason what is beyond its power, or rather
  17405. by subjecting it to discipline, and teaching it to moderate its vehement
  17406. desires for the extension of the sphere of cognition.
  17407. The first rule for our guidance is, therefore, not to attempt a
  17408. transcendental proof, before we have considered from what source we are
  17409. to derive the principles upon which the proof is to be based, and what
  17410. right we have to expect that our conclusions from these principles will
  17411. be veracious. If they are principles of the understanding, it is vain to
  17412. expect that we should attain by their means to ideas of pure reason;
  17413. for these principles are valid only in regard to objects of possible
  17414. experience. If they are principles of pure reason, our labour is alike
  17415. in vain. For the principles of reason, if employed as objective, are
  17416. without exception dialectical and possess no validity or truth, except
  17417. as regulative principles of the systematic employment of reason in
  17418. experience. But when such delusive proof are presented to us, it is
  17419. our duty to meet them with the non liquet of a matured judgement; and,
  17420. although we are unable to expose the particular sophism upon which the
  17421. proof is based, we have a right to demand a deduction of the principles
  17422. employed in it; and, if these principles have their origin in pure
  17423. reason alone, such a deduction is absolutely impossible. And thus it
  17424. is unnecessary that we should trouble ourselves with the exposure and
  17425. confutation of every sophistical illusion; we may, at once, bring all
  17426. dialectic, which is inexhaustible in the production of fallacies, before
  17427. the bar of critical reason, which tests the principles upon which all
  17428. dialectical procedure is based. The second peculiarity of transcendental
  17429. proof is that a transcendental proposition cannot rest upon more than
  17430. a single proof. If I am drawing conclusions, not from conceptions, but
  17431. from intuition corresponding to a conception, be it pure intuition, as
  17432. in mathematics, or empirical, as in natural science, the intuition which
  17433. forms the basis of my inferences presents me with materials for many
  17434. synthetical propositions, which I can connect in various modes, while,
  17435. as it is allowable to proceed from different points in the intention, I
  17436. can arrive by different paths at the same proposition.
  17437. But every transcendental proposition sets out from a conception,
  17438. and posits the synthetical condition of the possibility of an object
  17439. according to this conception. There must, therefore, be but one ground
  17440. of proof, because it is the conception alone which determines the
  17441. object; and thus the proof cannot contain anything more than the
  17442. determination of the object according to the conception. In our
  17443. Transcendental Analytic, for example, we inferred the principle: Every
  17444. event has a cause, from the only condition of the objective possibility
  17445. of our conception of an event. This is that an event cannot be
  17446. determined in time, and consequently cannot form a part of experience,
  17447. unless it stands under this dynamical law. This is the only possible
  17448. ground of proof; for our conception of an event possesses objective
  17449. validity, that is, is a true conception, only because the law of
  17450. causality determines an object to which it can refer. Other arguments
  17451. in support of this principle have been attempted--such as that from the
  17452. contingent nature of a phenomenon; but when this argument is considered,
  17453. we can discover no criterion of contingency, except the fact of an
  17454. event--of something happening, that is to say, the existence which is
  17455. preceded by the non-existence of an object, and thus we fall back on the
  17456. very thing to be proved. If the proposition: "Every thinking being is
  17457. simple," is to be proved, we keep to the conception of the ego, which
  17458. is simple, and to which all thought has a relation. The same is the
  17459. case with the transcendental proof of the existence of a Deity, which is
  17460. based solely upon the harmony and reciprocal fitness of the conceptions
  17461. of an ens realissimum and a necessary being, and cannot be attempted in
  17462. any other manner.
  17463. This caution serves to simplify very much the criticism of all
  17464. propositions of reason. When reason employs conceptions alone, only one
  17465. proof of its thesis is possible, if any. When, therefore, the dogmatist
  17466. advances with ten arguments in favour of a proposition, we may be sure
  17467. that not one of them is conclusive. For if he possessed one which proved
  17468. the proposition he brings forward to demonstration--as must always be
  17469. the case with the propositions of pure reason--what need is there for
  17470. any more? His intention can only be similar to that of the advocate who
  17471. had different arguments for different judges; this availing himself of
  17472. the weakness of those who examine his arguments, who, without going into
  17473. any profound investigation, adopt the view of the case which seems most
  17474. probable at first sight and decide according to it.
  17475. The third rule for the guidance of pure reason in the conduct of a proof
  17476. is that all transcendental proofs must never be apagogic or indirect,
  17477. but always ostensive or direct. The direct or ostensive proof not only
  17478. establishes the truth of the proposition to be proved, but exposes the
  17479. grounds of its truth; the apagogic, on the other hand, may assure us of
  17480. the truth of the proposition, but it cannot enable us to comprehend
  17481. the grounds of its possibility. The latter is, accordingly, rather an
  17482. auxiliary to an argument, than a strictly philosophical and rational
  17483. mode of procedure. In one respect, however, they have an advantage over
  17484. direct proofs, from the fact that the mode of arguing by contradiction,
  17485. which they employ, renders our understanding of the question more
  17486. clear, and approximates the proof to the certainty of an intuitional
  17487. demonstration.
  17488. The true reason why indirect proofs are employed in different sciences
  17489. is this. When the grounds upon which we seek to base a cognition are too
  17490. various or too profound, we try whether or not we may not discover
  17491. the truth of our cognition from its consequences. The modus ponens of
  17492. reasoning from the truth of its inferences to the truth of a proposition
  17493. would be admissible if all the inferences that can be drawn from it are
  17494. known to be true; for in this case there can be only one possible ground
  17495. for these inferences, and that is the true one. But this is a quite
  17496. impracticable procedure, as it surpasses all our powers to discover all
  17497. the possible inferences that can be drawn from a proposition. But this
  17498. mode of reasoning is employed, under favour, when we wish to prove
  17499. the truth of an hypothesis; in which case we admit the truth of the
  17500. conclusion--which is supported by analogy--that, if all the inferences
  17501. we have drawn and examined agree with the proposition assumed, all
  17502. other possible inferences will also agree with it. But, in this way, an
  17503. hypothesis can never be established as a demonstrated truth. The modus
  17504. tollens of reasoning from known inferences to the unknown proposition,
  17505. is not only a rigorous, but a very easy mode of proof. For, if it can
  17506. be shown that but one inference from a proposition is false, then the
  17507. proposition must itself be false. Instead, then, of examining, in an
  17508. ostensive argument, the whole series of the grounds on which the
  17509. truth of a proposition rests, we need only take the opposite of this
  17510. proposition, and if one inference from it be false, then must the
  17511. opposite be itself false; and, consequently, the proposition which we
  17512. wished to prove must be true.
  17513. The apagogic method of proof is admissible only in those sciences where
  17514. it is impossible to mistake a subjective representation for an objective
  17515. cognition. Where this is possible, it is plain that the opposite of a
  17516. given proposition may contradict merely the subjective conditions of
  17517. thought, and not the objective cognition; or it may happen that both
  17518. propositions contradict each other only under a subjective condition,
  17519. which is incorrectly considered to be objective, and, as the condition
  17520. is itself false, both propositions may be false, and it will,
  17521. consequently, be impossible to conclude the truth of the one from the
  17522. falseness of the other.
  17523. In mathematics such subreptions are impossible; and it is in this
  17524. science, accordingly, that the indirect mode of proof has its true
  17525. place. In the science of nature, where all assertion is based upon
  17526. empirical intuition, such subreptions may be guarded against by the
  17527. repeated comparison of observations; but this mode of proof is of little
  17528. value in this sphere of knowledge. But the transcendental efforts of
  17529. pure reason are all made in the sphere of the subjective, which is the
  17530. real medium of all dialectical illusion; and thus reason endeavours,
  17531. in its premisses, to impose upon us subjective representations for
  17532. objective cognitions. In the transcendental sphere of pure reason,
  17533. then, and in the case of synthetical propositions, it is inadmissible
  17534. to support a statement by disproving the counter-statement. For only
  17535. two cases are possible; either, the counter-statement is nothing but
  17536. the enouncement of the inconsistency of the opposite opinion with the
  17537. subjective conditions of reason, which does not affect the real case
  17538. (for example, we cannot comprehend the unconditioned necessity of the
  17539. existence of a being, and hence every speculative proof of the existence
  17540. of such a being must be opposed on subjective grounds, while the
  17541. possibility of this being in itself cannot with justice be denied); or,
  17542. both propositions, being dialectical in their nature, are based upon an
  17543. impossible conception. In this latter case the rule applies: non entis
  17544. nulla sunt predicata; that is to say, what we affirm and what we deny,
  17545. respecting such an object, are equally untrue, and the apagogic mode of
  17546. arriving at the truth is in this case impossible. If, for example, we
  17547. presuppose that the world of sense is given in itself in its totality,
  17548. it is false, either that it is infinite, or that it is finite and
  17549. limited in space. Both are false, because the hypothesis is false. For
  17550. the notion of phenomena (as mere representations) which are given in
  17551. themselves (as objects) is self-contradictory; and the infinitude of
  17552. this imaginary whole would, indeed, be unconditioned, but would be
  17553. inconsistent (as everything in the phenomenal world is conditioned)
  17554. with the unconditioned determination and finitude of quantities which is
  17555. presupposed in our conception.
  17556. The apagogic mode of proof is the true source of those illusions which
  17557. have always had so strong an attraction for the admirers of dogmatical
  17558. philosophy. It may be compared to a champion who maintains the honour
  17559. and claims of the party he has adopted by offering battle to all who
  17560. doubt the validity of these claims and the purity of that honour; while
  17561. nothing can be proved in this way, except the respective strength of the
  17562. combatants, and the advantage, in this respect, is always on the side
  17563. of the attacking party. Spectators, observing that each party is
  17564. alternately conqueror and conquered, are led to regard the subject of
  17565. dispute as beyond the power of man to decide upon. But such an opinion
  17566. cannot be justified; and it is sufficient to apply to these reasoners
  17567. the remark:
  17568. Non defensoribus istis
  17569. Tempus eget.
  17570. Each must try to establish his assertions by a transcendental deduction
  17571. of the grounds of proof employed in his argument, and thus enable us to
  17572. see in what way the claims of reason may be supported. If an opponent
  17573. bases his assertions upon subjective grounds, he may be refuted with
  17574. ease; not, however to the advantage of the dogmatist, who likewise
  17575. depends upon subjective sources of cognition and is in like manner
  17576. driven into a corner by his opponent. But, if parties employ the direct
  17577. method of procedure, they will soon discover the difficulty, nay, the
  17578. impossibility of proving their assertions, and will be forced to appeal
  17579. to prescription and precedence; or they will, by the help of criticism,
  17580. discover with ease the dogmatical illusions by which they had been
  17581. mocked, and compel reason to renounce its exaggerated pretensions to
  17582. speculative insight and to confine itself within the limits of its
  17583. proper sphere--that of practical principles.
  17584. CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason.
  17585. It is a humiliating consideration for human reason that it is
  17586. incompetent to discover truth by means of pure speculation, but, on the
  17587. contrary, stands in need of discipline to check its deviations from the
  17588. straight path and to expose the illusions which it originates. But,
  17589. on the other hand, this consideration ought to elevate and to give it
  17590. confidence, for this discipline is exercised by itself alone, and it is
  17591. subject to the censure of no other power. The bounds, moreover, which it
  17592. is forced to set to its speculative exercise, form likewise a check upon
  17593. the fallacious pretensions of opponents; and thus what remains of its
  17594. possessions, after these exaggerated claims have been disallowed, is
  17595. secure from attack or usurpation. The greatest, and perhaps the only,
  17596. use of all philosophy of pure reason is, accordingly, of a purely
  17597. negative character. It is not an organon for the extension, but a
  17598. discipline for the determination, of the limits of its exercise; and
  17599. without laying claim to the discovery of new truth, it has the modest
  17600. merit of guarding against error.
  17601. At the same time, there must be some source of positive cognitions which
  17602. belong to the domain of pure reason and which become the causes of error
  17603. only from our mistaking their true character, while they form the goal
  17604. towards which reason continually strives. How else can we account for
  17605. the inextinguishable desire in the human mind to find a firm footing in
  17606. some region beyond the limits of the world of experience? It hopes to
  17607. attain to the possession of a knowledge in which it has the deepest
  17608. interest. It enters upon the path of pure speculation; but in vain. We
  17609. have some reason, however, to expect that, in the only other way that
  17610. lies open to it--the path of practical reason--it may meet with better
  17611. success.
  17612. I understand by a canon a list of the a priori principles of the proper
  17613. employment of certain faculties of cognition. Thus general logic, in
  17614. its analytical department, is a formal canon for the faculties of
  17615. understanding and reason. In the same way, Transcendental Analytic was
  17616. seen to be a canon of the pure understanding; for it alone is competent
  17617. to enounce true a priori synthetical cognitions. But, when no proper
  17618. employment of a faculty of cognition is possible, no canon can exist.
  17619. But the synthetical cognition of pure speculative reason is, as has been
  17620. shown, completely impossible. There cannot, therefore, exist any canon
  17621. for the speculative exercise of this faculty--for its speculative
  17622. exercise is entirely dialectical; and, consequently, transcendental
  17623. logic, in this respect, is merely a discipline, and not a canon.
  17624. If, then, there is any proper mode of employing the faculty of pure
  17625. reason--in which case there must be a canon for this faculty--this canon
  17626. will relate, not to the speculative, but to the practical use of reason.
  17627. This canon we now proceed to investigate.
  17628. SECTION I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason.
  17629. There exists in the faculty of reason a natural desire to venture beyond
  17630. the field of experience, to attempt to reach the utmost bounds of all
  17631. cognition by the help of ideas alone, and not to rest satisfied until
  17632. it has fulfilled its course and raised the sum of its cognitions into a
  17633. self-subsistent systematic whole. Is the motive for this endeavour to be
  17634. found in its speculative, or in its practical interests alone?
  17635. Setting aside, at present, the results of the labours of pure reason in
  17636. its speculative exercise, I shall merely inquire regarding the problems
  17637. the solution of which forms its ultimate aim, whether reached or
  17638. not, and in relation to which all other aims are but partial and
  17639. intermediate. These highest aims must, from the nature of reason,
  17640. possess complete unity; otherwise the highest interest of humanity could
  17641. not be successfully promoted.
  17642. The transcendental speculation of reason relates to three things: the
  17643. freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the existence of
  17644. God. The speculative interest which reason has in those questions is
  17645. very small; and, for its sake alone, we should not undertake the labour
  17646. of transcendental investigation--a labour full of toil and ceaseless
  17647. struggle. We should be loth to undertake this labour, because the
  17648. discoveries we might make would not be of the smallest use in the sphere
  17649. of concrete or physical investigation. We may find out that the will is
  17650. free, but this knowledge only relates to the intelligible cause of our
  17651. volition. As regards the phenomena or expressions of this will, that is,
  17652. our actions, we are bound, in obedience to an inviolable maxim, without
  17653. which reason cannot be employed in the sphere of experience, to explain
  17654. these in the same way as we explain all the other phenomena of nature,
  17655. that is to say, according to its unchangeable laws. We may have
  17656. discovered the spirituality and immortality of the soul, but we cannot
  17657. employ this knowledge to explain the phenomena of this life, nor the
  17658. peculiar nature of the future, because our conception of an incorporeal
  17659. nature is purely negative and does not add anything to our knowledge,
  17660. and the only inferences to be drawn from it are purely fictitious. If,
  17661. again, we prove the existence of a supreme intelligence, we should be
  17662. able from it to make the conformity to aims existing in the arrangement
  17663. of the world comprehensible; but we should not be justified in deducing
  17664. from it any particular arrangement or disposition, or inferring any
  17665. where it is not perceived. For it is a necessary rule of the speculative
  17666. use of reason that we must not overlook natural causes, or refuse to
  17667. listen to the teaching of experience, for the sake of deducing what we
  17668. know and perceive from something that transcends all our knowledge.
  17669. In one word, these three propositions are, for the speculative reason,
  17670. always transcendent, and cannot be employed as immanent principles in
  17671. relation to the objects of experience; they are, consequently, of no use
  17672. to us in this sphere, being but the valueless results of the severe but
  17673. unprofitable efforts of reason.
  17674. If, then, the actual cognition of these three cardinal propositions is
  17675. perfectly useless, while Reason uses her utmost endeavours to induce us
  17676. to admit them, it is plain that their real value and importance relate
  17677. to our practical, and not to our speculative interest.
  17678. I term all that is possible through free will, practical. But if the
  17679. conditions of the exercise of free volition are empirical, reason can
  17680. have only a regulative, and not a constitutive, influence upon it, and
  17681. is serviceable merely for the introduction of unity into its empirical
  17682. laws. In the moral philosophy of prudence, for example, the sole
  17683. business of reason is to bring about a union of all the ends, which
  17684. are aimed at by our inclinations, into one ultimate end--that of
  17685. happiness--and to show the agreement which should exist among the
  17686. means of attaining that end. In this sphere, accordingly, reason cannot
  17687. present to us any other than pragmatical laws of free action, for our
  17688. guidance towards the aims set up by the senses, and is incompetent to
  17689. give us laws which are pure and determined completely a priori. On the
  17690. other hand, pure practical laws, the ends of which have been given by
  17691. reason entirely a priori, and which are not empirically conditioned, but
  17692. are, on the contrary, absolutely imperative in their nature, would be
  17693. products of pure reason. Such are the moral laws; and these alone belong
  17694. to the sphere of the practical exercise of reason, and admit of a canon.
  17695. All the powers of reason, in the sphere of what may be termed pure
  17696. philosophy, are, in fact, directed to the three above-mentioned problems
  17697. alone. These again have a still higher end--the answer to the question,
  17698. what we ought to do, if the will is free, if there is a God and a future
  17699. world. Now, as this problem relates to our in reference to the highest
  17700. aim of humanity, it is evident that the ultimate intention of nature, in
  17701. the constitution of our reason, has been directed to the moral alone.
  17702. We must take care, however, in turning our attention to an object which
  17703. is foreign* to the sphere of transcendental philosophy, not to injure
  17704. the unity of our system by digressions, nor, on the other hand, to fail
  17705. in clearness, by saying too little on the new subject of discussion.
  17706. I hope to avoid both extremes, by keeping as close as possible to the
  17707. transcendental, and excluding all psychological, that is, empirical,
  17708. elements.
  17709. [*Footnote: All practical conceptions relate to objects of pleasure and
  17710. pain, and consequently--in an indirect manner, at least--to objects of
  17711. feeling. But as feeling is not a faculty of representation, but lies
  17712. out of the sphere of our powers of cognition, the elements of our
  17713. judgements, in so far as they relate to pleasure or pain, that is, the
  17714. elements of our practical judgements, do not belong to transcendental
  17715. philosophy, which has to do with pure a priori cognitions alone.]
  17716. I have to remark, in the first place, that at present I treat of the
  17717. conception of freedom in the practical sense only, and set aside the
  17718. corresponding transcendental conception, which cannot be employed as a
  17719. ground of explanation in the phenomenal world, but is itself a problem
  17720. for pure reason. A will is purely animal (arbitrium brutum) when it is
  17721. determined by sensuous impulses or instincts only, that is, when it is
  17722. determined in a pathological manner. A will, which can be determined
  17723. independently of sensuous impulses, consequently by motives presented by
  17724. reason alone, is called a free will (arbitrium liberum); and everything
  17725. which is connected with this free will, either as principle or
  17726. consequence, is termed practical. The existence of practical freedom can
  17727. be proved from experience alone. For the human will is not determined
  17728. by that alone which immediately affects the senses; on the contrary, we
  17729. have the power, by calling up the notion of what is useful or hurtful in
  17730. a more distant relation, of overcoming the immediate impressions on
  17731. our sensuous faculty of desire. But these considerations of what is
  17732. desirable in relation to our whole state, that is, is in the end good
  17733. and useful, are based entirely upon reason. This faculty, accordingly,
  17734. enounces laws, which are imperative or objective laws of freedom and
  17735. which tell us what ought to take place, thus distinguishing themselves
  17736. from the laws of nature, which relate to that which does take place. The
  17737. laws of freedom or of free will are hence termed practical laws.
  17738. Whether reason is not itself, in the actual delivery of these laws,
  17739. determined in its turn by other influences, and whether the action
  17740. which, in relation to sensuous impulses, we call free, may not, in
  17741. relation to higher and more remote operative causes, really form a part
  17742. of nature--these are questions which do not here concern us. They are
  17743. purely speculative questions; and all we have to do, in the practical
  17744. sphere, is to inquire into the rule of conduct which reason has to
  17745. present. Experience demonstrates to us the existence of practical
  17746. freedom as one of the causes which exist in nature, that is, it shows
  17747. the causal power of reason in the determination of the will. The idea
  17748. of transcendental freedom, on the contrary, requires that reason--in
  17749. relation to its causal power of commencing a series of phenomena--should
  17750. be independent of all sensuous determining causes; and thus it seems to
  17751. be in opposition to the law of nature and to all possible experience.
  17752. It therefore remains a problem for the human mind. But this problem does
  17753. not concern reason in its practical use; and we have, therefore, in a
  17754. canon of pure reason, to do with only two questions, which relate to
  17755. the practical interest of pure reason: Is there a God? and, Is there
  17756. a future life? The question of transcendental freedom is purely
  17757. speculative, and we may therefore set it entirely aside when we come
  17758. to treat of practical reason. Besides, we have already discussed this
  17759. subject in the antinomy of pure reason.
  17760. SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining
  17761. Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason.
  17762. Reason conducted us, in its speculative use, through the field of
  17763. experience and, as it can never find complete satisfaction in that
  17764. sphere, from thence to speculative ideas--which, however, in the end
  17765. brought us back again to experience, and thus fulfilled the purpose of
  17766. reason, in a manner which, though useful, was not at all in accordance
  17767. with our expectations. It now remains for us to consider whether pure
  17768. reason can be employed in a practical sphere, and whether it will here
  17769. conduct us to those ideas which attain the highest ends of pure reason,
  17770. as we have just stated them. We shall thus ascertain whether, from
  17771. the point of view of its practical interest, reason may not be able to
  17772. supply us with that which, on the speculative side, it wholly denies us.
  17773. The whole interest of reason, speculative as well as practical, is
  17774. centred in the three following questions:
  17775. 1. WHAT CAN I KNOW?
  17776. 2. WHAT OUGHT I TO DO?
  17777. 3. WHAT MAY I HOPE?
  17778. The first question is purely speculative. We have, as I flatter myself,
  17779. exhausted all the replies of which it is susceptible, and have at last
  17780. found the reply with which reason must content itself, and with which it
  17781. ought to be content, so long as it pays no regard to the practical. But
  17782. from the two great ends to the attainment of which all these efforts of
  17783. pure reason were in fact directed, we remain just as far removed as if
  17784. we had consulted our ease and declined the task at the outset. So far,
  17785. then, as knowledge is concerned, thus much, at least, is established,
  17786. that, in regard to those two problems, it lies beyond our reach.
  17787. The second question is purely practical. As such it may indeed fall
  17788. within the province of pure reason, but still it is not transcendental,
  17789. but moral, and consequently cannot in itself form the subject of our
  17790. criticism.
  17791. The third question: If I act as I ought to do, what may I then hope?--is
  17792. at once practical and theoretical. The practical forms a clue to
  17793. the answer of the theoretical, and--in its highest form--speculative
  17794. question. For all hoping has happiness for its object and stands in
  17795. precisely the same relation to the practical and the law of morality as
  17796. knowing to the theoretical cognition of things and the law of nature.
  17797. The former arrives finally at the conclusion that something is (which
  17798. determines the ultimate end), because something ought to take place; the
  17799. latter, that something is (which operates as the highest cause), because
  17800. something does take place.
  17801. Happiness is the satisfaction of all our desires; extensive, in regard
  17802. to their multiplicity; intensive, in regard to their degree; and
  17803. protensive, in regard to their duration. The practical law based on the
  17804. motive of happiness I term a pragmatical law (or prudential rule); but
  17805. that law, assuming such to exist, which has no other motive than the
  17806. worthiness of being happy, I term a moral or ethical law. The first
  17807. tells us what we have to do, if we wish to become possessed of
  17808. happiness; the second dictates how we ought to act, in order to deserve
  17809. happiness. The first is based upon empirical principles; for it is only
  17810. by experience that I can learn either what inclinations exist which
  17811. desire satisfaction, or what are the natural means of satisfying them.
  17812. The second takes no account of our desires or the means of satisfying
  17813. them, and regards only the freedom of a rational being, and the
  17814. necessary conditions under which alone this freedom can harmonize with
  17815. the distribution of happiness according to principles. This second law
  17816. may therefore rest upon mere ideas of pure reason, and may be cognized a
  17817. priori.
  17818. I assume that there are pure moral laws which determine, entirely a
  17819. priori (without regard to empirical motives, that is, to happiness), the
  17820. conduct of a rational being, or in other words, to use which it makes of
  17821. its freedom, and that these laws are absolutely imperative (not merely
  17822. hypothetically, on the supposition of other empirical ends), and
  17823. therefore in all respects necessary. I am warranted in assuming this,
  17824. not only by the arguments of the most enlightened moralists, but by
  17825. the moral judgement of every man who will make the attempt to form a
  17826. distinct conception of such a law.
  17827. Pure reason, then, contains, not indeed in its speculative, but in
  17828. its practical, or, more strictly, its moral use, principles of the
  17829. possibility of experience, of such actions, namely, as, in accordance
  17830. with ethical precepts, might be met with in the history of man. For
  17831. since reason commands that such actions should take place, it must
  17832. be possible for them to take place; and hence a particular kind of
  17833. systematic unity--the moral--must be possible. We have found, it is
  17834. true, that the systematic unity of nature could not be established
  17835. according to speculative principles of reason, because, while reason
  17836. possesses a causal power in relation to freedom, it has none in relation
  17837. to the whole sphere of nature; and, while moral principles of reason can
  17838. produce free actions, they cannot produce natural laws. It is, then, in
  17839. its practical, but especially in its moral use, that the principles of
  17840. pure reason possess objective reality.
  17841. I call the world a moral world, in so far as it may be in accordance
  17842. with all the ethical laws--which, by virtue of the freedom of reasonable
  17843. beings, it can be, and according to the necessary laws of morality it
  17844. ought to be. But this world must be conceived only as an intelligible
  17845. world, inasmuch as abstraction is therein made of all conditions (ends),
  17846. and even of all impediments to morality (the weakness or pravity of
  17847. human nature). So far, then, it is a mere idea--though still a practical
  17848. idea--which may have, and ought to have, an influence on the world of
  17849. sense, so as to bring it as far as possible into conformity with itself.
  17850. The idea of a moral world has, therefore, objective reality, not as
  17851. referring to an object of intelligible intuition--for of such an
  17852. object we can form no conception whatever--but to the world of
  17853. sense--conceived, however, as an object of pure reason in its practical
  17854. use--and to a corpus mysticum of rational beings in it, in so far as the
  17855. liberum arbitrium of the individual is placed, under and by virtue of
  17856. moral laws, in complete systematic unity both with itself and with the
  17857. freedom of all others.
  17858. That is the answer to the first of the two questions of pure reason
  17859. which relate to its practical interest: Do that which will render thee
  17860. worthy of happiness. The second question is this: If I conduct myself
  17861. so as not to be unworthy of happiness, may I hope thereby to obtain
  17862. happiness? In order to arrive at the solution of this question, we must
  17863. inquire whether the principles of pure reason, which prescribe a priori
  17864. the law, necessarily also connect this hope with it.
  17865. I say, then, that just as the moral principles are necessary according
  17866. to reason in its practical use, so it is equally necessary according
  17867. to reason in its theoretical use to assume that every one has ground to
  17868. hope for happiness in the measure in which he has made himself worthy
  17869. of it in his conduct, and that therefore the system of morality is
  17870. inseparably (though only in the idea of pure reason) connected with that
  17871. of happiness.
  17872. Now in an intelligible, that is, in the moral world, in the conception
  17873. of which we make abstraction of all the impediments to morality
  17874. (sensuous desires), such a system of happiness, connected with and
  17875. proportioned to morality, may be conceived as necessary, because freedom
  17876. of volition--partly incited, and partly restrained by moral laws--would
  17877. be itself the cause of general happiness; and thus rational beings,
  17878. under the guidance of such principles, would be themselves the authors
  17879. both of their own enduring welfare and that of others. But such a system
  17880. of self-rewarding morality is only an idea, the carrying out of which
  17881. depends upon the condition that every one acts as he ought; in other
  17882. words, that all actions of reasonable beings be such as they would be if
  17883. they sprung from a Supreme Will, comprehending in, or under, itself all
  17884. particular wills. But since the moral law is binding on each individual
  17885. in the use of his freedom of volition, even if others should not act
  17886. in conformity with this law, neither the nature of things, nor the
  17887. causality of actions and their relation to morality, determine how the
  17888. consequences of these actions will be related to happiness; and the
  17889. necessary connection of the hope of happiness with the unceasing
  17890. endeavour to become worthy of happiness, cannot be cognized by reason,
  17891. if we take nature alone for our guide. This connection can be hoped for
  17892. only on the assumption that the cause of nature is a supreme reason,
  17893. which governs according to moral laws.
  17894. I term the idea of an intelligence in which the morally most perfect
  17895. will, united with supreme blessedness, is the cause of all happiness in
  17896. the world, so far as happiness stands in strict relation to morality
  17897. (as the worthiness of being happy), the ideal of the supreme Good. It is
  17898. only, then, in the ideal of the supreme original good, that pure reason
  17899. can find the ground of the practically necessary connection of
  17900. both elements of the highest derivative good, and accordingly of an
  17901. intelligible, that is, moral world. Now since we are necessitated by
  17902. reason to conceive ourselves as belonging to such a world, while the
  17903. senses present to us nothing but a world of phenomena, we must assume
  17904. the former as a consequence of our conduct in the world of sense (since
  17905. the world of sense gives us no hint of it), and therefore as future in
  17906. relation to us. Thus God and a future life are two hypotheses which,
  17907. according to the principles of pure reason, are inseparable from the
  17908. obligation which this reason imposes upon us.
  17909. Morality per se constitutes a system. But we can form no system of
  17910. happiness, except in so far as it is dispensed in strict proportion to
  17911. morality. But this is only possible in the intelligible world, under a
  17912. wise author and ruler. Such a ruler, together with life in such a world,
  17913. which we must look upon as future, reason finds itself compelled to
  17914. assume; or it must regard the moral laws as idle dreams, since the
  17915. necessary consequence which this same reason connects with them must,
  17916. without this hypothesis, fall to the ground. Hence also the moral laws
  17917. are universally regarded as commands, which they could not be did they
  17918. not connect a priori adequate consequences with their dictates, and thus
  17919. carry with them promises and threats. But this, again, they could not
  17920. do, did they not reside in a necessary being, as the Supreme Good, which
  17921. alone can render such a teleological unity possible.
  17922. Leibnitz termed the world, when viewed in relation to the rational
  17923. beings which it contains, and the moral relations in which they stand
  17924. to each other, under the government of the Supreme Good, the kingdom of
  17925. Grace, and distinguished it from the kingdom of Nature, in which these
  17926. rational beings live, under moral laws, indeed, but expect no other
  17927. consequences from their actions than such as follow according to the
  17928. course of nature in the world of sense. To view ourselves, therefore, as
  17929. in the kingdom of grace, in which all happiness awaits us, except in
  17930. so far as we ourselves limit our participation in it by actions which
  17931. render us unworthy of happiness, is a practically necessary idea of
  17932. reason.
  17933. Practical laws, in so far as they are subjective grounds of actions,
  17934. that is, subjective principles, are termed maxims. The judgements
  17935. of moral according to in its purity and ultimate results are framed
  17936. according ideas; the observance of its laws, according to according to
  17937. maxims.
  17938. The whole course of our life must be subject to moral maxims; but this
  17939. is impossible, unless with the moral law, which is a mere idea, reason
  17940. connects an efficient cause which ordains to all conduct which is in
  17941. conformity with the moral law an issue either in this or in another
  17942. life, which is in exact conformity with our highest aims. Thus, without
  17943. a God and without a world, invisible to us now, but hoped for, the
  17944. glorious ideas of morality are, indeed, objects of approbation and of
  17945. admiration, but cannot be the springs of purpose and action. For they do
  17946. not satisfy all the aims which are natural to every rational being, and
  17947. which are determined a priori by pure reason itself, and necessary.
  17948. Happiness alone is, in the view of reason, far from being the complete
  17949. good. Reason does not approve of it (however much inclination may desire
  17950. it), except as united with desert. On the other hand, morality alone,
  17951. and with it, mere desert, is likewise far from being the complete good.
  17952. To make it complete, he who conducts himself in a manner not unworthy
  17953. of happiness, must be able to hope for the possession of happiness. Even
  17954. reason, unbiased by private ends, or interested considerations, cannot
  17955. judge otherwise, if it puts itself in the place of a being whose
  17956. business it is to dispense all happiness to others. For in the practical
  17957. idea both points are essentially combined, though in such a way
  17958. that participation in happiness is rendered possible by the moral
  17959. disposition, as its condition, and not conversely, the moral disposition
  17960. by the prospect of happiness. For a disposition which should require the
  17961. prospect of happiness as its necessary condition would not be moral, and
  17962. hence also would not be worthy of complete happiness--a happiness which,
  17963. in the view of reason, recognizes no limitation but such as arises from
  17964. our own immoral conduct.
  17965. Happiness, therefore, in exact proportion with the morality of rational
  17966. beings (whereby they are made worthy of happiness), constitutes alone
  17967. the supreme good of a world into which we absolutely must transport
  17968. ourselves according to the commands of pure but practical reason.
  17969. This world is, it is true, only an intelligible world; for of such a
  17970. systematic unity of ends as it requires, the world of sense gives us no
  17971. hint. Its reality can be based on nothing else but the hypothesis of a
  17972. supreme original good. In it independent reason, equipped with all
  17973. the sufficiency of a supreme cause, founds, maintains, and fulfils the
  17974. universal order of things, with the most perfect teleological harmony,
  17975. however much this order may be hidden from us in the world of sense.
  17976. This moral theology has the peculiar advantage, in contrast with
  17977. speculative theology, of leading inevitably to the conception of a sole,
  17978. perfect, and rational First Cause, whereof speculative theology does
  17979. not give us any indication on objective grounds, far less any convincing
  17980. evidence. For we find neither in transcendental nor in natural theology,
  17981. however far reason may lead us in these, any ground to warrant us in
  17982. assuming the existence of one only Being, which stands at the head of
  17983. all natural causes, and on which these are entirely dependent. On the
  17984. other band, if we take our stand on moral unity as a necessary law of
  17985. the universe, and from this point of view consider what is necessary to
  17986. give this law adequate efficiency and, for us, obligatory force, we
  17987. must come to the conclusion that there is one only supreme will, which
  17988. comprehends all these laws in itself. For how, under different wills,
  17989. should we find complete unity of ends? This will must be omnipotent,
  17990. that all nature and its relation to morality in the world may be
  17991. subject to it; omniscient, that it may have knowledge of the most secret
  17992. feelings and their moral worth; omnipresent, that it may be at hand to
  17993. supply every necessity to which the highest weal of the world may give
  17994. rise; eternal, that this harmony of nature and liberty may never fail;
  17995. and so on.
  17996. But this systematic unity of ends in this world of intelligences--which,
  17997. as mere nature, is only a world of sense, but, as a system of freedom
  17998. of volition, may be termed an intelligible, that is, moral world (regnum
  17999. gratiae)--leads inevitably also to the teleological unity of all things
  18000. which constitute this great whole, according to universal natural
  18001. laws--just as the unity of the former is according to universal and
  18002. necessary moral laws--and unites the practical with the speculative
  18003. reason. The world must be represented as having originated from an idea,
  18004. if it is to harmonize with that use of reason without which we cannot
  18005. even consider ourselves as worthy of reason--namely, the moral use,
  18006. which rests entirely on the idea of the supreme good. Hence the
  18007. investigation of nature receives a teleological direction, and becomes,
  18008. in its widest extension, physico-theology. But this, taking its rise
  18009. in moral order as a unity founded on the essence of freedom, and
  18010. not accidentally instituted by external commands, establishes the
  18011. teleological view of nature on grounds which must be inseparably
  18012. connected with the internal possibility of things. This gives rise to
  18013. a transcendental theology, which takes the ideal of the highest
  18014. ontological perfection as a principle of systematic unity; and this
  18015. principle connects all things according to universal and necessary
  18016. natural laws, because all things have their origin in the absolute
  18017. necessity of the one only Primal Being.
  18018. What use can we make of our understanding, even in respect of
  18019. experience, if we do not propose ends to ourselves? But the highest ends
  18020. are those of morality, and it is only pure reason that can give us the
  18021. knowledge of these. Though supplied with these, and putting ourselves
  18022. under their guidance, we can make no teleological use of the knowledge
  18023. of nature, as regards cognition, unless nature itself has established
  18024. teleological unity. For without this unity we should not even possess
  18025. reason, because we should have no school for reason, and no cultivation
  18026. through objects which afford the materials for its conceptions. But
  18027. teleological unity is a necessary unity, and founded on the essence of
  18028. the individual will itself. Hence this will, which is the condition of
  18029. the application of this unity in concreto, must be so likewise. In this
  18030. way the transcendental enlargement of our rational cognition would be,
  18031. not the cause, but merely the effect of the practical teleology which
  18032. pure reason imposes upon us.
  18033. Hence, also, we find in the history of human reason that, before the
  18034. moral conceptions were sufficiently purified and determined, and
  18035. before men had attained to a perception of the systematic unity of
  18036. ends according to these conceptions and from necessary principles, the
  18037. knowledge of nature, and even a considerable amount of intellectual
  18038. culture in many other sciences, could produce only rude and vague
  18039. conceptions of the Deity, sometimes even admitting of an astonishing
  18040. indifference with regard to this question altogether. But the more
  18041. enlarged treatment of moral ideas, which was rendered necessary by
  18042. the extreme pure moral law of our religion, awakened the interest, and
  18043. thereby quickened the perceptions of reason in relation to this object.
  18044. In this way, and without the help either of an extended acquaintance
  18045. with nature, or of a reliable transcendental insight (for these have
  18046. been wanting in all ages), a conception of the Divine Being was arrived
  18047. at, which we now bold to be the correct one, not because speculative
  18048. reason convinces us of its correctness, but because it accords with the
  18049. moral principles of reason. Thus it is to pure reason, but only in its
  18050. practical use, that we must ascribe the merit of having connected with
  18051. our highest interest a cognition, of which mere speculation was able
  18052. only to form a conjecture, but the validity of which it was unable to
  18053. establish--and of having thereby rendered it, not indeed a demonstrated
  18054. dogma, but a hypothesis absolutely necessary to the essential ends of
  18055. reason.
  18056. But if practical reason has reached this elevation, and has attained to
  18057. the conception of a sole Primal Being as the supreme good, it must not,
  18058. therefore, imagine that it has transcended the empirical conditions of
  18059. its application, and risen to the immediate cognition of new objects; it
  18060. must not presume to start from the conception which it has gained, and
  18061. to deduce from it the moral laws themselves. For it was these very laws,
  18062. the internal practical necessity of which led us to the hypothesis of an
  18063. independent cause, or of a wise ruler of the universe, who should give
  18064. them effect. Hence we are not entitled to regard them as accidental
  18065. and derived from the mere will of the ruler, especially as we have no
  18066. conception of such a will, except as formed in accordance with these
  18067. laws. So far, then, as practical reason has the right to conduct us,
  18068. we shall not look upon actions as binding on us, because they are the
  18069. commands of God, but we shall regard them as divine commands, because
  18070. we are internally bound by them. We shall study freedom under the
  18071. teleological unity which accords with principles of reason; we shall
  18072. look upon ourselves as acting in conformity with the divine will only in
  18073. so far as we hold sacred the moral law which reason teaches us from the
  18074. nature of actions themselves, and we shall believe that we can obey
  18075. that will only by promoting the weal of the universe in ourselves and in
  18076. others. Moral theology is, therefore, only of immanent use. It teaches
  18077. us to fulfil our destiny here in the world, by placing ourselves in
  18078. harmony with the general system of ends, and warns us against the
  18079. fanaticism, nay, the crime of depriving reason of its legislative
  18080. authority in the moral conduct of life, for the purpose of directly
  18081. connecting this authority with the idea of the Supreme Being. For this
  18082. would be, not an immanent, but a transcendent use of moral theology,
  18083. and, like the transcendent use of mere speculation, would inevitably
  18084. pervert and frustrate the ultimate ends of reason.
  18085. SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief.
  18086. The holding of a thing to be true is a phenomenon in our understanding
  18087. which may rest on objective grounds, but requires, also, subjective
  18088. causes in the mind of the person judging. If a judgement is valid for
  18089. every rational being, then its ground is objectively sufficient, and it
  18090. is termed a conviction. If, on the other hand, it has its ground in the
  18091. particular character of the subject, it is termed a persuasion.
  18092. Persuasion is a mere illusion, the ground of the judgement, which lies
  18093. solely in the subject, being regarded as objective. Hence a judgement
  18094. of this kind has only private validity--is only valid for the individual
  18095. who judges, and the holding of a thing to be true in this way cannot
  18096. be communicated. But truth depends upon agreement with the object, and
  18097. consequently the judgements of all understandings, if true, must be in
  18098. agreement with each other (consentientia uni tertio consentiunt inter
  18099. se). Conviction may, therefore, be distinguished, from an external point
  18100. of view, from persuasion, by the possibility of communicating it and by
  18101. showing its validity for the reason of every man; for in this case the
  18102. presumption, at least, arises that the agreement of all judgements with
  18103. each other, in spite of the different characters of individuals, rests
  18104. upon the common ground of the agreement of each with the object, and
  18105. thus the correctness of the judgement is established.
  18106. Persuasion, accordingly, cannot be subjectively distinguished from
  18107. conviction, that is, so long as the subject views its judgement simply
  18108. as a phenomenon of its own mind. But if we inquire whether the grounds
  18109. of our judgement, which are valid for us, produce the same effect on
  18110. the reason of others as on our own, we have then the means, though only
  18111. subjective means, not, indeed, of producing conviction, but of detecting
  18112. the merely private validity of the judgement; in other words, of
  18113. discovering that there is in it the element of mere persuasion.
  18114. If we can, in addition to this, develop the subjective causes of the
  18115. judgement, which we have taken for its objective grounds, and thus
  18116. explain the deceptive judgement as a phenomenon in our mind, apart
  18117. altogether from the objective character of the object, we can then
  18118. expose the illusion and need be no longer deceived by it, although, if
  18119. its subjective cause lies in our nature, we cannot hope altogether to
  18120. escape its influence.
  18121. I can only maintain, that is, affirm as necessarily valid for every one,
  18122. that which produces conviction. Persuasion I may keep for myself, if it
  18123. is agreeable to me; but I cannot, and ought not, to attempt to impose it
  18124. as binding upon others.
  18125. Holding for true, or the subjective validity of a judgement in relation
  18126. to conviction (which is, at the same time, objectively valid), has the
  18127. three following degrees: opinion, belief, and knowledge. Opinion is a
  18128. consciously insufficient judgement, subjectively as well as objectively.
  18129. Belief is subjectively sufficient, but is recognized as being
  18130. objectively insufficient. Knowledge is both subjectively and objectively
  18131. sufficient. Subjective sufficiency is termed conviction (for myself);
  18132. objective sufficiency is termed certainty (for all). I need not dwell
  18133. longer on the explanation of such simple conceptions.
  18134. I must never venture to be of opinion, without knowing something, at
  18135. least, by which my judgement, in itself merely problematical, is brought
  18136. into connection with the truth--which connection, although not perfect,
  18137. is still something more than an arbitrary fiction. Moreover, the law of
  18138. such a connection must be certain. For if, in relation to this law,
  18139. I have nothing more than opinion, my judgement is but a play of the
  18140. imagination, without the least relation to truth. In the judgements of
  18141. pure reason, opinion has no place. For, as they do not rest on empirical
  18142. grounds and as the sphere of pure reason is that of necessary truth
  18143. and a priori cognition, the principle of connection in it
  18144. requires universality and necessity, and consequently perfect
  18145. certainty--otherwise we should have no guide to the truth at all. Hence
  18146. it is absurd to have an opinion in pure mathematics; we must know, or
  18147. abstain from forming a judgement altogether. The case is the same with
  18148. the maxims of morality. For we must not hazard an action on the mere
  18149. opinion that it is allowed, but we must know it to be so. In the
  18150. transcendental sphere of reason, on the other hand, the term opinion
  18151. is too weak, while the word knowledge is too strong. From the merely
  18152. speculative point of view, therefore, we cannot form a judgement at
  18153. all. For the subjective grounds of a judgement, such as produce belief,
  18154. cannot be admitted in speculative inquiries, inasmuch as they cannot
  18155. stand without empirical support and are incapable of being communicated
  18156. to others in equal measure.
  18157. But it is only from the practical point of view that a theoretically
  18158. insufficient judgement can be termed belief. Now the practical reference
  18159. is either to skill or to morality; to the former, when the end proposed
  18160. is arbitrary and accidental, to the latter, when it is absolutely
  18161. necessary.
  18162. If we propose to ourselves any end whatever, the conditions of its
  18163. attainment are hypothetically necessary. The necessity is subjectively,
  18164. but still only comparatively, sufficient, if I am acquainted with no
  18165. other conditions under which the end can be attained. On the other hand,
  18166. it is sufficient, absolutely and for every one, if I know for certain
  18167. that no one can be acquainted with any other conditions under which the
  18168. attainment of the proposed end would be possible. In the former case my
  18169. supposition--my judgement with regard to certain conditions--is a merely
  18170. accidental belief; in the latter it is a necessary belief. The physician
  18171. must pursue some course in the case of a patient who is in danger, but
  18172. is ignorant of the nature of the disease. He observes the symptoms, and
  18173. concludes, according to the best of his judgement, that it is a case
  18174. of phthisis. His belief is, even in his own judgement, only contingent:
  18175. another man might, perhaps come nearer the truth. Such a belief,
  18176. contingent indeed, but still forming the ground of the actual use of
  18177. means for the attainment of certain ends, I term Pragmatical belief.
  18178. The usual test, whether that which any one maintains is merely his
  18179. persuasion, or his subjective conviction at least, that is, his firm
  18180. belief, is a bet. It frequently happens that a man delivers his opinions
  18181. with so much boldness and assurance, that he appears to be under no
  18182. apprehension as to the possibility of his being in error. The offer of
  18183. a bet startles him, and makes him pause. Sometimes it turns out that
  18184. his persuasion may be valued at a ducat, but not at ten. For he does not
  18185. hesitate, perhaps, to venture a ducat, but if it is proposed to stake
  18186. ten, he immediately becomes aware of the possibility of his being
  18187. mistaken--a possibility which has hitherto escaped his observation. If
  18188. we imagine to ourselves that we have to stake the happiness of our whole
  18189. life on the truth of any proposition, our judgement drops its air of
  18190. triumph, we take the alarm, and discover the actual strength of our
  18191. belief. Thus pragmatical belief has degrees, varying in proportion to
  18192. the interests at stake.
  18193. Now, in cases where we cannot enter upon any course of action in
  18194. reference to some object, and where, accordingly, our judgement is
  18195. purely theoretical, we can still represent to ourselves, in thought,
  18196. the possibility of a course of action, for which we suppose that we have
  18197. sufficient grounds, if any means existed of ascertaining the truth of
  18198. the matter. Thus we find in purely theoretical judgements an analogon of
  18199. practical judgements, to which the word belief may properly be applied,
  18200. and which we may term doctrinal belief. I should not hesitate to stake
  18201. my all on the truth of the proposition--if there were any possibility of
  18202. bringing it to the test of experience--that, at least, some one of the
  18203. planets, which we see, is inhabited. Hence I say that I have not merely
  18204. the opinion, but the strong belief, on the correctness of which I would
  18205. stake even many of the advantages of life, that there are inhabitants in
  18206. other worlds.
  18207. Now we must admit that the doctrine of the existence of God belongs to
  18208. doctrinal belief. For, although in respect to the theoretical cognition
  18209. of the universe I do not require to form any theory which necessarily
  18210. involves this idea, as the condition of my explanation of the phenomena
  18211. which the universe presents, but, on the contrary, am rather bound so
  18212. to use my reason as if everything were mere nature, still teleological
  18213. unity is so important a condition of the application of my reason to
  18214. nature, that it is impossible for me to ignore it--especially since, in
  18215. addition to these considerations, abundant examples of it are supplied
  18216. by experience. But the sole condition, so far as my knowledge extends,
  18217. under which this unity can be my guide in the investigation of nature,
  18218. is the assumption that a supreme intelligence has ordered all things
  18219. according to the wisest ends. Consequently, the hypothesis of a wise
  18220. author of the universe is necessary for my guidance in the investigation
  18221. of nature--is the condition under which alone I can fulfil an end which
  18222. is contingent indeed, but by no means unimportant. Moreover, since
  18223. the result of my attempts so frequently confirms the utility of this
  18224. assumption, and since nothing decisive can be adduced against it, it
  18225. follows that it would be saying far too little to term my judgement,
  18226. in this case, a mere opinion, and that, even in this theoretical
  18227. connection, I may assert that I firmly believe in God. Still, if we use
  18228. words strictly, this must not be called a practical, but a doctrinal
  18229. belief, which the theology of nature (physico-theology) must also
  18230. produce in my mind. In the wisdom of a Supreme Being, and in the
  18231. shortness of life, so inadequate to the development of the glorious
  18232. powers of human nature, we may find equally sufficient grounds for a
  18233. doctrinal belief in the future life of the human soul.
  18234. The expression of belief is, in such cases, an expression of modesty
  18235. from the objective point of view, but, at the same time, of firm
  18236. confidence, from the subjective. If I should venture to term this merely
  18237. theoretical judgement even so much as a hypothesis which I am entitled
  18238. to assume; a more complete conception, with regard to another world and
  18239. to the cause of the world, might then be justly required of me than I
  18240. am, in reality, able to give. For, if I assume anything, even as a mere
  18241. hypothesis, I must, at least, know so much of the properties of such a
  18242. being as will enable me, not to form the conception, but to imagine the
  18243. existence of it. But the word belief refers only to the guidance which
  18244. an idea gives me, and to its subjective influence on the conduct of
  18245. my reason, which forces me to hold it fast, though I may not be in a
  18246. position to give a speculative account of it.
  18247. But mere doctrinal belief is, to some extent, wanting in stability.
  18248. We often quit our hold of it, in consequence of the difficulties which
  18249. occur in speculation, though in the end we inevitably return to it
  18250. again.
  18251. It is quite otherwise with moral belief. For in this sphere action is
  18252. absolutely necessary, that is, I must act in obedience to the moral law
  18253. in all points. The end is here incontrovertibly established, and there
  18254. is only one condition possible, according to the best of my perception,
  18255. under which this end can harmonize with all other ends, and so have
  18256. practical validity--namely, the existence of a God and of a future
  18257. world. I know also, to a certainty, that no one can be acquainted with
  18258. any other conditions which conduct to the same unity of ends under the
  18259. moral law. But since the moral precept is, at the same time, my maxim
  18260. (as reason requires that it should be), I am irresistibly constrained to
  18261. believe in the existence of God and in a future life; and I am sure
  18262. that nothing can make me waver in this belief, since I should thereby
  18263. overthrow my moral maxims, the renunciation of which would render me
  18264. hateful in my own eyes.
  18265. Thus, while all the ambitious attempts of reason to penetrate beyond the
  18266. limits of experience end in disappointment, there is still enough left
  18267. to satisfy us in a practical point of view. No one, it is true, will be
  18268. able to boast that he knows that there is a God and a future life; for,
  18269. if he knows this, he is just the man whom I have long wished to find.
  18270. All knowledge, regarding an object of mere reason, can be communicated;
  18271. and I should thus be enabled to hope that my own knowledge would
  18272. receive this wonderful extension, through the instrumentality of his
  18273. instruction. No, my conviction is not logical, but moral certainty; and
  18274. since it rests on subjective grounds (of the moral sentiment), I must
  18275. not even say: It is morally certain that there is a God, etc., but: I
  18276. am morally certain, that is, my belief in God and in another world is so
  18277. interwoven with my moral nature that I am under as little apprehension
  18278. of having the former torn from me as of losing the latter.
  18279. The only point in this argument that may appear open to suspicion is
  18280. that this rational belief presupposes the existence of moral sentiments.
  18281. If we give up this assumption, and take a man who is entirely
  18282. indifferent with regard to moral laws, the question which reason
  18283. proposes, becomes then merely a problem for speculation and may, indeed,
  18284. be supported by strong grounds from analogy, but not by such as
  18285. will compel the most obstinate scepticism to give way.* But in these
  18286. questions no man is free from all interest. For though the want of good
  18287. sentiments may place him beyond the influence of moral interests, still
  18288. even in this case enough may be left to make him fear the existence of
  18289. God and a future life. For he cannot pretend to any certainty of the
  18290. non-existence of God and of a future life, unless--since it could only
  18291. be proved by mere reason, and therefore apodeictically--he is prepared
  18292. to establish the impossibility of both, which certainly no reasonable
  18293. man would undertake to do. This would be a negative belief, which could
  18294. not, indeed, produce morality and good sentiments, but still could
  18295. produce an analogon of these, by operating as a powerful restraint on
  18296. the outbreak of evil dispositions.
  18297. [*Footnote: The human mind (as, I believe, every rational being must
  18298. of necessity do) takes a natural interest in morality, although this
  18299. interest is not undivided, and may not be practically in preponderance.
  18300. If you strengthen and increase it, you will find the reason become
  18301. docile, more enlightened, and more capable of uniting the speculative
  18302. interest with the practical. But if you do not take care at the outset,
  18303. or at least midway, to make men good, you will never force them into an
  18304. honest belief.]
  18305. But, it will be said, is this all that pure reason can effect, in
  18306. opening up prospects beyond the limits of experience? Nothing more than
  18307. two articles of belief? Common sense could have done as much as this,
  18308. without taking the philosophers to counsel in the matter!
  18309. I shall not here eulogize philosophy for the benefits which the
  18310. laborious efforts of its criticism have conferred on human
  18311. reason--even granting that its merit should turn out in the end to be
  18312. only negative--for on this point something more will be said in the next
  18313. section. But, I ask, do you require that that knowledge which concerns
  18314. all men, should transcend the common understanding, and should only be
  18315. revealed to you by philosophers? The very circumstance which has called
  18316. forth your censure, is the best confirmation of the correctness of
  18317. our previous assertions, since it discloses, what could not have been
  18318. foreseen, that Nature is not chargeable with any partial distribution of
  18319. her gifts in those matters which concern all men without distinction
  18320. and that, in respect to the essential ends of human nature, we cannot
  18321. advance further with the help of the highest philosophy, than under the
  18322. guidance which nature has vouchsafed to the meanest understanding.
  18323. CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason.
  18324. By the term architectonic I mean the art of constructing a system.
  18325. Without systematic unity, our knowledge cannot become science; it will
  18326. be an aggregate, and not a system. Thus architectonic is the doctrine of
  18327. the scientific in cognition, and therefore necessarily forms part of our
  18328. methodology.
  18329. Reason cannot permit our knowledge to remain in an unconnected and
  18330. rhapsodistic state, but requires that the sum of our cognitions should
  18331. constitute a system. It is thus alone that they can advance the ends
  18332. of reason. By a system I mean the unity of various cognitions under one
  18333. idea. This idea is the conception--given by reason--of the form of a
  18334. whole, in so far as the conception determines a priori not only the
  18335. limits of its content, but the place which each of its parts is to
  18336. occupy. The scientific idea contains, therefore, the end and the form of
  18337. the whole which is in accordance with that end. The unity of the end, to
  18338. which all the parts of the system relate, and through which all have a
  18339. relation to each other, communicates unity to the whole system, so that
  18340. the absence of any part can be immediately detected from our knowledge
  18341. of the rest; and it determines a priori the limits of the system, thus
  18342. excluding all contingent or arbitrary additions. The whole is thus an
  18343. organism (articulatio), and not an aggregate (coacervatio); it may grow
  18344. from within (per intussusceptionem), but it cannot increase by external
  18345. additions (per appositionem). It is, thus, like an animal body, the
  18346. growth of which does not add any limb, but, without changing their
  18347. proportions, makes each in its sphere stronger and more active.
  18348. We require, for the execution of the idea of a system, a schema, that
  18349. is, a content and an arrangement of parts determined a priori by the
  18350. principle which the aim of the system prescribes. A schema which is not
  18351. projected in accordance with an idea, that is, from the standpoint of
  18352. the highest aim of reason, but merely empirically, in accordance
  18353. with accidental aims and purposes (the number of which cannot be
  18354. predetermined), can give us nothing more than technical unity. But the
  18355. schema which is originated from an idea (in which case reason presents
  18356. us with aims a priori, and does not look for them to experience), forms
  18357. the basis of architectonical unity. A science, in the proper acceptation
  18358. of that term, cannot be formed technically, that is, from observation
  18359. of the similarity existing between different objects, and the purely
  18360. contingent use we make of our knowledge in concreto with reference to
  18361. all kinds of arbitrary external aims; its constitution must be framed on
  18362. architectonical principles, that is, its parts must be shown to possess
  18363. an essential affinity, and be capable of being deduced from one supreme
  18364. and internal aim or end, which forms the condition of the possibility
  18365. of the scientific whole. The schema of a science must give a priori the
  18366. plan of it (monogramma), and the division of the whole into parts, in
  18367. conformity with the idea of the science; and it must also distinguish
  18368. this whole from all others, according to certain understood principles.
  18369. No one will attempt to construct a science, unless he have some idea to
  18370. rest on as a proper basis. But, in the elaboration of the science, he
  18371. finds that the schema, nay, even the definition which he at first gave
  18372. of the science, rarely corresponds with his idea; for this idea lies,
  18373. like a germ, in our reason, its parts undeveloped and hid even from
  18374. microscopical observation. For this reason, we ought to explain and
  18375. define sciences, not according to the description which the originator
  18376. gives of them, but according to the idea which we find based in reason
  18377. itself, and which is suggested by the natural unity of the parts of
  18378. the science already accumulated. For it will of ten be found that the
  18379. originator of a science and even his latest successors remain attached
  18380. to an erroneous idea, which they cannot render clear to themselves, and
  18381. that they thus fail in determining the true content, the articulation or
  18382. systematic unity, and the limits of their science.
  18383. It is unfortunate that, only after having occupied ourselves for a long
  18384. time in the collection of materials, under the guidance of an idea which
  18385. lies undeveloped in the mind, but not according to any definite plan of
  18386. arrangement--nay, only after we have spent much time and labour in the
  18387. technical disposition of our materials, does it become possible to view
  18388. the idea of a science in a clear light, and to project, according to
  18389. architectonical principles, a plan of the whole, in accordance with the
  18390. aims of reason. Systems seem, like certain worms, to be formed by a kind
  18391. of generatio aequivoca--by the mere confluence of conceptions, and to
  18392. gain completeness only with the progress of time. But the schema or
  18393. germ of all lies in reason; and thus is not only every system organized
  18394. according to its own idea, but all are united into one grand system
  18395. of human knowledge, of which they form members. For this reason, it is
  18396. possible to frame an architectonic of all human cognition, the formation
  18397. of which, at the present time, considering the immense materials
  18398. collected or to be found in the ruins of old systems, would not indeed
  18399. be very difficult. Our purpose at present is merely to sketch the plan
  18400. of the architectonic of all cognition given by pure reason; and we begin
  18401. from the point where the main root of human knowledge divides into two,
  18402. one of which is reason. By reason I understand here the whole higher
  18403. faculty of cognition, the rational being placed in contradistinction to
  18404. the empirical.
  18405. If I make complete abstraction of the content of cognition, objectively
  18406. considered, all cognition is, from a subjective point of view, either
  18407. historical or rational. Historical cognition is cognitio ex datis,
  18408. rational, cognitio ex principiis. Whatever may be the original source of
  18409. a cognition, it is, in relation to the person who possesses it, merely
  18410. historical, if he knows only what has been given him from another
  18411. quarter, whether that knowledge was communicated by direct experience
  18412. or by instruction. Thus the Person who has learned a system of
  18413. philosophy--say the Wolfian--although he has a perfect knowledge of all
  18414. the principles, definitions, and arguments in that philosophy, as well
  18415. as of the divisions that have been made of the system, possesses really
  18416. no more than an historical knowledge of the Wolfian system; he knows
  18417. only what has been told him, his judgements are only those which he has
  18418. received from his teachers. Dispute the validity of a definition, and
  18419. he is completely at a loss to find another. He has formed his mind
  18420. on another's; but the imitative faculty is not the productive. His
  18421. knowledge has not been drawn from reason; and although, objectively
  18422. considered, it is rational knowledge, subjectively, it is merely
  18423. historical. He has learned this or that philosophy and is merely a
  18424. plaster cast of a living man. Rational cognitions which are objective,
  18425. that is, which have their source in reason, can be so termed from
  18426. a subjective point of view, only when they have been drawn by the
  18427. individual himself from the sources of reason, that is, from principles;
  18428. and it is in this way alone that criticism, or even the rejection of
  18429. what has been already learned, can spring up in the mind.
  18430. All rational cognition is, again, based either on conceptions, or on
  18431. the construction of conceptions. The former is termed philosophical, the
  18432. latter mathematical. I have already shown the essential difference of
  18433. these two methods of cognition in the first chapter. A cognition may be
  18434. objectively philosophical and subjectively historical--as is the case
  18435. with the majority of scholars and those who cannot look beyond the
  18436. limits of their system, and who remain in a state of pupilage all their
  18437. lives. But it is remarkable that mathematical knowledge, when committed
  18438. to memory, is valid, from the subjective point of view, as rational
  18439. knowledge also, and that the same distinction cannot be drawn here as in
  18440. the case of philosophical cognition. The reason is that the only way
  18441. of arriving at this knowledge is through the essential principles of
  18442. reason, and thus it is always certain and indisputable; because reason
  18443. is employed in concreto--but at the same time a priori--that is, in pure
  18444. and, therefore, infallible intuition; and thus all causes of illusion
  18445. and error are excluded. Of all the a priori sciences of reason,
  18446. therefore, mathematics alone can be learned. Philosophy--unless it be
  18447. in an historical manner--cannot be learned; we can at most learn to
  18448. philosophize.
  18449. Philosophy is the system of all philosophical cognition. We must use
  18450. this term in an objective sense, if we understand by it the archetype of
  18451. all attempts at philosophizing, and the standard by which all subjective
  18452. philosophies are to be judged. In this sense, philosophy is merely the
  18453. idea of a possible science, which does not exist in concreto, but
  18454. to which we endeavour in various ways to approximate, until we have
  18455. discovered the right path to pursue--a path overgrown by the errors
  18456. and illusions of sense--and the image we have hitherto tried in vain to
  18457. shape has become a perfect copy of the great prototype. Until that time,
  18458. we cannot learn philosophy--it does not exist; if it does, where is
  18459. it, who possesses it, and how shall we know it? We can only learn
  18460. to philosophize; in other words, we can only exercise our powers of
  18461. reasoning in accordance with general principles, retaining at the same
  18462. time, the right of investigating the sources of these principles, of
  18463. testing, and even of rejecting them.
  18464. Until then, our conception of philosophy is only a scholastic
  18465. conception--a conception, that is, of a system of cognition which we are
  18466. trying to elaborate into a science; all that we at present know being
  18467. the systematic unity of this cognition, and consequently the logical
  18468. completeness of the cognition for the desired end. But there is also a
  18469. cosmical conception (conceptus cosmicus) of philosophy, which has always
  18470. formed the true basis of this term, especially when philosophy was
  18471. personified and presented to us in the ideal of a philosopher. In this
  18472. view philosophy is the science of the relation of all cognition to
  18473. the ultimate and essential aims of human reason (teleologia rationis
  18474. humanae), and the philosopher is not merely an artist--who occupies
  18475. himself with conceptions--but a lawgiver, legislating for human reason.
  18476. In this sense of the word, it would be in the highest degree arrogant to
  18477. assume the title of philosopher, and to pretend that we had reached the
  18478. perfection of the prototype which lies in the idea alone.
  18479. The mathematician, the natural philosopher, and the logician--how far
  18480. soever the first may have advanced in rational, and the two latter in
  18481. philosophical knowledge--are merely artists, engaged in the arrangement
  18482. and formation of conceptions; they cannot be termed philosophers. Above
  18483. them all, there is the ideal teacher, who employs them as instruments
  18484. for the advancement of the essential aims of human reason. Him alone
  18485. can we call philosopher; but he nowhere exists. But the idea of his
  18486. legislative power resides in the mind of every man, and it alone teaches
  18487. us what kind of systematic unity philosophy demands in view of
  18488. the ultimate aims of reason. This idea is, therefore, a cosmical
  18489. conception.*
  18490. [*Footnote: By a cosmical conception, I mean one in which all men
  18491. necessarily take an interest; the aim of a science must accordingly be
  18492. determined according to scholastic conceptions, if it is regarded merely
  18493. as a means to certain arbitrarily proposed ends.]
  18494. In view of the complete systematic unity of reason, there can only be
  18495. one ultimate end of all the operations of the mind. To this all other
  18496. aims are subordinate, and nothing more than means for its attainment.
  18497. This ultimate end is the destination of man, and the philosophy which
  18498. relates to it is termed moral philosophy. The superior position occupied
  18499. by moral philosophy, above all other spheres for the operations of
  18500. reason, sufficiently indicates the reason why the ancients always
  18501. included the idea--and in an especial manner--of moralist in that of
  18502. philosopher. Even at the present day, we call a man who appears to have
  18503. the power of self-government, even although his knowledge may be very
  18504. limited, by the name of philosopher.
  18505. The legislation of human reason, or philosophy, has two objects--nature
  18506. and freedom--and thus contains not only the laws of nature, but also
  18507. those of ethics, at first in two separate systems, which, finally, merge
  18508. into one grand philosophical system of cognition. The philosophy of
  18509. nature relates to that which is, that of ethics to that which ought to
  18510. be.
  18511. But all philosophy is either cognition on the basis of pure reason, or
  18512. the cognition of reason on the basis of empirical principles. The former
  18513. is termed pure, the latter empirical philosophy.
  18514. The philosophy of pure reason is either propaedeutic, that is, an
  18515. inquiry into the powers of reason in regard to pure a priori cognition,
  18516. and is termed critical philosophy; or it is, secondly, the system of
  18517. pure reason--a science containing the systematic presentation of the
  18518. whole body of philosophical knowledge, true as well as illusory, given
  18519. by pure reason--and is called metaphysic. This name may, however, be
  18520. also given to the whole system of pure philosophy, critical philosophy
  18521. included, and may designate the investigation into the sources or
  18522. possibility of a priori cognition, as well as the presentation of the a
  18523. priori cognitions which form a system of pure philosophy--excluding, at
  18524. the same time, all empirical and mathematical elements.
  18525. Metaphysic is divided into that of the speculative and that of the
  18526. practical use of pure reason, and is, accordingly, either the metaphysic
  18527. of nature, or the metaphysic of ethics. The former contains all the pure
  18528. rational principles--based upon conceptions alone (and thus excluding
  18529. mathematics)--of all theoretical cognition; the latter, the principles
  18530. which determine and necessitate a priori all action. Now moral
  18531. philosophy alone contains a code of laws--for the regulation of our
  18532. actions--which are deduced from principles entirely a priori. Hence the
  18533. metaphysic of ethics is the only pure moral philosophy, as it is not
  18534. based upon anthropological or other empirical considerations. The
  18535. metaphysic of speculative reason is what is commonly called metaphysic
  18536. in the more limited sense. But as pure moral philosophy properly forms a
  18537. part of this system of cognition, we must allow it to retain the name
  18538. of metaphysic, although it is not requisite that we should insist on so
  18539. terming it in our present discussion.
  18540. It is of the highest importance to separate those cognitions which
  18541. differ from others both in kind and in origin, and to take great care
  18542. that they are not confounded with those with which they are generally
  18543. found connected. What the chemist does in the analysis of substances,
  18544. what the mathematician in pure mathematics, is, in a still higher
  18545. degree, the duty of the philosopher, that the value of each different
  18546. kind of cognition, and the part it takes in the operations of the mind,
  18547. may be clearly defined. Human reason has never wanted a metaphysic
  18548. of some kind, since it attained the power of thought, or rather of
  18549. reflection; but it has never been able to keep this sphere of thought
  18550. and cognition pure from all admixture of foreign elements. The idea of a
  18551. science of this kind is as old as speculation itself; and what mind does
  18552. not speculate--either in the scholastic or in the popular fashion? At
  18553. the same time, it must be admitted that even thinkers by profession have
  18554. been unable clearly to explain the distinction between the two elements
  18555. of our cognition--the one completely a priori, the other a posteriori;
  18556. and hence the proper definition of a peculiar kind of cognition, and
  18557. with it the just idea of a science which has so long and so deeply
  18558. engaged the attention of the human mind, has never been established.
  18559. When it was said: "Metaphysic is the science of the first principles
  18560. of human cognition," this definition did not signalize a peculiarity in
  18561. kind, but only a difference in degree; these first principles were thus
  18562. declared to be more general than others, but no criterion of distinction
  18563. from empirical principles was given. Of these some are more general,
  18564. and therefore higher, than others; and--as we cannot distinguish what is
  18565. completely a priori from that which is known to be a posteriori--where
  18566. shall we draw the line which is to separate the higher and so-called
  18567. first principles, from the lower and subordinate principles of
  18568. cognition? What would be said if we were asked to be satisfied with a
  18569. division of the epochs of the world into the earlier centuries and those
  18570. following them? "Does the fifth, or the tenth century belong to the
  18571. earlier centuries?" it would be asked. In the same way I ask: Does the
  18572. conception of extension belong to metaphysics? You answer, "Yes." Well,
  18573. that of body too? "Yes." And that of a fluid body? You stop, you are
  18574. unprepared to admit this; for if you do, everything will belong
  18575. to metaphysics. From this it is evident that the mere degree of
  18576. subordination--of the particular to the general--cannot determine the
  18577. limits of a science; and that, in the present case, we must expect to
  18578. find a difference in the conceptions of metaphysics both in kind and in
  18579. origin. The fundamental idea of metaphysics was obscured on another
  18580. side by the fact that this kind of a priori cognition showed a certain
  18581. similarity in character with the science of mathematics. Both have the
  18582. property in common of possessing an a priori origin; but, in the
  18583. one, our knowledge is based upon conceptions, in the other, on the
  18584. construction of conceptions. Thus a decided dissimilarity between
  18585. philosophical and mathematical cognition comes out--a dissimilarity
  18586. which was always felt, but which could not be made distinct for want
  18587. of an insight into the criteria of the difference. And thus it happened
  18588. that, as philosophers themselves failed in the proper development of the
  18589. idea of their science, the elaboration of the science could not
  18590. proceed with a definite aim, or under trustworthy guidance. Thus, too,
  18591. philosophers, ignorant of the path they ought to pursue and always
  18592. disputing with each other regarding the discoveries which each asserted
  18593. he had made, brought their science into disrepute with the rest of the
  18594. world, and finally, even among themselves.
  18595. All pure a priori cognition forms, therefore, in view of the peculiar
  18596. faculty which originates it, a peculiar and distinct unity; and
  18597. metaphysic is the term applied to the philosophy which attempts to
  18598. represent that cognition in this systematic unity. The speculative part
  18599. of metaphysic, which has especially appropriated this appellation--that
  18600. which we have called the metaphysic of nature--and which considers
  18601. everything, as it is (not as it ought to be), by means of a priori
  18602. conceptions, is divided in the following manner.
  18603. Metaphysic, in the more limited acceptation of the term, consists of two
  18604. parts--transcendental philosophy and the physiology of pure reason.
  18605. The former presents the system of all the conceptions and principles
  18606. belonging to the understanding and the reason, and which relate to
  18607. objects in general, but not to any particular given objects (Ontologia);
  18608. the latter has nature for its subject-matter, that is, the sum of given
  18609. objects--whether given to the senses, or, if we will, to some other kind
  18610. of intuition--and is accordingly physiology, although only rationalis.
  18611. But the use of the faculty of reason in this rational mode of regarding
  18612. nature is either physical or hyperphysical, or, more properly speaking,
  18613. immanent or transcendent. The former relates to nature, in so far as our
  18614. knowledge regarding it may be applied in experience (in concreto); the
  18615. latter to that connection of the objects of experience, which transcends
  18616. all experience. Transcendent physiology has, again, an internal and
  18617. an external connection with its object, both, however, transcending
  18618. possible experience; the former is the physiology of nature as a whole,
  18619. or transcendental cognition of the world, the latter of the connection
  18620. of the whole of nature with a being above nature, or transcendental
  18621. cognition of God.
  18622. Immanent physiology, on the contrary, considers nature as the sum of
  18623. all sensuous objects, consequently, as it is presented to us--but still
  18624. according to a priori conditions, for it is under these alone that
  18625. nature can be presented to our minds at all. The objects of immanent
  18626. physiology are of two kinds: 1. Those of the external senses, or
  18627. corporeal nature; 2. The object of the internal sense, the soul, or, in
  18628. accordance with our fundamental conceptions of it, thinking nature.
  18629. The metaphysics of corporeal nature is called physics; but, as it must
  18630. contain only the principles of an a priori cognition of nature, we must
  18631. term it rational physics. The metaphysics of thinking nature is called
  18632. psychology, and for the same reason is to be regarded as merely the
  18633. rational cognition of the soul.
  18634. Thus the whole system of metaphysics consists of four principal parts:
  18635. 1. Ontology; 2. Rational Physiology; 3. Rational cosmology; and 4.
  18636. Rational theology. The second part--that of the rational doctrine of
  18637. nature--may be subdivided into two, physica rationalis* and psychologia
  18638. rationalis.
  18639. [*Footnote: It must not be supposed that I mean by this appellation what
  18640. is generally called physica general is, and which is rather mathematics
  18641. than a philosophy of nature. For the metaphysic of nature is completely
  18642. different from mathematics, nor is it so rich in results, although it
  18643. is of great importance as a critical test of the application of pure
  18644. understanding--cognition to nature. For want of its guidance, even
  18645. mathematicians, adopting certain common notions--which are, in fact,
  18646. metaphysical--have unconsciously crowded their theories of nature with
  18647. hypotheses, the fallacy of which becomes evident upon the application
  18648. of the principles of this metaphysic, without detriment, however, to the
  18649. employment of mathematics in this sphere of cognition.]
  18650. The fundamental idea of a philosophy of pure reason of necessity
  18651. dictates this division; it is, therefore, architectonical--in accordance
  18652. with the highest aims of reason, and not merely technical, or according
  18653. to certain accidentally-observed similarities existing between the
  18654. different parts of the whole science. For this reason, also, is the
  18655. division immutable and of legislative authority. But the reader may
  18656. observe in it a few points to which he ought to demur, and which may
  18657. weaken his conviction of its truth and legitimacy.
  18658. In the first place, how can I desire an a priori cognition or metaphysic
  18659. of objects, in so far as they are given a posteriori? and how is
  18660. it possible to cognize the nature of things according to a priori
  18661. principles, and to attain to a rational physiology? The answer is this.
  18662. We take from experience nothing more than is requisite to present us
  18663. with an object (in general) of the external or of the internal sense;
  18664. in the former case, by the mere conception of matter (impenetrable and
  18665. inanimate extension), in the latter, by the conception of a thinking
  18666. being--given in the internal empirical representation, I think. As to
  18667. the rest, we must not employ in our metaphysic of these objects any
  18668. empirical principles (which add to the content of our conceptions by
  18669. means of experience), for the purpose of forming by their help any
  18670. judgements respecting these objects.
  18671. Secondly, what place shall we assign to empirical psychology, which has
  18672. always been considered a part of metaphysics, and from which in our time
  18673. such important philosophical results have been expected, after the hope
  18674. of constructing an a priori system of knowledge had been abandoned? I
  18675. answer: It must be placed by the side of empirical physics or physics
  18676. proper; that is, must be regarded as forming a part of applied
  18677. philosophy, the a priori principles of which are contained in pure
  18678. philosophy, which is therefore connected, although it must not be
  18679. confounded, with psychology. Empirical psychology must therefore be
  18680. banished from the sphere of metaphysics, and is indeed excluded by
  18681. the very idea of that science. In conformity, however, with scholastic
  18682. usage, we must permit it to occupy a place in metaphysics--but only
  18683. as an appendix to it. We adopt this course from motives of economy;
  18684. as psychology is not as yet full enough to occupy our attention as
  18685. an independent study, while it is, at the same time, of too great
  18686. importance to be entirely excluded or placed where it has still less
  18687. affinity than it has with the subject of metaphysics. It is a stranger
  18688. who has been long a guest; and we make it welcome to stay, until it can
  18689. take up a more suitable abode in a complete system of anthropology--the
  18690. pendant to empirical physics.
  18691. The above is the general idea of metaphysics, which, as more was
  18692. expected from it than could be looked for with justice, and as these
  18693. pleasant expectations were unfortunately never realized, fell into
  18694. general disrepute. Our Critique must have fully convinced the reader
  18695. that, although metaphysics cannot form the foundation of religion,
  18696. it must always be one of its most important bulwarks, and that human
  18697. reason, which naturally pursues a dialectical course, cannot do without
  18698. this science, which checks its tendencies towards dialectic and, by
  18699. elevating reason to a scientific and clear self-knowledge, prevents the
  18700. ravages which a lawless speculative reason would infallibly commit in
  18701. the sphere of morals as well as in that of religion. We may be sure,
  18702. therefore, whatever contempt may be thrown upon metaphysics by those who
  18703. judge a science not by its own nature, but according to the accidental
  18704. effects it may have produced, that it can never be completely abandoned,
  18705. that we must always return to it as to a beloved one who has been for a
  18706. time estranged, because the questions with which it is engaged relate
  18707. to the highest aims of humanity, and reason must always labour either
  18708. to attain to settled views in regard to these, or to destroy those which
  18709. others have already established.
  18710. Metaphysic, therefore--that of nature, as well as that of ethics, but in
  18711. an especial manner the criticism which forms the propaedeutic to all the
  18712. operations of reason--forms properly that department of knowledge which
  18713. may be termed, in the truest sense of the word, philosophy. The path
  18714. which it pursues is that of science, which, when it has once been
  18715. discovered, is never lost, and never misleads. Mathematics, natural
  18716. science, the common experience of men, have a high value as means, for
  18717. the most part, to accidental ends--but at last also, to those which are
  18718. necessary and essential to the existence of humanity. But to guide them
  18719. to this high goal, they require the aid of rational cognition on the
  18720. basis of pure conceptions, which, be it termed as it may, is properly
  18721. nothing but metaphysics.
  18722. For the same reason, metaphysics forms likewise the completion of the
  18723. culture of human reason. In this respect, it is indispensable, setting
  18724. aside altogether the influence which it exerts as a science. For its
  18725. subject-matter is the elements and highest maxims of reason, which form
  18726. the basis of the possibility of some sciences and of the use of all.
  18727. That, as a purely speculative science, it is more useful in preventing
  18728. error than in the extension of knowledge, does not detract from its
  18729. value; on the contrary, the supreme office of censor which it occupies
  18730. assures to it the highest authority and importance. This office it
  18731. administers for the purpose of securing order, harmony, and well-being
  18732. to science, and of directing its noble and fruitful labours to the
  18733. highest possible aim--the happiness of all mankind.
  18734. CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason.
  18735. This title is placed here merely for the purpose of designating a
  18736. division of the system of pure reason of which I do not intend to treat
  18737. at present. I shall content myself with casting a cursory glance, from
  18738. a purely transcendental point of view--that of the nature of pure
  18739. reason--on the labours of philosophers up to the present time. They have
  18740. aimed at erecting an edifice of philosophy; but to my eye this edifice
  18741. appears to be in a very ruinous condition.
  18742. It is very remarkable, although naturally it could not have been
  18743. otherwise, that, in the infancy of philosophy, the study of the nature
  18744. of God and the constitution of a future world formed the commencement,
  18745. rather than the conclusion, as we should have it, of the speculative
  18746. efforts of the human mind. However rude the religious conceptions
  18747. generated by the remains of the old manners and customs of a less
  18748. cultivated time, the intelligent classes were not thereby prevented from
  18749. devoting themselves to free inquiry into the existence and nature of
  18750. God; and they easily saw that there could be no surer way of pleasing
  18751. the invisible ruler of the world, and of attaining to happiness in
  18752. another world at least, than a good and honest course of life in this.
  18753. Thus theology and morals formed the two chief motives, or rather the
  18754. points of attraction in all abstract inquiries. But it was the former
  18755. that especially occupied the attention of speculative reason, and which
  18756. afterwards became so celebrated under the name of metaphysics.
  18757. I shall not at present indicate the periods of time at which the
  18758. greatest changes in metaphysics took place, but shall merely give a
  18759. hasty sketch of the different ideas which occasioned the most important
  18760. revolutions in this sphere of thought. There are three different ends in
  18761. relation to which these revolutions have taken place.
  18762. 1. In relation to the object of the cognition of reason, philosophers
  18763. may be divided into sensualists and intellectualists. Epicurus may be
  18764. regarded as the head of the former, Plato of the latter. The distinction
  18765. here signalized, subtle as it is, dates from the earliest times, and was
  18766. long maintained. The former asserted that reality resides in sensuous
  18767. objects alone, and that everything else is merely imaginary; the latter,
  18768. that the senses are the parents of illusion and that truth is to
  18769. be found in the understanding alone. The former did not deny to the
  18770. conceptions of the understanding a certain kind of reality; but with
  18771. them it was merely logical, with the others it was mystical. The former
  18772. admitted intellectual conceptions, but declared that sensuous objects
  18773. alone possessed real existence. The latter maintained that all real
  18774. objects were intelligible, and believed that the pure understanding
  18775. possessed a faculty of intuition apart from sense, which, in their
  18776. opinion, served only to confuse the ideas of the understanding.
  18777. 2. In relation to the origin of the pure cognitions of reason, we find
  18778. one school maintaining that they are derived entirely from experience,
  18779. and another that they have their origin in reason alone. Aristotle may
  18780. be regarded as the bead of the empiricists, and Plato of the noologists.
  18781. Locke, the follower of Aristotle in modern times, and Leibnitz of Plato
  18782. (although he cannot be said to have imitated him in his mysticism),
  18783. have not been able to bring this question to a settled conclusion.
  18784. The procedure of Epicurus in his sensual system, in which he always
  18785. restricted his conclusions to the sphere of experience, was much more
  18786. consequent than that of Aristotle and Locke. The latter especially,
  18787. after having derived all the conceptions and principles of the mind
  18788. from experience, goes so far, in the employment of these conceptions and
  18789. principles, as to maintain that we can prove the existence of God and
  18790. the existence of God and the immortality of them objects lying beyond
  18791. the soul--both of them of possible experience--with the same force of
  18792. demonstration as any mathematical proposition.
  18793. 3. In relation to method. Method is procedure according to principles.
  18794. We may divide the methods at present employed in the field of inquiry
  18795. into the naturalistic and the scientific. The naturalist of pure reason
  18796. lays it down as his principle that common reason, without the aid of
  18797. science--which he calls sound reason, or common sense--can give a more
  18798. satisfactory answer to the most important questions of metaphysics than
  18799. speculation is able to do. He must maintain, therefore, that we can
  18800. determine the content and circumference of the moon more certainly
  18801. by the naked eye, than by the aid of mathematical reasoning. But this
  18802. system is mere misology reduced to principles; and, what is the most
  18803. absurd thing in this doctrine, the neglect of all scientific means is
  18804. paraded as a peculiar method of extending our cognition. As regards
  18805. those who are naturalists because they know no better, they are
  18806. certainly not to be blamed. They follow common sense, without parading
  18807. their ignorance as a method which is to teach us the wonderful secret,
  18808. how we are to find the truth which lies at the bottom of the well of
  18809. Democritus.
  18810. Quod sapio satis est mihi, non ego curo Esse quod
  18811. Arcesilas aerumnosique Solones. PERSIUS
  18812. --Satirae, iii. 78-79.
  18813. is their motto, under which they may lead a pleasant and praiseworthy
  18814. life, without troubling themselves with science or troubling science
  18815. with them.
  18816. As regards those who wish to pursue a scientific method, they have now
  18817. the choice of following either the dogmatical or the sceptical, while
  18818. they are bound never to desert the systematic mode of procedure. When I
  18819. mention, in relation to the former, the celebrated Wolf, and as regards
  18820. the latter, David Hume, I may leave, in accordance with my present
  18821. intention, all others unnamed. The critical path alone is still open.
  18822. If my reader has been kind and patient enough to accompany me on this
  18823. hitherto untravelled route, he can now judge whether, if he and others
  18824. will contribute their exertions towards making this narrow footpath
  18825. a high road of thought, that which many centuries have failed to
  18826. accomplish may not be executed before the close of the present--namely,
  18827. to bring Reason to perfect contentment in regard to that which has
  18828. always, but without permanent results, occupied her powers and engaged
  18829. her ardent desire for knowledge.